This article was downloaded by: [University of York] On: 2 September 2010 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 917198451] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 3741 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Applied Economics Letters Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713684190 Do people plan ahead? John D. Bonea; John D. Hey; John R. Sucklinga a Department of Economics, University of York, Heslington, York YO10 5DD, UK. To cite this Article Bone, John D. , Hey, John D. and Suckling, John R.(2003) 'Do people plan ahead?', Applied Economics Letters, 10: 5, 277 — 280 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/1350485032000056882 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350485032000056882 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. Applied Economics Letters, 2003, 10, 277–280 Do people plan ahead? J O H N D . B O N E { , J O H N D . HE Y *{ { and J O H N R . S U C K L I N G { { Department of Economics, University of York, Heslington, York YO10 5DD, UK and { University of Bari Downloaded By: [University of York] At: 14:14 2 September 2010 A crucial basic assumption of economic theories of dynamic behaviour is that people plan ahead. This paper reports on an extremely simple experimental test of this fundamental principle. Indeed the experiment is so simple and so straightforward that it is difficult to believe that anyone would not plan ahead. However subjects are found who do not. What are they doing? I. INTRODUCTION The three co-authors of this paper were divided as to whether this experiment was worth running. It was thought that the set-up was so simple that no subjects would be found whose behaviour violated a key economic principle – that people plan ahead. However, it was agreed that if such subjects were found then it would be interesting. Moreover it is wanted to run a particularly simple experiment – as a ‘special promotion’ to attract subjects to our Register. The basic idea of the experiment was one on which we have been working for some time – to set up an experiment in which a first move by a subject reveals – where pertinent – what they are planning to do in the future. One of us (Hey, 2001) has shown that such an experiment is impossible in general unless some assumptions are made. In this experiment, the only assumption made is that subjects’ preferences respect dominance. As will be seen, the weakness of this assumption means that the predictions are similarly weak. I I . T H E E X P E R IM E N T A L D E S I G N The experiment is extremely simple – an outline of the instructions can be found in the Appendix to this paper. These instructions were publicly available (in this format, via the web, and hence in colour) to subjects in advance of the experiment, except that the exact payoffs were not disclosed in advance. Each subject undertook the experiment individually, in our laboratory office, in the presence of two experimenters. The subject made decisions by ticking boxes on an individual form, and realizing the chance events by drawing a ball from a bag. On average it took a little over two minutes for each subject to complete the experiment. There are two Stages – Stage 1 and Stage 2. In Stage 1 subjects are presented with a bag which contains four red balls and one green ball. They have two options from which to choose, (1) and (2), after which a ball is drawn at random from the bag. The choice must be made before the ball is drawn, but the outcome depends on the colour of the ball that is drawn. If the ball drawn is green then the implications are: (1) to enter Stage 2; (2) to take £4.50 without entering Stage 2; if the ball drawn is red then the subject is dismissed from the experiment without any payment. After the subject has chosen (1) or (2) a ball is drawn and the subject either enters Stage 2 (if the ball drawn is green and if he or she has chosen (1)), or gets paid £4.50 and does not enter Stage 2 (if the ball drawn is green and if he or she has chosen (2)), or gets dismissed from the experiment (if the ball drawn is red). If Stage 2 is reached then the subject is immediately presented with another bag which contains one red ball and one green ball. The subject again has two options from which to choose: (1) to draw a ball at random from the bag, being paid £10 if the ball drawn is green (and nothing otherwise); (2) to be paid £4 without drawing from the bag. It may be noted that the payoffs and probabilities used in this experiment are motivated by considerations similar to those employed when experimenters wish to design an * Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected] Applied Economics Letters ISSN 1350–4851 print/ISSN 1466–4291 online # 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals DOI: 10.1080/1350485032000056882 277 Downloaded By: [University of York] At: 14:14 2 September 2010 278 experiment in which common ratio effects may be observed. As viewed from Stage 2, the two options available in Stage 2 are (A) £4 for sure and (B) a 50–50 gamble between £0 and £10, whereas as viewed from Stage 1 the two options available in Stage 2 are (C) a gamble which yields £4 with probability 0.2 and £0 with probability 0.8 and (D) a gamble which yields £10 with probability 0.1 and £0 with probability 0.9. Note that if a subject obeys the axioms of Expected Utility theory then he or she would prefer (A) to (B) if and only if he or she prefers (C) to (D) – so if he or she planned to go for Stage 2 and then go for the risky choice (the 50–50 gamble on £0 and £10) then he or she would not change his or her mind if he or she managed to pass to Stage 2. However, if the individual does not obey the axioms of Expected Utility theory, then it could be the case that he or she preferred A to B and yet preferred D to C, or that he or she preferred B to A and yet preferred C to D. The former is the interesting case from the point of view of this experiment – the individual might choose to enter Stage 2 planning to go for the risky choice (the 50–50 gamble on £0 and £10) – because he or she prefers D to C – yet change his or her mind upon entering Stage 2 – because he or she prefers A to B. But all this is beside the point if the individual plans ahead – because he or she would be able to anticipate this behaviour – and, in anticipating it, realize that he or she would end up, if lucky, with £4 at the end of the day rather than the £4.50 gained from not entering Stage 2. So the design of the experiment is such that we will capture non-EU people only if they do not plan ahead. For non-EU people who do plan ahead we can argue in the following way. Being non-EU it is possible that they are dynamically inconsistent in that they plan to do one thing but change their minds – as illustrated above. If such nonEU people want to be dynamically consistent, then they have two choices – they can either act in a sophisticated manner (to use the terminology of Machina, 1989) or can act in a resolute manner (to use the terminology of McClennen, 1990). Let us start with the non-EU person discussed above – one who prefers A to B yet prefers D to C. If this person is sophisticated in Machina’s sense then he or she anticipates that he or she will choose A if she succeeds in entering Stage 2. This would give the individual £4 on entering Stage 2. However the individual can work out that not opting to enter Stage 2 gives him or her £4.50 under the same circumstances – which is obviously preferable. This individual chooses not to enter Stage 2. No inconsistency will be observed. If the individual has the opposite non-EU preferences – prefers B to A yet prefers C to D – this individual would anticipate that if he or she opted for Stage 2 and were successful he or she would go for the 50–50 gamble in Stage 2 – therefore at Stage 1 the individual has the choice between C and D. He or she prefers C to D and would therefore not opt for Stage 2 in Stage 1. No inconsistency will be observed. J. D. Bone et al. If, instead, the individual acts in a resolute manner in McClennen’s sense then he or she chooses the best strategy as viewed from the beginning of the experiment – and then resolutely implements it. The possible strategies are: (a) in Stage 1 opt for Stage 2 and, if successful, go for the gamble; (b) in Stage 1 opt for Stage 2 and, if successful, go for the £4 for sure; (c) in Stage 1 opt for the £4.50 for sure. It can be seen that (a) is a gamble between £0 and £10 with respective probabilities 0.9 and 0.1; that (b) is a gamble between £0 and £4 with respective probabilities 0.2 and 0.8 and that (c) is a gamble between £0 and £4.50 with respective probabilities 0.2 and 0.8. What is crucial is that strategy (c) (first-degree) dominates strategy (b) – which implies that strategy (b) will never be chosen by our non-EU individual. He or she might opt to enter Stage 2 but will then resolutely go for the gamble, or he or she might opt to go for the certainty in Stage 1. Never would this resolute non-EU individual opt to enter Stage 2 and then go for the £4 certainty. Therefore the predictions of the experiment are simple: if the subject chooses option (1) at Stage 1 then he or she must choose option (1) at Stage 2. Note that we only get a prediction if the subject chooses (1) at Stage 1 – for if he or she chooses (2) at Stage 1 then there are no further decisions to take. Note further that a test of this prediction is only obtained if the subject chooses (1) at Stage 1 and then if a green ball is drawn – for if a red ball is drawn in Stage 1 then there are no further decisions to take. Moreover it is noted that this prediction requires only the assumption that the subject’s preferences respect dominance – for the choice of (1) in Stage 1 followed by (2) in Stage (2) is dominated by the choice of (1) in Stage 1 followed by (1) in Stage (2). To put it in simpler terms – opting for £4 in Stage 2 (rather than go for the 50–50 gamble over £0 and £10) is dominated by opting for £4.50 if the ball drawn in Stage 2 is green. £4.50 dominates £4. Why settle for £4 in the event that the ball drawn in Stage 1 is green when you can have £4.50? I I I . D I F F E R E N T T R EA T M E N T S The above describes the basic story. In practice two treatments were run – but with the same basic structure. Treatment 1 is as described above; Treatment 2 has the £4.50 at Stage 1 replaced by £5 and the £4 at Stage 2 replaced by £4.50. The prediction in both treatments is the same: if the subject chooses option (1) at Stage 1 then he or she must choose option (1) at Stage 2. And the argument is the same: in Treatment 1, why settle for £4.00 in the event that the ball drawn in Stage 1 is green when you can have £4.50?; in Treatment 2, why settle for £4.50 in the event that the ball drawn in Stage 1 is green when you can have £5.00? 279 Do people plan ahead? Treatment 1 9 10 40 16 30 3 13 1 6 £10 3 £0 £4 £0 £4.50 £0 Treatment 2 9 Downloaded By: [University of York] At: 14:14 2 September 2010 11 65 52 54 12 40 2 3 £10 6 £0 £4.50 £0 £5 V. DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSION £0 Fig. 1. Was different behaviour expected in the two treatments? Some of us said ‘no’ – the predictions are the same. Some of us said ‘perhaps’ – in Treatment 2 one is more likely to see subjects having ‘cold feet’ having reached Stage 2 than in Treatment 1 (because £4.50 is more attractive relative to the 50–50 gamble between £0 and £10 than is £4.00). IV. THE RESULTS A total of 173 subjects took part in the experiment – 56 on Treatment 1 and 117 on Treatment 2. The results are shown in Fig. 1 – Treatment 1 at the top and Treatment 2 at the bottom – in which a square box denotes a choice node and a round box a chance node. The numbers on the various branches show the number of subjects following that branch – either through choice or by chance. The interesting numbers are those following the second choice node: it will be seen that in Treatment 1 of the 10 subjects opting to enter Stage 2 and succeeding in so doing, nine of them chose option (1) in Stage 2 while one chose option (2); in Treatment 2 of the 11 subjects opting to enter Stage 2 and succeeding in so doing, nine of them chose option (1) in Stage 2 while two chose option (2). So in Treatment 1 there is one subject (out of 10) violating the prediction and in Treatment 2 there are two subjects (out of 11) violating 1 the prediction – a total of three subjects out of 21 violating the prediction. Obviously these numbers significantly reject the null hypothesis of the prediction at any level of significance – but this is hardly interesting. It is also the case that the hypothesis that subjects choose between (1) and (2) in Stage 2 by picking at random is rejected at most conventional significance levels, but again this is not particularly interesting. What is interesting is that these three subjects are there at all. What are they doing? It could be argued that they have developed ‘cold feet’: having reached Stage 2 they might think that they have been lucky once and are unlikely to be lucky again; they might feel that they have pushed their luck too far. But why did they not anticipate this? They have no new information than they could have realized they would have if they had thought ahead. But perhaps the answer is simple – that they did not plan ahead? There is an alternative story – that these three subjects did not plan ahead but they did think ahead. Choosing to enter Stage 2 opens up the possibility of choosing either to go for the 50–50 gamble or to go for the £41 for sure. If the subject opts to enter Stage 2 then he or she may face the choice set {[£0, £10]; £4}, containing two elements, £4 for sure and [£0, £10] where this denotes a 50–50 gamble between £0 and £10. Choosing not to enter Stage 2 opens up the possibility of the choice set {£4.50}, containing a single element. Maybe the choice set {[£0, £10]; £4} containing two elements looks more attractive to the subjects who chose to enter Stage 2 than the choice set {£4.50} containing one element? Well that may be true but what would the economist now say? That the subject should anticipate his or her decision if he or she opted for Stage 2 and were successful. There are two possibilities: (1) that the subject would choose the gamble [£0, £10] from the choice set {[£0, £10]; £4}; (2) that the subject would choose £4 from the choice set {[£0, £10]; £4}. Consider these in order. Under (1) the subject eliminates the non-chosen option from the choice set at Stage 2 and therefore considers the choice between {[£0, £10]} and {£4.50} in deciding whether to enter Stage 2 or not. He or she may or may not decide to enter Stage 2 under these circumstances, but if he or she does then (as already argued) he or she will choose the gamble [£0,£10] in Stage 2. Under (2) the subject eliminates the non-chosen option from the choice set at Stage 2 and therefore considers the choice between {£4} and {£4.50} in deciding whether to enter Stage 2 or not. It is obvious which is best. £4 in Treatment 1; £4.50 in Treatment 2. Stated here is the argument for Treatment 1; a similar argument applies to Treatment 2. 280 Downloaded By: [University of York] At: 14:14 2 September 2010 But these arguments assume that the subjects are able to anticipate their own future behaviour. There is evidence from elsewhere (see, for example, Carbone and Hey, 2001) that this is something that some subjects are not particularly good at – either because they are unable to anticipate what they will do in the future, or because they do not know now what their preferences in the future will be. Indeed, in Carbone and Hey (2001) there seemed to be many subjects who looked ahead but did not plan ahead in the sense of anticipating their own future decisions. To such subjects, possibly choosing from the choice set {[£0, £10]; £4} might appear to be more attractive than possibly choosing from the choice set {£4.50}, not least because the former of these has two elements while the latter has just one. If this argument is correct, perhaps it should be concluded that subjects think ahead but do not plan ahead? A C K NO WL E D G E M E N T S We wish to thank the European Community under its TMR Programme Savings and Pensions (TMR Network J. D. Bone et al. Contract number ERB FMR XCT 96 0016 (‘Structural Analysis of Household Savings and Wealth Positions over the Life Cycle’)) for part financing the research reported in this paper. We would also like to thank Miguel Costas-Gomes, Tibor Neugabauer and Giorgio Coricelli for comments and help in running this experiment. REFERENCES Carbone, E. and Hey, J. D. (2001) A test of the principle of optimality, Theory and Decision, 50, 263–81. Hey, J. D. (2001) ‘Are Revealed Intentions Possible?’, under submission. Machina, M. J. (1989) Dynamic consistency and non-expected utility models of choice under uncertainty, Journal of Economic Literature, 27, 1622–68. McClennen, E. F. (1990) Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations, Cambridge University Press:, Cambridge. APPENDIX Instructions2 STAGE 1 Bag 1 contains four red balls and one green ball. If you draw the green ball then you may either: . enter Stage 2, or . take £4.50 without entering Stage 2 You will be asked to make your choice before drawing from Bag 1. If you choose ‘enter Stage 2’ and then draw the green ball from Bag 1, you will proceed to . . . STAGE 2 Bag 2 contains one red ball and one green ball. If you draw the green ball then you win £10. However, you may choose not to draw from Bag 2, but to take £4 instead. So in Stage 2 you may either: . draw from Bag 2, winning £10 if green, or . take £4 without drawing from Bag 2 You will be asked to make your choice if, and only if, you have won entry to Stage 2. 2 For Treatment 1. For Treatment 2,the £4.50 in Stage 1 is replaced by £5 and the £4 in Stage 2 is replaced by £4.50.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz