McKinnon, W., Weisse, C.S., Reynolds, C.P., Bowles, C.A., & Baum, A. (1989). Chronic stress, leukocyte subpopulations, and humoral response to latent viruses. Health Psychology. 8, 389-402. Meyer, R.J., & Haggerty, R.J. (1962). Streptococcal infections in families. Pediatrics. 29, 539549. Rabin, B.S , Cohen, 5., Ganguli, R., I.vie, D.T., & Cunnick, J.E. (1989). Bidirectional interaction between the central nervous system and immune system. CRC Critical Rei'iewb in humunologu, 9, 279-312. Stone, A.A., Bovbjerg, D.ll., Neale, J.M., Napoli, A., Valdimarsdottir, H., Cox, D., Hayden, E.G., &Gwaltney, J.M. (1993). Development of common cold symptoms foUowmg expcrmiental rhinovirus infection is related to prior stressful life events Behavioral Medicme, 8, 115-120. Stone, A.A., Cox, D.S., Valdimarsdottir, H., Jandorf, L., & Neale, J.M. (1987). Evidence that secretory igA antibody is a.ssocuited with daily mood, journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 988-993. Stone, A.A., Neale, |.M., Cox, D.S., Napoli, A., Valdimarsdottir, H., & Kennedy-Moore, F (1994). Daily events are associated with ii secre- Possible Individuals in Language and Cognition Paul Bloom^ Department of Psychology, University of Arizona, Tucson, Arizona One approach to the psychology of proper names and count nouns explores the role these expressions play in our mental life. Proper names such as fido correspond to entities we think of as individuals—entities that can be categorized, counted, and tracked over space and time. Count nouns such as dog correspond to kinds of individuals. It makes sense to talk of 2 dogs or 10 dogs, or to say that a certain dog is the same one that I saw yesterday, or to ask what happened to Fido. Not all parts of speech refer to individuals; adjectives like hig and mass nouns like water do not correspond to entities that are countable or trackable in the same sense. This observation raises the question of what sorts of entities are naturally thought of as individuals. We count, name, and track dogs—they are psychologically natural individuals. As a result, words that refer to this kind {dog) and words that refer to particular members of this kind {Fido) are easily learned by children. But not every logically possible individual is acceptable from the standpoint of human psychology. For in- stance, construing the spatially discontinuous entity composed of my dog and his favorite bone as a single individual is cognitively unnatural. We could not easily learn a proper name {Fidobone, say) for this entity, nor can we easily track it over space and time. Why is it that Fido is a psychologically possible individual, but Fidobone is not? One answer is that Fido is a discrete physical object—and discrete physical objects are natural individuals. People count objects, track them, categorize them as belonging to different kinds, and learn names for these kinds. Psychologists typically concern themselves with objects when constructing theories of linguistic and noniinguistic capacities, and many theories of how we learn and understand words are restricted to the learning and understanding of object names, implicitly adopting the view that, for humans, individuals just are discrete whole objects. This view cannot be right, however. Children and adults do learn words such as chapter, party, and joke; we can count chapters, par- Published hy Cambridge University i'ress tory immune response Eo an oral antigen in men. Health Psychology, 13. 440-446. Recommended Reading Cohen, S., & Herbert, T.B. (1996). Psychological factors and physical disease from the perspective of human psychoneuroimmunology. Annual Rn'iavof P<ychologif. 47, 113-142. Gkiser, R., & Kiecok-Claser, J (Eds.). (1994). Handbook ol human stress and immunity. New York: Academic Press. ties, and jokes; we can track them, categorize them, and so on. But to say that Jane wrote two chapters does not mean that she created two objects. If she goes to two parties on Saturday night, and tells two jokes at each party, what individuates the parties and jokes rests on subtle intentional factors, obvious enough intuitively, but difficult to specify precisely. What properties, if any, do these concepts share that make them all acceptable candidates for enumeration and naming? What makes these nonobject entities psychologically natural individuals? This issue is not special to word learning. All theories of counting, categorization, and tracking must posit a domain over which these operations work, that is, a domain of individuals that get counted, categorized, and tracked. This domain cannot be limited to objects; many animals, including people, pigeons, and rats, are capable of quite complex computations over distinct sounds, events, and actions (see Wynn, 1992). A similar issue arises in social cognition. When we attribute mental states such as beliefs and goals, the targets of these attributions are not necessarily physical objects. We talk about a nation hesitating to take action, a hockey team seeking another chance for victory, and the Internal Revenue Service becoming concerned about one's homeoffice deduction. Such attributions are not merely metaphorical. In a recent study, Csaba Veres and I extended a classic experiment by Heider and Simmel (1944) which found that people exposed to movies of simple geometrical shapes moving in a structured pattern will describe these movies in terms of purposeful and intentional action. We redid this study with both individual shapes and groups of shapes as stimuli, and found that moving groups are naturally viewed as intentional entities—as "characters," with beliefs and desires—to the same extent as moving shapes are (Bloom & Veres, 1996). Within social cognition as well, then, the question arises: What are psychologically natural individuals? OBJECTS AND OTHER INDIVIDUAtS Some insight might emerge from the study of development. Infants are predisposed to parse the physical world into bounded units that move on continuous paths, that is, into discrete physical objects (Spelke, 1994). Most of the count nouns that 2-year-olds know refer to objects, much more so than for older children or adults. When exposed to new words, children tend to treat them as object names, even if this interpretation is inconsistent with the syntax, such as when a word is presented as an adjective or a mass noun (Markman, 1990). Moreover, when asked to count different arrays, preschoolers are strongly biased to count the distinct objects, even if explicitly asked to do otherwise. For instance, when shown a display of five forks, one broken into two separate pieces, and asked "Can you count the forks?" preschoolers typically say there are six (Shipley & Shepperson, 1990). Such results could be taken as suggesting that children are conceptually enfeebled, and that objects are the only individuals they can think about, count, track, and name. But this is plainly not the case. Even young infants can enumerate actions (Wynn, 1996) and sounds (Starkey, Spelke, & Gelman, 1990). Many of children's first words refer to nonobject individuals, such as nap, family, and story, and these words arc used in correct semantic and grammatical contexts (Nelson, Hampson, & Shaw, 1993). In a few domains, researchers have attempted to teach names for nonobject individuals to young children. One set of studies focused on words like church, camp, and school, which lead interesting double lives. A word like church can refer to a physical entity, as in "There is a church on the corner," but it can also be a proper name of a specific cultural institution, as when one says, "John goes to church regularly." Preschoolers understand the multiple usage of such words, and can learn new words that have a similar abstract usage even on the basis of only a few exposures (Soja, 1994). A different domain is that of collective nouns, such as army and family, wbich refer to groups of discrete physical objects. Some such nouns are acquired early, and preschoolers can learn names for novel collections with the aid of linguistic support. For instance, if an adult points to a group of objects and describes it with the syntax associated with a single individual (e.g., "This is a fendle"), preschoolers will often construe the new word as a collective noun, not as an object name (Bloom & Kelemen, 1995). These findings raise a puzzle: If children can understand abstract individuals, why are they so drawn to objects in their word learning and counting? Why are objects so salient? One explanation Cupyright i-^ 1996 American PsychologiiTji Society appeals to the functional importance of objects. Humans and other animals construe the world in terms of objects that endure over time and move cohesively through space because animals that do so are better able to track prey, avoid predators, find shelter, and so on. Enduring objects are extremely relevant causal entities from an ecological standpoint, and this fact could have led to the evolution of a hard-wired object module that operates in essentially the same fashion for children and adults, and most likely exists within other primates as well. But objects are not the only individuals worth thinking about. Just as making sense of the physical world motivated the evolutionary origins of object cognition, the need to predict and understand the social world motivates thinking about individuals like chapters, parlies, and jokes. Following Carey (1988), we can view such individuals as emerging through a process of theory construction. The chiid who posits such individuals in the course of making sense of the social world does so for the same reason, and perhaps in the same way, as the scientist who posits individuals like electrons and genes as part of the study of the physical world. It is conceivable that a single mechanism parses the world into both objects and nonobject individuals, but certain considerations suggest otherwise. In particular, the salience of whole objects for children might result from the fact that children's object module is fully operational, whereas their capacity for individuation of at least some abstract entities is less so, because of lack of knowledge or of experience. A similar dissociation is found in adult novices. A novice watching a soccer game will track only the moving objects, the players and the bail, whereas a soccer aficionado watching a game can track the movement of the teams— spatially discontinuous entities— as well as of the objects. The parsing of the world into objects is involuntary and automatic; the soccer expert can decide whether to view the game as the interplay of two distinct teams, but viewing it in terms of moving objects is not a matter of choice. Another distinction between object individuation and nonobject individuation is found in studies of apparent motion. When successive stimuli are presented at very brief intervals, people perceive only the movement of spatially distinct entities. For instance, if a row of three vertical lines is shown alternately in two positions, so that the positions of the two rightmost lines in one exposure coincide with the positions of the two leftmost lines in the alternating exposure, people see a single line jumping back and forth over two stationary lines. At slower intervals, however, a sensitivity to nonobject individuals (defined through Cestalt principles such as proximity) emerges. In this example, the subjects construe the group of three lines as an individual and see the entire group as moving back and forth, even though two of the lines do not actually change position across the successive exposures (see Braddick, 1980). Finally, the cues that identify objects are distinct from those that identify other types of individuals. The perception of objects is a highly inferential process (consider the problems posed by occlusion), but nevertheless the mechanisms that typically govern the on-line perception and tracking of objects are based on a limited set of unlearned principles (see Spelke, 1994).^ In contrast, the parsing of the world into other sorts of individuals is a less encapsulated process, drawing upon cues that emerge from a range of different sources, including perception, language, and social cognition. By saying that humans possess two distinct modes of individuation, I do not mean to imply that we possess only two. For instance, there might exist dedicated systems for domains other than objects, such as a "person module" that uses cues to animacy— structural properties indicative of faces or certain patterns of movement—to parse the world into intentional beings that are not coextensive with objects (BaronCohen, 1995; Bloom & Veres, 1996). But we certainly do not have specialized modules for chimneys, or chapters, or families. How is it that these nonobject entities are treated as distinct individuals in language and cognition? SOME CUES TO One cue that could cause us to construe something other than a discrete object as an individual is the existence of perceived nonrandomness. For example, if a set of objects is moving together through space, this is seen as a nonrandon:! state of affairs, and it is natural to posit some connection between the objects in order to explain their proximity and common fate. As a result, a person might construe the set of objects as a single individual, as with a flock or pack. Similarly, certain discontinuities in contour are seen as the result of nonrandom processes, and this inference can lead to the identification of some material individuals that are not discrete objects (Hoffman & Richards, 1984; Leyton, 1992). These include fingers (created through biological processes), mountains (created through geological processes), and Published by Cambridge University Press chimneys (created through intentional processes). Intuitions of nonrandomness can also apply in the domain of actions, as when an infant's sensitivity to systematic patterns in motion can lead her to count the jumps of a continually moving puppet (Wynn, 1996). A related cue to the existence ot nonobject individuals is their participation (as agents, patients, or goals) in intentional activities. Chapters, parties, and jokes are individuals precisely because they are created and regarded by other people as singular entities. There is no independent motivation for treating them as such. Similarly, a bikini can be viewed as a single individual because it is created and used for a singular purpose, and the world is divided into distinct countries through social and historical facts, not physical ones. One basic source of information about the intentions of other people is linguistic. Our appreciation that there exist individuals such as specific countries emerges simply by hearing people refer to such entities in their speech, and inferring that some such entities must therefore exist. It is not surprising that the cues to nonobject individuals are abstract and diverse, given that they pick out entities as disparate as jokes and fingers. To make the investigation of such cues more tractable, my students and I have focused on a very specific question: Exactly what is it about the collections named by count nouns in natural language—individuals like families and flocks—that makes them natural individuals in language and cognition? Our experiments typically involve showing children and adults displays of three groups of several objects each, either actual physical objects or entities depicted on a computer screen. The displays are described using a novel word (e.g., "These are fendles"); subjects are then tested as to what they think the new word means. We are interested in the factors that lead people to construe the groups of objects as individuals and thus to interpret the new word as a collective name (Bloom & Kelemen, 1995; Bloom, Kelemen, Fountain, &L Courtney, 1995). Figure 1 shows some of the displays used in these experiments, in schematic form. When subjects are presented with a simple display of stationary objects (Fig. la), they overwhelmingly construe the word as an object name (i.e., there are 15 "fendles"). Apparently the bias to parse the scene into objects overrides the Gestalt cue of proximity. However, if the same stationary groups are the recipients of purposeful action, a very different result obtains. Adults were shown a display in which three "machines" rose up (Fig. Ibl), each surrounding one of the groups. Colored balloons popped out of each machine when it made contact with a group (Fig. Ib2), and the machines then gradually re11 rr r r r r n rn c r rr rr rr c r r r rr r -^ i't ri r 11 r i rri ir/ •''• ' ? r fi . 1 tr rr r rr r r rr rr r r Fig. 1. Schematic representation of the stimuli used in the collection studies: stationary groups of objects (a), stationary groups that are the targets of machines (bl) that react when they contact the groups (b2), moving groups of objects (c), and groups that are perceived as moving because they are resting on moving plates (d). treated from the screen, leaving the screen empty except for the original, still stationary, groups. In this condition, subjects tended to interpret "fendle" as a collective noun, referring either to each group (the target of an action) or to each group and its corresponding machine (all of the participants in an action). Thus, the object bias disappears if a group is seen as a participant in some structured interaction, even if the group remains stationary throughout. The perceived intention of the experimenter, signaled through language or in some other fashion, is also sufficient to guide people to treat collections as individuals. For instance, if each of three stationary groups is described with a singular count noun (e.g., if the experimenter says, "This is a fendle . . . this is a fendle . . . and this is a fendle," while pointing to each group in turn), adults and 5-yearolds tend to treat the word as denoting the collections, sensitive to the fact that the experimenter was referring to them as individuals. A similar effect obtains without syntactic cues. In one study, 4- and 5-year-olds watched while the experimenter carefully arranged three groups of objects and described them with a plural count noun ("These are fendles"). For some of the children, a picture frame was placed around each group as it was being created (the frame was removed before the groups were named), giving the impression that each group was an independent artistic creation. The children in this frame condition gave collective interpretations of "fendle" significantly more frequently than those not given this intentional cue, suggesting that these children inferred that the groups were thought of as individuals in the mind of the experimenter and therefore construed the groups as individuals. Finally, people may be moti- Copyright (C 1996 American Psychological S(iciL't\' vated to treat collections as individuals when the collections themselves appear to be causally potent entities. In one study, adults viewed a computer screen showing three groups, each moving as a single unit, tracing a path across the screen, avoiding the other groups, and so on (Eig. lc). These subjects construed the groups as individuals and interpreted "fendle" as a collective noun. This construal was not the result of the movement of the groups per se. In another study, other subjects were shown the same moving groups, but each group was surrounded by a circle (Fig. Id). The experimenter told the subjects, "These are fendles on plates," to make it clear that the circles were defined as plates. Placing the groups on "plates" explains the common movement of the objects within a group without appeal to any deeper shared properties of the objects. Without such a motivation to treat the groups as distinct causal entities, subjects abandoned the collective interpretation and treated "fendle" as an object name, despite the fact that the groups were moving. Future studies may reveal that intentional and causal notions are i m p o r t a n t not only for collections, as we have found, but also for nonobject individuals more generally. Such findings would support the theory of individuation I proposed earlier: Although the functional motivations for positing objects and positing other individuals are identical, the procedures responsible for their individuation differ. Object individuation results from specialized mechanisms that draw upon perceptual input. In contrast, the understanding of abstract individuals emerges from more general aspects of our mental life: intuitions about randomness and systematicity, inferences about which entities count as participants in causal interactions, and our appreciation of the beliefs and desires of other people. Acknowledgments—I am grateful to Susan Carey, Emanuel Donchin, Tim German, Mary Petersoti, Karen Wynn, and an anonymous reviewer for helpfui comments on a previous version of this article and for discussion of the ideas within. The research discussed here is supported by grants from the Sloan Foundation and the Spencer Foundation. Notes 1. Address correspondence to Paul Bloom, Department of Psychology', Universitv' of Arizona, Tucson, AZ 85721; e-manl: bkxjmCfiu.arizona.edu. 2. Not all object individuation is plausibly viewed as emerging from an innate object module, in particular, the identification of objects in a static scene draws on a person's prior experience with the objects and on sensitivity to cues such as discontinuities in color and texture. These are the same factors that apply for the individualion ol nonobject entities such as parts, suggesting that the procedures for nonobject individuation can sometimes extend to objects as well. Note, however, that although infants are sensitive to objecl properties such as spatiotemporal continuity, the ability to exploit those other types of cues is not present early in development (for discussion, seo Baillargeon & Hanko-Summers, 199U; Spelke, Breinlinger, Jacobson, & Phillips, 1993), This developmental dissociation suggests that although the two modes of individuation might sometimes apply to the same entities (objects), they are nonetheless distinct. References Baillargeon, R., & Hanko-Summers, S. (1990), Is the top ob]cct adequately supported by the bottom object? Young infants' understanding of support relations. Cognitive Dezvlopment, 5, 29-33, Baron-Cohen, 5. (1995), Mindbltndness An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Bloom, [>., & Kelemen, D. (1995], Syntactic cues in the acquisition of collective nouns. Cognition, 56, 1-30, Bloom, P., Kelemen, 13,, Fountain, A., & Courtney, t,. (1995). The acquisition of colleclive nouns. In D. MacLaughlin & S. McEwen (Hds,), Proceedings of the 19th Boston lluivcrsity Conference oil Language Development. Boston; Cascadilla Press Bloom, P,, & Veres, C (1996), The perceived mtentionaUty of groups Manuscript submitted lor publication, Braddick, O.j, (1980) Low-level and highlevel processes in apparent motion. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 290, 137-151, Carey, S. (1988), Conceptual differences between children and adults, .\4iiul aud Language, ^, 167-181. Heider, F,, & Simmel, M, (1944), An experimental study of apparent behavior, American journal of Psychology, 57, 243-239 Hoffman, ' D , D , , & Richards, W.A, (1984). Parts of recognition. Cognition, IS, 63-96. Leyton, M, (1992), Symmetry, causality, mind. Cambridge, MA; MIT Press, Markman, E.M. (1990) Constraints children Integrating Information Across Saccadic Eye Movements David E. Irwin^ Department of Psychology, University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign, Champaign, Illinois We make rapid eye movements called saccades about three times each second in order to examine the world around us. The still periods between saccades are called fixations. The average fixation is approximately 300 ms in duration, whereas the average saccade is only 30 ms in duration. We make saccades in order to direct the fovea of the eye, which provides our clearest vision, at objects of interest in the environment. Sac- cadic eye movements create problems for perception because visual information sweeps across the back of the eyes during each saccade; as a consequence, objects in the world have different positions on the retina from one fixation to the next. Even though the visual input is continually changing in this way, we ordinarily perceive the world as a coherent whole, with objects maintaining their positions in space. There is no feeling Published by Cambridge University Press place on word meanings. Cognitive Science, 14, 5777. Nelson, K., Hampson, ], , & Shaw, L,K, (1993). Nouns in early lexicons; Evidence, explanations, and extensions, journal of Child langiia^f, 20, 61-84. Shipley, E.E,, & S h e p p e r s o n , B, (1990), Countable entities; Developmental changes, Qi^'nition, 34, 11)9-136. Soja, N.N (1994), Evidence for a distinct type of noun Cognition, 51, 2h7~-2SA Spelke, E.S. (1994). Initial knowledge; Six suggestions, Cogiitlion, 50, 431^45, Spelke, E,S , Bieinlinger, K,, Jacobsoii, K,, & Phillips, A (1993). Geslalt relations and object perception: A developmental study Perception, :2, 1483-1501, Slarkey, i'., Spelke, E.S., & Celman, K. (199(3), Numerical abstracHon by human infants. CAigndion, 36, 97-127 Wynn, K. (1992). Evidence against empiricist accounts of the origin of numerical knowledge. Mind and Ltinguagc, 7, 313-332. Wynn, K, (1996). Infants' mdividuation and enumeration ot actions, Psycholoiiical Science, 7, 16^169, Recommended Reading Bloom, P. (in press). Inlenlion, histor\, and arlifart concepts Cognition. Dennett, D 1199!). Real patterns, journal of Philosophy, S8, 27-r-l. Macnamara, |. (1994). Logic and cognition. In ), Macnamara & G E, Reyes (Eds.), The logical loiiudiittons of cognition (pp. 11- 34). Mew York: Oxford University Press, Spelke, E.S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, j . , & lacobson, K. (1992). Origins ol knowledge Psychological Rerwu\ 99, 605-632, of "starting anew" with each fixation; rather, we remember the positions and the identities of at least some of the objects in a scene, even if we close our eyes. Psychologists and vision researchers have wondered for more than a century how this quality of perception is achieved. One frequently proposed hypothesis is that visual information acquired during individual eye fixations is accumulated across saccades. This view assumes the existence of a transsaccadic memory that combines the information from successive eye fixations in such a way that a percept of a stable and continuous visual world is produced. In this article, I summarize research that my colleagues and 1 have conducted during the past 15 years to
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz