Rend. Sem. Mat. Univ. Poi. Torino Fascicolo Speciale 1987 Logic and Computer Sciences (1986) Elmar Eder THEOREM PROVING AND THE CONNECTION METHOD THE STATE OF THE ART 1. Introduction In this paper an outline is given of the present state of the art of the connection method. The connection method is a method of automated theorem proving inventèd by W. Bibel. The goals of automated theorem proving can roughly be devided into three parts: 1. 2. 3. to formalize logicai reasoning to implement it on a computer to do this efficiently. The problem of formalization of logicai reasoning has been solved by logicians at the end of the last century and early in this century. Ali the formai systems used in theorem provers today for first order predicate logie can be proved to be equivalent in expressive power to ali of these early solutions to the problem or to parts thereof. Given a formalization of logicai reasoning it is not a great problem to obtain some implementation of a sound and complete theorem prover. The problem is to be efficient in terms of the amount of time and memory required by the system as well as the user-friendlyness and the information 94 which the system provides to the user. This depends heavily upon which formalization has been chosen. The formai calculus for logicai reasoning used by most theorem provers implemented so far is the calculus of resolution. It is very easy to formulate and to implement in its simplest version since it has only two rufes resolution and factorization. Yet it is a powerful tool for theorem proving. However, its search space fans out tremendously so that a good strategy is essential for a resolution theorem prover to be efficient enough to be useful. Unfortunately, the resolution calculus does not give us much evidence for a strategy that might help to reduce the search space. Other methods used for automated theorem proving are the tableau calculus and the connection method which is closely related to it. The connection method which is presented in this paper yields a more restricted search space and offers more guidance to the search process than resolution. Moreover, it is easier for the system to provide information to the user in the connection method than in resolution. Finally, we want to mention some of the many applications of automated theorem proving. In ali of the follo wing types of software systems a logicai reasoning component is used as an essential part: Knowledge based systems (expert systems). Automated program synthesis Program verification Logic Programming, PROLOG. 2. What is an Automatic Theorem Prover? In this section we try to give a definition of what we mean by an automatic theorem prover. In order be able to speak about theorem proving in general and about automated theorem proving in special we have to assume that we are given some formai system of logie with its syntax and semantics. We assume that the following three concepts are given. A language L , i.e., as set of words built from characters of some given alphabet. We cali the elements of this language formulas. In 95 general we can assume that it is decidable whether some word is a formula or not. An example of such a language is the set of formulas of first order predicate logie, and it is essentially this set or a subset thereof which we shall consider in this paper as our language of formulas. A semantic concept of validity of a formula. We assume that a subset of the set of ali formulas is somehow defined the elements of which are called valid formulas. The exact meaning of the word "semantic" is not cruciai for our purposes, and so we shall make no attempt to give a precise definitiòn of it. In our example of first order predicate logie we take the usuai definitiòn of validity of a formula. A formai concept of a derivation of a formula. The semantic concept of validity does not, in general, suggest any obvious way for deciding whether a given formula is valid or not. The way this problem is solved in mathematical logie is to consider derivations of formulas. These derivations can be considered as (or coded into) words over some alphabet. We assume that it is decidable whether a given such word is a derivation of a given formula. If there is a derivation of a formula we say the formula is derivable. The concept of derivation is said to be sound if every derivable formula is valid and it is said to be complete if every valid formula is derivable. In order for a concept of derivation to be useful it should be at least sound. Definitiòn An automatic theorem prover is an algorithm with the following properties Its input is an arbitrary formula F If it terminates then its output is either a derivation of F (then we say the output is positive) or some string indicating that the formula is not valid (output negative) or some string indicating just that the formula could not be derived (output indefinite). The theorem prover is said to be sound if for every formula F If output to the input F is positive then F is valid. If output to the input F is negative then F is not valid. it holds 96 The theorem prover is said to be complete if for every formula holds F it If F is valid then the output to the input F is positive. Clearly, a theorem prover based on a sound derivation concept is sound. 3.. Resolution As an example of the concepts defined here we give the resolution calculus. We take, as the formulas, the formulas of first order predicate logie. In order to derive some formula have to F with the resolution method we transform the negation of F to its conjunctive normal form and build the set S of clauses corresponding to it apply the resolution (and factorization) rule to until the empty clause is obtained. S repeatedly The repeated application of the resolution and factorization rules is coded as a derivation of F . We shall not give the definition of the resolution calculus here but refer the reader to the literature. We only give a simple example from propositional logie. Let F bet the formula -i[/V(C/AK)VnW. The conjunctive normal form G of the negation of F is the formula U A (-. U V -i V) A W. Its clauses are {U} {W} By resolving the first and the second clause we obtain the resolvent {-i V }. Now no new clauses can be obtained by applying any other resolution or factorization steps. In particular, the empty clause cannot be obtained. 97 So F is not derivable in the resolution calculus. THE CONNECTION METHOD 4. The Connection Method in the Case of Formulas of Propositional Logic in Dsjunctive Normal Form We start the presentation of the connection method with formulas of propositional logie in disjunctive normal form since some of the main aspeets of the method are already present in this restricted domain and the connection method in the general case of first order predicate logie can be founded on this simple case. As opposed to resolution, the connection method is a direct proof method, Le., we do not negate the given formula and then refute its negation, but we work directly with the given formula itself. This is not a matter that affeets thè proof algorithm in principle but can be regarded just as a matter of terminology. One main difference to resolution is that we do not generate new clauses that differ in structure from the given clauses. Ali operations that are done in the connection method are defined on the set of clauses, or the structure tree, of the given formula and on structures built on top of it. The formulas that we consider in this section are disjunctions of conjunctions of literals. Each of the conjunctions of literals can be represented by the set of its conjunets, called a clause. The formula itself is represented as the set of its clauses. To depict the structure of the formula on a two-dimensional piece of paper we use a matrix representation with the clauses represented as vertical columns. As an example we take the same formula -»l/ V (U/\V) V-» W that we considered for resolution. Its matrix representation is U V representing the three clauses {-il/}, {U, V} , and {-iW). Before we explain the connection method we need a few concepts. 98 Definition A path through a matrix is a set of occurrences of literals, exactly one from each clause. In our example there are exactly two paths, namely {-il/, V,->W}. {•-» U, U, -i W} and Remarle For sake of brevity we represent occurrences of literals by the (representations of) the literals themselves here if there is no source of confusion. Definition A connection in a matrix is an unordered pair of occurrences of complementary literals, i.e., of literals X and -»X. A path is said to be complementary iff it contains a connection. In the example above the path the path {-.£/, V, -^W} is not. {-»1/, U, ~\W} is complementary but Theorem A formula of propositional logie in disjunctive normal form is valid iff every path through its matrix representation is complementary. This theorem is obvious if you consider transforming the formula to its conjuntive normal form. Then the formula is valid iff ali the conjuncts are valid. But each of the conjuncts is a disjunction of the literals of some path and vice-versa. Such a disjunction is valid iff it contains a complementary pair of literals. Definition A set of connections in a matrix is said to be spanning iff every path through the matrix contains at least one of the connections belonging to this set. 99 Then the theorem above is equivalent to saying that a formula of propositional logie in disjunctive normal form is valid iff the set of ali connections in its matrix is spanning. Now, the connection method systematically checks ali paths through a given matrix for complementarity. If it finds ali paths to be complementary then the formula is proved to be valid. If, on the other hand, it finds some path which is not complementary then the formula is proved not to be valid. Moreover, in this case, an interpretation of the propositional variables can be given explicitly that makes ali literals of that particular path false. Then this same interpretation makes the whole formula false. So a failure automatically yields a counterexample. We shall not give a formai definition of the connection calculus here but merely show the way it works with an example. Consider the formula (U/\V/\^W)\/(UAw/\^X)V^UV XV-^V Its matrix representation is U V U W ~^U X ^V The procedure starts by collecting one of the clauses as its start clause, say the clause {-•• U} . We indicate this in the figure below by interchangin the clauses so that the starting clause is the leftmost clause in the matrix. This does not mean, however, that a similar step of interchanging the clauses is done in an implementation. In the picture we draw a small arrow pointing at the first literal of the starting clause indicating that ali paths passing through this literal or any literal below it (in our example there is no literal below it) have stili to be checked for complementarity. -i U^ U V ~>w U W X -. V -,x The next step is an extension step. We try to find an occurrence of a literal that is complementary to the one pointed at by the arrow. In our example 100 we take the literal U of the second clause. We draw a connection between the two occurrences of literals, and we mark the set {-• 17-} as the current path, indicating that we are just now trying to prove the complementarity of ali extensions of the current path through whole matrix. The extensions of the current path that go through the occurence of the literal U in the second clause are complementary because of the connection {-> U, U} . Therefore V is the next literal to be checked for the complementarity of ali extensions of the current path passing through it, and it is marked with an arrow. We say that the literal V and the literal -i W below it are unsolved subgoals. / ^ "U U In another extension step we draw a connection from the literal V of the second clause to the literal ~» V of the last clause. To indicate that the last clause is the next one to be chosen we moveit to the third place in our picture (again, not in an implementation). The new current path is {-• U, V}. Ali extensions of the current. path pass through the literal -i V, contain the connection {V, -* V} and hence are complementary. So there are no more unsolved subgoals in the clause {-» V} , Le., no more extensions of the current path to be checked for complementarity, and we let the arrow point to a place below the literal — V u U V V w +~. U W X —t X The next step is a truncatton step. We retract the current path from the second clause obtaining the new current path {-i U} . Now the literals U and V of the second clause are solved subgoals and —• W is its only unsolved subgoal. - V w, U W ~^X X 101 The next step is an extension step again. The new current path is {-il/, —\W } and we choose as the clause to which we make the extension the clause {U, W, ~i X}. This clause has two literals, U and W , which are complementary to literals of the new current path. Therefore we have two new connections in this case and the clause {U, W, -i X } has only one unsolved subgoal ~» X . As before, we interchanged the clauses to right of the new current path in the figure so that the clause {U, W, ~-i X} is the leftmost among these clauses. Another extension step yields By truncation we obtàin and two more truncation steps finally result in where the current path is empty and there are no more unsolved subgoals. This completes the deduction in the connection method. Reductions and Improvements of Efficieny As we have seen, it is not necessary to check each single path through 102 the matrix for complementarity separately. Instead, the connection method checks a whole set of paths containing one particular connection in one (extension) step. This idea can be pushed further to obtain the concept of Factorization Consider a matrix containing, among other clauses, two clauses {U, V, W} and {-i U, V, X}. Assume that the clause {U, V, W} has been chosen as the start clause and that an extension step has been made to the clause {~,U,V,X}. v v^ W X Let P be the set of paths passing through both, the occurrence of U in the first clause and the occurrence of V in the second clause, and let Q be the set of paths passing through both occurrences of V in the first two clauses. Then the next thing that the simplest version of the connection method does is to check the paths of P for complementarity. In a later step the paths of Q have to be checked for complementarity. But every path of P , considered as a set of literals, is a superset of some path of Q. Therefore, if ali paths of Q are complementary then so are ali paths of P . This means we need not check the paths of P for complementarity if we make sure that we check ali paths of Q for complementarity. This is expressed in the connection method by considering the subgoal V of the second clause as solved due to a factorization link between the two occurrences of V in the first two clauses. W XK There are also reductions of the set of clauses itself well known from resolution such as the elimination of clauses containing a pure literal or the subsumption. There are further rules for reducing the search space such as avoidance 103 of circuits or elimination of redundant clauses. But we shall not go into the details of any of these reductions here. 5. Propositional Logic, Genaral Case The connection method can also be applied directly to formulas which are not in disjunctive normal form. In this case the elements of the clauses do not have to be literals but they may themselves be matrices built up from many clauses. A path through a matrix is then obtained by choosing exactly one element from each of its clauses, choosing one path through each of the chosen elements, and building the union of ali chosen paths. As an example we give the matrix representation of the formula -i K V [(((K VM) AN) V (-. N A?)) A I ] V (-1? A / ) V (-.j A L AR) and a path through this matrix. - K—-M —' " P N L R Again, a formula is valid iff every path through its matrix representation is complementary. The connection method here works in a similar way as for disjunctive normal form. 6. The Connection Method for First Order Predicate Logic in Disjunctive Normal Form In this section we assume that we are given a formula predicate logie in disjunctive normal form, 3 * ! ... xr where each of the formulas rise to clauses cx,..., cn . F of first order (Cj V ...V Cn) Ch ..., Cn is a conjunction of literals, giving 104 As an example consider the formula F0.= Pa A Vx(Px-+Pfx)^>Pfa . Let F be the normal form of F0 : F : = 3x(-^PaV(Px/\ ~*Pfx)VPfa). In the figure below we depict the matrix representation of this formula together with a spanning set of connections ^^Px ~^Pa Pfa ^Pfx^ The substitution a : = {x +- a} replacing the variable x with the Constant a unifies both ofthese connections, i.e., a (Pa) = a (Px) and a (Pfx) = a (Pfa). Thus the formula F is valid. In general, a formula of first order logie in normal form is valid if its matrix representation has a unifiable spanning set of connections. So the connection method works, for this example, the same way as for propositional logie with the one differenee that ali the connections occurring must be simultaneously unifiable. Variants of clauses As another example we take the very similar formula Fb :=Pa\ Its matrix representation is Vx(Px-+Pfx)^>Pffa. 105 The two connections indicated in the figure are not simultaneously unifiable. We say, these connections are not compatible. The remedy we have to use in this case is to take two variants of the second clause: -»Pa /S ~^Pfx1 ^-—pffa ~*Pfx2 Now there is a simultaneous unifier of ali three connections indicated in this figure, namely {xt <- a, x2 «- fa}. Herbrand's Theorem Definition An instance of a clause is the result of applying a substitution to it. An instance that does not contain any variables is called a ground instance. A compound instance of a finite set S of clauses (or of the formula corresponding to this set of clauses) is a finite set of instances of clauses of S . A variant of a clause e is a clause obtained from e by applying a renaming of variables, i.e., a substitution that is a permutation of variables, to it. A compound instance of a finite set S of clauses can be obtained by applying a substitution to a finite set of variants of clauses of S (such as the four variants of clauses in the example above). Herbrand's Theorem A formula F of first order predicate logie in disjunctive normal form is valid iff there is a compound ground instance of F that is valid. Since any compound ground instance can be regarded as a formula of propositional logie Herbrand's theorem shows us how we can use the methods of theorem proving in propositional logie in the case of first order logie. 106 Main differences between the connection method in propositional and first order logie. The main differences are the following. In propositional logie the extension is always done to one of the clauses of the given matrix always ali connections from literals of the current path to the newly chosen clause are chosen the procedure always terminates In first order logie the extension is done to a possibly new variant of a clause the connections must be compatible, and it is necessary to keep track of the most general unifier of the set of connections. In particular, in general a subset of the set of ali connections to the newly chosen clause must be chosen. Backtracking is necessary since it cannot be decided whether a particular choice of this subset will succeed. there is no bound on the number of variants of clauses that have to to be chosen in general, and the procedure does not terminate for ali input formulas. 7. First Order Predicate Logic, Non-Norma! Form The connection method for first order predicate logie in the general case is based on the Gentzen-Schùtte calculus whose axioms are ali disjunctions containing two complementary literals as disjuncts, G^ Ptx ... tnVG2W^Pt1 ... tnVG3 where Glt G2 , and G 3 may themselves be disjunctions (we consider the operation of building a disjunction as associative here). Its inference rules are GVF^H .... GVFnVH GV(FjA ... A F )VH 107 GMFVH GVvyt...ynFVH if the variables y\,--,yn donotoccurin G and H GV{x1<-tl,...,xu4-tn}F\/ 3xì...xnFVH GV 3xl ... xm FVH if the variables in tlt ..., t are not bound by quantifiers of F . The connection method essentially applies these rules backwards where the last rule corresponds to taking a new variant of a clause in the case of normal form. Of course, the terms tl} ..., t are not totally instanciated in the connection method as they are in the Gentzen-Schùtte calculus but they are only partially instanciated by unification. The axioms of the Gentzen-Schùtte calculus are reflected in the connection method by connections between two complementary literals. We shall not go beyond these vague hints here because there is an efficient way of reducing the problem of theorem proving in full first order predicate logie to theorem proving for normal form formulas, as we shall see presently. The Definitional Form In an implementation of the connection method we use an efficient reduction of any given formula F of full first order logie to a formula F' in disjunctive normal form that has the following properties F' is in normal form F' is valid iff F is valid The syntactic structure of the formula F is stili visible in F' The length of F' and the time needed to compute it grow slowly (of the order of the product of the length of F and the maximal depth of nesting of quantifiers of F) with the length of F There is a stepwise correspondence between a connection proof of F and a connection proof of F' and vice-versa. 108 The last property implies that a connection prover for normal form (for F' ) can simulate a connection proof of the formula F. We show the idea of the construction of F' (which has been known to logicians for a long time but seems to be very little known to researchers in theorem proving) with an example. Consider the formula F= 3x(Rx*> V yRy). Now, we construct, for each subformula G of F an atomic formula that has the same free variables as G , by introducing a new predicate symbol each time and taking, as its arguments, the free variables of G . This atomic formula will serve as a kind of abbreviation of G , i.e., we shall consider interpretations where this atomic formula is equivalent to G . In our example, P0 «* 3x (Rx *>VyRy) Pxx *> (RxoVyRy) P2x *> Rx P3 o VyRy P4y «• Ry These equivalences can be viewed as definitions of the predicates denoted by Po, •••, P* • Then P 0 is the assertion we want to prove. Let D 0 ,..., D4 D0 = be the following formulas PQ DJ = Vx(Ptx O *> 3XPXX (P2x^P3)) D2 = Vx (P2x <* Rx) D3= P3 D4 = Vy (P4y <* VyP4y » Ry) and let F* = D0A D, A D2A D 3 A D 4 ^P0 . Then F is valid iff F* is valid. 109 F* is already close to normal form and can be transformed to its normal form F' in the usuai way by applying the laws for the propositional connectives and by Skolemization. In particular, non exponential increaseof thelegth of the formula is encountered. Finally, a number of reductions is applied to the formula F' yielding a formula whose number of literals is at most 6n — 5 (on 4» — 3 if F does not contain any equivalence signs or exclusive or's) where n is the number of subformulas of F. The Use of Lemmata In the resolution calculus a resolvent can be considered as a lemma that has been derived from its parent clauses (or of some of its ancestors). Such a lemma can be used independently in several places for further deduction. As an example let us consider a formula stating that there is a fourth Fibonacci number. Fib (0,1) A Fib (1,1) A Vn, f, g (Fib (», f) A Fib (n + l , g ) ^ Fib (n 4- 2 , / + g)) -• Ex Fib (4, x) The meaning of Fib (n, f) here is "/ is the n-th fibonacci number". We assume that the unification can cope properly with + . The clauses are Fib (0,1) Fib (1,1) Fib(« + 2 , / + g) -.Fib ( » , / ) - F i b ( « + l,g) -> Fib (4, x) A resolution theorem prover could prove Fib (2,2) first. When it then tries to prove Fib (3,3) it can use Fib (2,2) as a lemma (or it starts by proving Fib (3,3) in the course of which it also has to prove Fib (2,2) which it can use as a lemma later). Of course, a resolution theorem prover will be abìe to make use of lemmata in a reasonable way only if it has a suitable strategy. A PROLOG system, for example, never detects a lemma. 110 The connection method in its simplest version does not have the possibility of lemma generation. We have, hpwever, already encountered one refinement of the connection method that allows limited use of lemmata, namely factorization. In an, implementation of the connection method we use explicit lemma generation to extend the limited possibilities that are offered by factorization. The lemmata generated here are of the form of universally quantified clauses similar to the resolvents occurring in resolution. They are generated and selected according to a heuristics that tries to estimate the usefulness of the lemma and gives a preference to short clauses. Splitting Another way of introducing lemmata in the proof process is the feature of splitting. As an example we consider the formula Vx (PxVPfx)-*Ey (Py/\ Pffy) with the matrix ->Px Py - Pfic Pffy The shortest compound instance that yields a connection proof is the following - ~ ^Pxt—Py, ^ - Pfiti Pffy! - Py* •~»PX2 ->Pfx2 ^S2J*fx3 Pffy* ^ We observe that the submatrix consisting of the last three clauses is just a variant of the submatrix consisting of the first three clauses (the two boxes in the figure). Also, the connections within thése submatrices are the sàme. Merely the connections to the fourth clause differ for the two submatrices. Therefore is suffices to represent just one of these submatrices as in the following figure. Ili The horizontal bar between the two literals of the fourth clause indicates that the connections from the first of these litterals have to be considered as going into another variant of the rest of the matrix than the connections from the second literal (splitting of the fourth clause). This fact is reflected in a more liberal condition of unifiability of the connections. The connections starting from the first literal of the fourth clause are not required to be (and, in fact, are not) compatible with the connections starting from the second literal of the fourth clause. Splitting can also be applied in a nested way with several levels of splitting represented in a tree-like structure. There is not enough space here to go into any details of this. Splitting can be combined with factorization. For the example above we then obtain the compound instance Of course, for ali these compound instances it is not necessary to actually represent ali of the variants in a computer. One index (subscript) and a poin-, ter to the clause of the originai matrix (or pointers to its literals) are enough. Extensions of First Order Predicate Logic It is a widely accepted opinion (based on practical experience) that a theorem prover that is to be useful in practical application should not be just a theorem prover for first order predicate logie but it should be specialized to some particular field of application. One such example is that some of the function symbols are assumed to 112 obey certain laws, for example associativity or commutativity. Such assumptions can be brought into a proof calculus such as the resolution or the connection method by replacing the concept of unification by the concept of unification modulo these laws (theory unification). Equality is handled in resolution by the paramodulation rule. In the connection method a new kind of connections, equality-connections, is introduced. A similar approach has been used to handle induction. The connection method is also suitable for theorem provihg in higher order logie. However, the problem of unification is undecidable in this case. Parallelism There are several possibilities for exploting parallelism in the connection method. One obvious way is to view the process of finding a deduction in the connecton method as an and-or-tree with each and-node corresponding to the choice of a literal within a clause and each or-node corresponding to the choice of the next clause for extension. In the case of and-nodes the substitutions obtained for the subtrees corresponding to this node must be compatible. Another way of exploiting parallelism is to choose small subsets of the set of ali clauses of the matrix and to determine the set of non-complementary paths through each of these subsets in parallel and to stepwise increase these subsets by suitably combining the corresponding sets of paths until a characterization of the set of non-complementary paths of the whole matrix is obtained. For both of these there exist experimental implementations in Munich in the frame of an ESPRIT project in the course of which a parallel theoremprover is being implemented as a simulation on a sequential machine and then on a multiprocessor system. Conclusions The connection method has more complicated rules that the resolution method which has just the rules of resolution and factorization. However, 113 this variety of rules gives the connection method the advantage that the proof process is more structured. Also, there is the simplest version of the connection calculus which by itself is not efficient enough but can serve as a guide for a strategy for the more efficient extensions we have discussed in this paper. It is stili not yet clear in detail which extensions of the simplest version are necessary, for example to get exactly the potential strength, in terms of length of shortest deductions, as the resolution method. This is one topic for future research. Some of the newer developments of implementations have been indicated in the paper. Parallel implementations is a working field of the Munich group. LITERATURE P.B. Andrews, Theorem Proving Via General Matings. J. ACM 28, 193-214 (1981) W. Bibel, Automated Theorem Proving, Vieweg (1982) W. Bibel, Matings in Matrices. C. ACM 26, Nov. 1983, 844-852 C. L. Chang, R. C. T. Lee, Symbolìc Logic and Mechanical Theorem Proving. Academic Press, New York (1973). D.W. Loveland, Automated Theorem Proving, A Logicai Bases. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1978) J.A. Robinson, A Machine-Oriented Logic Based on the Resolution Principle. J. ACM 12,23-41(1965) Stickel, Automated Deduction by Theory Resolution L. Wos, R. Overbeek, E. Lusk, J. Boyle, Automated Reasoning. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N. J. (1984) 114 E. Eder, Properties of Substitutions and Unifications-, Journal of Symbolic Computation Voi. 1 (1985). E. Eder, An Implementation of a Theorem Prover Based on the Connection_method\ Art. Intell. (W. Bibel, B. Petkoff, eds.); North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 121-128 (1985). S. Bayerl, E. Eder, F. Kurfej3, R. Letz, J. Schumann, An implementation of a PROLOGlike Theorem Prover based on the Connection Method-, Art. Intell. II, Ph. Jorrand. V. Sgurev, (eds.), Proc. Sec. Int. Conf. on Artificial Intelligence: Methodology, Systems, Applications (AIMSA 86), North-Hplland, Amesterdam, p. 29-36 (1987). B. Fronhòfer, On réftnements of the connection method. In: Algebra, Combinatorics and Logic in Computer Science, (J. Demetrovics, G. Katona, A. Salomas, eds.), Colloquia Mathematica Soc. J. Bolyal, Voi. 42, North-Holland, Amsterdam 1985, pp. 391-401. S. Bayerl, R. Letz, J. Schumann, SETHEO/1 Sequential Theorem prover based on the connection method for full first order logie - Deliverable D 11 - ESPRIT 415 F DeliverableDll (1987). W. Bibel, R. Letz, J. Schumann: Bottom-up Enhancements of Deductive Systems-, Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Information-Control Systems of Robots, NorthHolland, Amsterdam (1987). E. EDER - Fachbercich Informatile, Universitàt Dortmund, D - 4600, Dortmund 50, F.R. Germany.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz