2. Utility functions How to rank the following 4 investment choices? Investment A x p(x) 4 1 Investment B x p(x) 5 1 Investment C x p(x) −5 1/4 0 1/2 40 1/4 Investment D x p(x) −10 1/5 10 1/5 20 2/5 30 1/5 When there is no risk, we choose the investment with the highest rate of return. — Maximum Return Criterion. e.g. Investment B dominates Investment A, but this criterion fails to compare Investment B with Investment C. Maximum expected return criterion (for risky investments) Identifies the investment with the highest expected return. 1 1 1 (−5) + (0) + (40) = 8.75 4 2 4 1 2 1 1 ED (x) = (−10) + (10) + (20) + (30) = 14. 5 5 5 5 Is such procedure well justified? EC (x) = St Petersburg paradox (failure of Maximum Expected Return Criterion) Tossing of a fair coin until the first head shows up. The prize is 2x−1 where x is the number of tosses until the first head shows up (the game is then ended). ∞ 1 x−1 Expected prize of the game = 2 = ∞. x 2 x=1 Question What is the certain amount that one would be willing to accept so that it is indifferent between playing the game for free or receiving this certain sum? This certain amount is called the certainty equivalent of the game. • When people are faced with such a lottery in experimental trials, they refuse to pay more than a finite price (usually low). • There is a very small chance to receive large sum of money. This occurs when x is large. 1 e.g. x = 10, there is a change of 10 to receive 29. 2 • Alternative view In Mark Six, people are willing to pay a few dollars to bet on winning a reasonably large sum with infinitesimally small chance. • Certainty equivalent of the game under log utility ∞ ∞ 1 x−1 x−1 ln 2 = ln 2 = ln 2 ln c = E[ln R] = x x x=1 2 x=1 2 so that c = 2 is the certainty equivalent. How much the player is ready to pay to play the game? We need to solve for U (w) = E[U (w + y − p)] where w = initial wealth y = price received from the game p = price that the player is willing to pay to participate in the game. Pairwise comparison Consider the set of alternatives B, how to determine which element in the choice set B that is preferred? The individual first considers two arbitrary elements: x1, x2 ∈ B. He then picks the preferred element x1 and discards the other. From the remaining elements, he picks the third one and compares with the winner. The process continues and the winner among all alternatives is identified. Let the choice set B be a convex subset of the n-dimensional Euclidean space. The component xi of the n-dimensional vector x may represent xi units of commodity i. By convex, we mean that if x1, x2 ∈ B, then αx1 + (1 − α)x2 ∈ B for any α ∈ [0, 1]. • Each individual is endowed with a preference relation, . • Given any elements x1 and x2 ∈ B, x1 x2 means either that x1 is preferred to x2 or that x1 is indifferent to x2. Three axioms for Reflexivity For any x1 ∈ B, x1 x1. Comparability For any x1, x2 ∈ B, either x1 x2 or x2 x1 . Transitivity For x1 , x2, x3 ∈ B, given x1 x2 and x2 x3, then x1 x3. Remark 1. Without the comparability axiom, an individual could not determine an optimal choice. This is because there would exist at least two elements of B between which the individual could not discriminate. 2. The transitivity axiom ensures that the choices are consistent. Example 1 Let B = {(x, y) : x ∈ [0, ∞) and y ∈ [0, ∞)} represent the set of alternatives. Let x represent ounces of orange soda and y represent ounces of grape soda. It is easily seen that B is a convex subset of R2. Suppose the individual is concerned only with the total quantity of soda available, the more the better, then the individual is endowed with the following preference relation: For (x1 , y1), (x2, y2 ) ∈ B, (x1 , y1 ) (x2 , y2) if and only if x1 + y1 ≥ x2 + y2 . Dictionary order Let the choice set B = {(x, y) : x ∈ [0, ∞), y ∈ [0, ∞)}, the dictionary order is defined as follows: Suppose (x1, y1 ) ∈ B and (x2, y2 ) ∈ B, then (x1 , y1 ) (x2 , y2) if and only if [x1 > x2 ] or [x1 = x2 and y1 ≥ y2]. It is easy to check that the dictionary order satisfies the three basic axioms of a preference relation. Definition Given x, y ∈ B and a preference relation satisfying the above three axioms. 1. x is indifferent to y, written as x∼y if and only if x y and y x. 2. x is strictly preferred to y, written as xy if and only if x y and not x ∼ y. Axiom 4 – Order Preserving For any x, y ∈ B where x y and α, β ∈ [0, 1], [αx + (1 − α)y] [βx + (1 − β)y] if and only if α > β. Example 1 revisited Recall the preference relation defined in Example 1, we take (x1 , y1 ), (x2 , y2) ∈ B such that (x1 , y1 ) (x2, y2 ) so that x1 + y1 − x2 − y2 > 0. Take α, β ∈ [0, 1] such that α > β, and observe α[(x1 + y1 ) − (x2 + y2 )] > β[(x1 + y1) − (x2 + y2)]. Adding x2 + y2 to both sides, we obtain α(x1 + y1) + (1 − α)(x2 + y2) > β(x1 + y1 ) + (1 − β)(x2 + y2). Axiom 5 – Intermediate Value For any x, y, z ∈ B, if x y z, then there exists a unique α ∈ (0, 1) such that αx + (1 − α)z ∼ y. Remark Given 3 alternatives with rankings of x y z, there exists a fractional combination of x and z that is indifferent to y. Trade-offs between the alternatives exist. Example 1 revisited Given x1 + y1 > x2 + y2 > x3 + y3 , choose α= (x2 + y2 ) − (x3 + y3) . (x1 + y1 ) − (x3 + y3) Rearranging gives α(x1 + y1 ) + (1 − α)(x3 + y3 ) = x2 + y2 so that [α(x1 , y1 ) + (1 − α)(x3 , y3)] ∼ (x2, y2 ). Dictionary order does not satisfy the intermediate value axiom Suppose (x1 , y1), (x2 , y2 ), (x3 , y3) ∈ B such that (x1, y1 ) (x2 , y2) (x3 , y3) and x1 > x2 = x3 and y2 > y3. For any α ∈ (0, 1), we have α(x1 , y1) + (1 − α)(x3 , y3 ) = α(x1 , y1) + (1 − α)(x2 , y3 ) = (αx1 + (1 − α)x2 , αy1 + (1 − α)y3 ). But for α > 0, we have αx1 + (1 − α)x2 > x2 so α(x1 , y1) + (1 − α)(x3 , y3 ) (x2 , y2) for all In other words, there is no α ∈ (0, 1) such that αx + (1 − α)z ∼ y. α ∈ (0, 1). Axiom 6 – Boundedness There exist x∗, y ∗ ∈ B such that x∗ z y ∗ for all z ∈ B. • This Axiom ensures the existence of a most preferred element x∗ ∈ B and a least preferred element y ∗ ∈ B. Example 1 revisited Recall B = {(x, y) : x ∈ [0, ∞) and y ∈ [0, ∞)}. Given any (z1, z2) ∈ B, we have (z1 + 1, z2) (z1, z2) since z1 + z2 + 1 > z1 + z2. Therefore, a maximum does not exist. Motivation for defining utility Knowledge of the preference relation effectively requires a complete listing of preferences over all pairs of elements from the choice set B. We define a utility function that assigns a numeric value to each element of the choice set such that larger numeric value implies higher preference. Theorem – Existence of Utility Function Let B denote the set of payoffs from a finite number of securities, also being a convex subset of Rn. Let denote a preference relation on B. Suppose satisfies the following axioms (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) ∀x ∈ B, x x. ∀x, y ∈ B, x y or y x. For any x, y, z ∈ B, if x y and y z, then x z. For any x, y ∈ B, x y and α, β ∈ [0, 1], αx + (1 − α)y βx + (1 − β)y if and only if α > β. (v) For any x, y, z ∈ B, suppose x y z, then there exists a unique α ∈ (0, 1) such that αx + (1 − α)z ∼ y. (vi) There exist x∗, y ∗ ∈ B such that ∀z ∈ B, x∗ z y ∗. Then there exists a utility function U : B → R such that (a) x y iff U (x) > U (y). (b) x ∼ y iff U (x) = U (y). To show the existence of U : B → R, we write down one such function and show that it satisfies the stated conditions. Based on Axiom 6, we choose x∗, y ∗ ∈ B such that x∗ z y ∗ for all z ∈ B. Without loss of generality, let x∗ y ∗. [Otherwise, x∗ ∼ z ∼ y ∗ for all z ∈ B. In this case, U (z) = 0 for all z ∈ B, which is a trivial utility function that satisfies conditions (a) and (b).] Consider an arbitrary z ∈ B. There are 3 possibilities: 1. z ∼ x∗; 2. x∗ z y ∗; 3. z ∼ y∗. We define U by giving its value under all 3 cases: 1. U (z) = 1 2. By Axiom 5, there exists a unique α ∈ (0, 1) such that [αx∗ + (1 − α)y ∗] ∼ z. Define U (z) = α. 3. U (z) = 0. Such U satisfies properties (a) and (b). Proof of property (a) Necessity Suppose z1, z2 ∈ B are such that z1 z2, we need to show U (z1) > U (z2). Consider the four possible cases. 1. 2. 3. 4. z1 ∼ x∗ z1 ∼ x∗ x∗ z1 x∗ z1 Case 1 z2 z2 z2 z2 y∗ ∼ y∗ y∗ ∼ y∗. By definition, U (z1) = 1 and U (z2 ) = α, where α ∈ (0, 1) uniquely satisfies αx∗ + (1 − α)y ∗ ∼ z2. Now, U (z1) = 1 > α = U (z2 ). Case 2 By definition, U (z1) = 1 > 0 = U (z2). Case 3 By defintion, U (zi) = αi, where αi ∈ (0, 1) uniquely satisfies αix∗ + (1 − αi)y∗ ∼ zi, so that z1 ∼ [α1x∗ + (1 − α)y∗ ] ∼ [α2x∗ + (1 − α2)y∗ ] ∼ z2 . We claim α1 > α2. Assume not, then α1 ≤ α2 . By Axiom 4, [α2 x∗ + (1 − α2)y∗ ] [α1x∗ + (1 − α1)y∗ ]. This is a contradiction. Hence, α1 > α2 is true and U (z1 ) = α1 > U (z2) = α2. Case 4 By definition, U (z1) = α1, where α1 ∈ (0, 1) uniquely satisfies α1x∗ + (1 − α1 )y∗ ∼ y1 and U (z2 ) = 0. We have U (z1) = α1 > 0 = U (z2). Sufficiency Suppose, given z1, z2 ∈ B, that U (z1) > U (z2), we would like to show z1 z2. Consider the following 4 cases 1. U (z1) = 1 and U (z2) = α2 , where α2 ∈ (0, 1) uniquely satisfies [α2x∗ + (1 − α2 )y ∗] ∼ z2. 2. U (z1) = 1, where z1 ∼ x∗ and U (z2 ) = 0, where z2 ∼ y ∗. 3. U (zi) = αi , where αi ∈ (0, 1) uniquely satisfies [αi x∗ + (1 − αi )y ∗] ∼ zi. 4. U (z1) = α1 and U (z2) = 0, where z2 ∼ y ∗. Case 1 z1 ∼ x∗ ∼ [1 · x∗ + 0 · y ∗] and z2 ∼ [α2 x∗ + (1 − α2)y ∗]. By Axiom 4, 1 > α2 so that z1 z2. Case 2 z1 ∼ x∗ y ∗ ∼ z2. Case 3 z1 ∼ [α1 x∗ + (1 − α1)y ∗] z2 ∼ [α2x∗ + (1 − α2)y ∗ ] Since α1 > α2 , by Axiom 4, z1 z2. Case 4 z1 ∼ [α1 x∗ + (1 − α1)y ∗] and z2 ∼ y ∗ ∼ [0x∗ + (1 − 0)y ∗]. By Axiom 4 and Axiom 3, since α1 > 0, z1 z2. Proof of Property (b) Necessity Suppose z1 ∼ z2 but U (z1) = U (z2), then U (z1) > U (z2) or U (z2) > U (z1 ). By property (a), this implies z1 z2 or z2 z1, a contradiction. Hence, U (z1) = U (z2). Sufficiency Suppose U (z1) = U (z2), but z1 z2 or z1 ≺ z2. By property (a), this implies U (z1 ) > U (z2) or U (z2) > U (z1), a contradiction. Hence, z1 ∼ z2 . Choices among lotteries How to make a choice between the following two lotteries: L1 = {p1, A1; p2, A2; · · · ; pn , An} L2 = {q1, A1; q2, A2; · · · ; qn , An}? The outcomes are A1, · · · , An ; pi and qi are the probabilities of occurrence of Ai in L1 and L2, respectively. These outcomes are mutually exclusive and only one outcome can be realized under each investment. Comparability When faced by two monetary outcomes Ai and Aj , the investor must say Ai Aj , Aj Ai or Ai ∼ Aj . Continuity If A3 A2 and A2 A1, then there exists U (A2) [0 ≤ U (A2 ) ≤ 1] such that L = {[1 − U (A2)], A1; U (A2), A3} ∼ A2. For a given set of outcomes A1, A2 and A3, these probabilities are a function of A2, hence the notation U (A2). Why is it called continuity axiom? When U (A2) = 1, we obtain L = A3 A2; when U (A2) = 0, we obtain L = A1 ≺ A2. If we increase U (A2) continuously from 0 to 1, we hit a value U (A2 ) such that L ∼ A2. Remark Though U (A2) is a probability value, we will see that it is also the investor’s utility function. Interchangeability Given L1 = {p1, A1; p2, A2; p3, A3} and A2 ∼ A = {q, A1; (1 − q), A2}, the investor is indifferent between L1 and L2 = {p1, A1; p2 , A; p3, A3}. Transitivity Given L1 L2 and L2 L3, then L1 L3. Also, if L1 ∼ L2 and L2 ∼ L3, then L1 ∼ L3. Decomposability A complex lottery has lotteries as prizes. A simple lottery has monetary values A1, A2 etc as prizes. Consider a complex lottery L∗ = (q, L1; (1 − q), L2), where L1 = {p1, A1; (1 − p1 ), A2} and L2 = {p2 , A1; (1 − p2), A2}, L∗ can be decomposed into a simply lottery L = {p∗, A1; (1−p∗), A2}, with A1 and A2 as prizes where p∗ = qp1 + (1 − q)p2. Monotonicity (a) For monetary outcomes, A2 > A1 =⇒ A2 A1. (b) For lotteries (i) Let L1 = {p, A1; (1 − p), A2} and L2{p, A1; (1 − p), A3}. A3 > A2, then A3 A2; and L2 L1. If (ii) Let L1 = {p, A1; (1 − p), A2} and L2 = {q, A1; (1 − q), A2}, also A2 > A1 (hence A2 A1). If p < q, then L1 L2. Theorem The optimal criterion for ranking alternative investments is the expected utility of the various investments. Proof How to make a choice between L1 and L2 L1 = {p1, A1; p2, A2; · · · ; pn , An} L2 = {q1, A1; q2, A2; · · · ; qn , An} A1 < A2 < · · · < An , where Ai are various monetary outcomes? By comparability axiom, we can compare Ai. Further, by monotonicity axiom, we determine that A1 < A2 < · · · < An implies A1 ≺ A2 ≺ · · · ≺ An. Define A∗i = {[1 − U (Ai)], A1; U (Ai), An} where 0 ≤ U (Ai ) ≤ 1. By continuity axiom, for every Ai, there exists U (Ai) such that Ai ∼ A∗i . For A1, U (A1) = 0, hence A∗1 ∼ A1; for An , U (An) = 1. For other Ai, 0 < U (Ai) < 1. By the monotonicity and transitivity axioms, U (Ai) increases from zero to one as Ai increases from A1 to An . Substitute Ai by A∗i in L1 successively and by the interchangeability axiom, = {p , A∗ ; p , A∗ ; · · · ; pn, A∗ }. L1 ∼ L 1 1 n 1 2 2 By the decomposability axiom, ∼ L∗ = {Σp [1 − U (A )], A ; Σp U (A ), A }. L1 ∼ L n 1 i i 1 i i 1 Similarly L2 ∼ L∗2 = {Σqi[1 − U (Ai)], A1; ΣqiU (Ai), An}. By the monotonicity axiom, L∗1 L∗2 if ΣpiU (Ai) > ΣqiU (Ai). This is precisely the expected utility criterion. The same conclusion applies to L1 L2, due to transitivity. Remark Why does U (Ai) reflect the investor’s utility? Recall Ai ∼ A∗i = {[1 − U (Ai)], A1; U (Ai), An }, such a function U (Ai) always exists, though not all investors would agree on the specific value of U (Ai). • By the monotonicity axiom, utility is non-decreasing. • A utility function is determined up to a positive linear transformation, so its value is not limited to the range [0, 1]. “Determined” means that the ranking of the projects by the MEUC does not change. • The absolute difference or ratio of the utilities of two investment choices gives no indication of the degree of preference of one over the other since utility values can be expanded or suppressed by a linear transformation. Characterization of utility functions 1. More is being preferred to less: u(w) > 0 2. Investors’ taste for risk – averse to risk (reject a fair gamble) – neutral toward risk (indifferent to a fair gamble) – seek risk (select a fair gamble) 3. Investors’ preference changes with a change in wealth. Percentage of wealth invested in risky asset changes as wealth changes. Jensen’s inequality Suppose u(w) ≤ 0 and X is a random variable, then u(E[X]) ≥ E[u(X)]. Write E[X] = µ; since u(w) is concave, we have u(w) ≤ u(µ) + u(µ)(w − µ) for all values of w. Risk aversion Replace w by X and take the expectation on each side E[u(X)] ≤ u(µ). Interpretation E[u(X)] represents the expected utility of the gamble associated with X. The investor prefers a sure wealth of µ = E[X] rather than playing the game, if u(w) ≤ 0. This indicates risk aversion. Insurance premium Individual’s total initial wealth is w, and the wealth is subject to random loss Y during the period, 0 ≤ Y < w. Let π be the insurable premium payable at time 0 that fully reimburses the loss (neglecting the time value of money). 1. If the individual decides not to buy insurance, then the expected utility is E[u(w − Y )]. The expectation is based on investor’s own subjective assessment of the loss. 2. If he buys the insurance, the utility at time 1 is u(w − π). Note that w − π is the sure wealth. If the individual is risk averse [u(w) ≤ 0], then from Jensen’s inequality (change X to w − Y ), we obtain u(w − E[Y ]) ≥ E[u(w − Y )]. The fair value of insurance premium π is determined by u(w − π) = E[u(w − Y )] so that we can deduce that π ≥ E[Y ]. Suppose the higher moments of Y are negligible, it can be deduced that the maximum price that a risk-averse individual with wealth w is willing to pay to avoid a possible loss of Y is approximately σY2 π ≈ µY + RA(w − µ), 2 where RA(w) = −u(w)/u (w), 0 ≤ Y < w and µ = E[Y ] < w. With higher RA(w), the individual is willing to pay a higher premium to avoid risk. Proof We start from the governing equation for π u(w − π) = E[u(w − Y )]. Write Y = µ + zV , where V is a random variable with zero mean. Here, z is a small perturbation parameter. We then have u(w − π) = E[u(w − µ − zV )]. (1) We are seeking the perturbation expansion of π in powers of z in the form π = a + bz + cz 2 + · · · (i) Setting z = 0, u(w − a) = E[u(w − µ)] = u(w − µ) so that a = µ. (ii) Differentiating (1) with respect to z and setting z = 0, −π (0)u(w − π) = E[−V u(w − µ)] since E(V ) = 0 and π (0) = b, so b = 0. (2) (iii) Differentiating (1) twice with respect to z and setting z = 0 −π (0)u(w − π) = E[V 2u(w − µ)] var(V ) u c = − . w−µ 2 u u(w) Define the absolute risk aversion coefficient: RA(w) = − , we u (w) have RA(w − µ) 2 z var(V ) 2 σY2 RA(w − µ). = µ+ 2 π ≈ µ+ σY2 RA(w − µ) is called the risk premium. For low level of π−µ = 2 risks, π − µ is proportional to the product of variance of the loss distribution and individual’s absolute risk aversion. Relative risk aversion coefficient 2 . The whole Let X be a fair game with E[X] = 0 and var(X) = σX wealth w is invested into the game. Choice A Choice B w+X wC (with certainty) The investor is indifferent to these two positions iff E[u(w + X)] = u(wC ). Note that wC = w − (w − wC ), indicating the payment of w − wC for Choice B. The difference w − wC represents the maximum amount the investor would be willing to pay in order to avoid the risk of the game. Let q be the fraction of wealth an investor is giving up in order to w − wC or wC = w(1 − q). Let Z be the avoid the gamble; then q = w return per dollar invested so that for a fair gamble, E[Z] = 1. Write 2. var(Z) = σZ Suppose we invest w dollars, the return would be wZ. Expand u(wZ) around w: u(w) u(wZ) = u(w) + u (w)(wZ − w) + (wZ − w)2 + · · · E[u(wZ)] = u(w) + 0 + u(w) 2 2 2 w2 σZ + ··· On the other hand, u(wC ) = u(w(1 − q)) = u(w) − qwu (w) + · · · . Equating u(wC ) with E[u(wZ)], we obtain u(w) 2 2 w σZ = −u(w)qw 2 so that 2 u (w) σZ q=− w . 2 u (w) u(w) , Define RR(w) = coefficient of relative risk aversion = −w u (w) 2 σZ w − wC = percentage of risk premium = RR (w). then q = w 2 Types of utility functions 1. Exponential utility u(x) = 1 − e−ax, x > 0 u(x) = ae−ax u(x) = −a2e−ax < 0 (risk aversion) so that RA(x) = a for all wealth level x. 2. Power utility xα − 1 , u(x) = α u(x) = xα−1 α≤1 u(x) = (α − 1)xα−2 1−α and RR (x) = 1 − α. RA(x) = x 3. Logarithmic utility (corresponds to α → 0+ in power utility) u(x) = a ln x + b, u(x) = a/x u(x) = −a/x2 1 RA(x) = and RR (x) = 1. x a>0 Properties of power utility functions: U (x) = xγ /γ, γ ≤ 1 (i) γ > 0, aggressive utility Consider γ = 1, corresponding to U (x) = x. This is the expected value criterion. Recall that the strategy that maximizes the expected value bets all capital on the most favorable sector – prone to early bankruptcy. For γ = 1/2; consider two opportunities: (a) capital will double with a probability of 0.9 or it will go to zero with probability 0.10, (b) capital will increase by 25% with certainty. √ √ Since 0.9 × 2 > 1.25, so opportunity (a) is preferred to (b). However, opportunity (a) is certain to go bankrupt. (ii) γ < 0, conservative utility For γ = −1/2, consider two opportunities (a) capital quadruples in value with certainty (b) with probability 0.5 capital remains constant and with probability 0.5 capital is multiplied by 10 million. Since −4−1/2 > −0.5 − 0.5(10, 000, 000)−1/2, opportunity (a) is preferred to (b). Apparently, the best choice for γ may be negative, but close to zero. This utility function is close to the logarithm function. Example An investor has an initial wealth of w and can allocate funds between two assets: a risky asset and a riskless asset. m = expected rate of return on the risky security = piu + (1 − p)id so that m − id iu − m p= , 1−p = . iu − id iu − id • Impose the condition: m > if , otherwise a rational investor will never invest a positive amount in the risky asset. • No arbitrage conditions: iu > if > id. Also, iu > m > id for 0 < p < 1. • Let x be the fraction of initial wealth placed on the risky asset. wα , 0 < α < 1. Choose the power utility function: α Investor’s expected utility: p {w[(1 + if ) + x(iu − if )]}α α + (1 − p) {w[1 + if ) + x(id − if )]}α α . Since the utility function is concave, the second order condition for a maximum is automatically satisfied. Optimal proportion where θ= x∗ = (1 + if )(θ − 1) (iu − if ) + θ(if − id) [p(iu − if )]1/(1−α) [(1 − p)(if − id)]1/(1−α) . The no-arbitrage condition leads to θ ≥ 1. (i) x∗ > 0 ⇐⇒ θ > 1. (ii) As m → if , θ → 1 and x∗ → 0. A risk-averse investor will prefer the riskless asset if it has the same return as the expected return on the risky asset. (iii) x∗ < 1 as long as θ < 1 + iu . 1 + id Continuous-time limit of the discrete-time model Assume stationarity of the return distribution and no transaction costs, the multi-period case collapses to a series of identical singleperiod problems. The optimal x∗ is the same at each time interval and it is the same as that of the one-period case. Assuming discrete random walk of proportional jumps, with h = time step and σ 2 as the variance rate, we obtain √ 1 + iu = e σ h , √ 1 + id = e−σ h, 1 + m = eµh, erh = 1 + rf . Express iu, id, if and p in terms of h. Taking h → 0, x∗ = µ−r risk premium on risky asset . = 2 σ (1− α) variance × relative risk aversion Merton’s ratio • Merton assumes GBM for the asset price process with mean µ and variance σ 2; and power utility function. • It is optimal for the investor to maintain a constant proportion of wealth in the risky asset – continuous rebalancing of portfolio is required (though at no transaction cost). Minimum expected excess return required to induce the individual to invest on the risky asset r = random rate of return of the single risky asset x = proportion of wealth invested in the risky asset w0 = initial wealth a = wealth invested in the risky asset = random wealth at the end of the investment period w r = riskfree interest rate = (w0 − a)(1 + r) + a(1 + r) = w0(1 + r) + a(r − r), w a = xw0 For the individual to invest at least xw0 amount of his wealth on d {E[u(w)]} ≥ 0 or the risky asset, it must be that da E[u(w0 (1 + r) + xw0 (r − r))(r − r)] ≥ 0. Performing the Taylor expansion of u(w0 (1 + r) + xw0(r − r)) at w0(1 + r), we obtain E[u(w0 (1 + r) + xw0 (r − r))(r − r)] = u(w0(1 + r))E[r − r] + u(w0(1 + r))xw0 E[(r − r)2] + o(E[(r − r)2 ]). Assuming low level of risk of r so that o(E[(r−r)2]) can be neglected. The minimum risk premium required to induce x portion of wealth invested on the risky asset is u(w0(1 + r)) E[r − r] ≥ −xw0 E[(r − r)2 ], u (w0(1 + r)) for all 0 < x ≤ 1. Log utility and maximization of the geometric mean return pj − 1, where r is the (1 + r ) Geometric mean return = rG = n j j j=1 rate of return if outcome j occurs with probability pj . Taking logarithm on both sides ln(1 + rG) = n pj ln(1 + rj ). j=1 Consider the log utility function: max E ln w1, where w1 is the endof-period wealth. Let r be the random rate of return. Maximization of the expected log utility is given by w max E[ln w1 − ln w0] = max E ln 1 w0 = max E[ln(1 + r)] = max n pj ln(1 + rj ). j=1 Maximization of the geometric mean return is equivalent to the maximization of the expected utility, where the logarithmic function is used as the utility function. Summary on risk aversion coefficients Absolute risk aversion U (W ) A(W ) = − U (W ) If A(W ) has the same sign for all values of W , then the investor has the same risk preference (risk averse, neutral or seeker) for all values of W (global). Relative risk aversion W U (W ) . R(W ) = − U (W ) Note that utility functions are only unique up to a strictly positive affine transformation. The second derivative alone cannot be used to characterize the intensity of risk averse behaviors. The risk aversion coefficients are invarant to a strictly positive affine transformation of individual utility function. Changes in Absolute Risk Aversion with Wealth Condition Increasing absolute risk aversion Constant absolute risk aversion Decreasing absolute risk aversion Definition As wealth increases, hold fewer dollars in risky assets As wealth increases, hold some dollar amount in risky assets As wealth increases, hold more dollars in risky assets Property of A(W ) A(W ) > 0 Example A(W ) = 0 −e−CW A(W ) < 0 ln W W −CW 2 Changes in Relative Risk Aversion with Wealth Condition Increasing relative risk aversion Constant relative risk aversion Decreasing relative risk aversion Definition Percentage invested in risky assets declines as wealth increases Percentage invested in risky assets is unchanged as wealth increases Percentage invested in risky assets increases as wealth increases Property of R(W ) R(W ) > 0 Examples of Utility Functions W − bW 2 R(W ) = 0 ln W R(W ) < 0 −1/2 2W −e
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz