Religious Research Association, Inc. Rationality, Choice, and the Religious Economy: Individual and Collective Rationality in Supply and Demand Author(s): Carl L. Bankston III Source: Review of Religious Research, Vol. 45, No. 2 (Dec., 2003), pp. 155-171 Published by: Religious Research Association, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3512580 Accessed: 28/10/2009 14:15 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=rra. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Religious Research Association, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Review of Religious Research. http://www.jstor.org RATIONALITY, CHOICE, AND THE RELIGIOUS ECONOMY: INDIVIDUAL AND COLLECTIVE RATIONALITY IN SUPPLY AND DEMAND CARLL. BANKSTON III TULANEUNIVERSITY REVIEWOF RELIGIOUSRESEARCH,2003, VOLUME45:2, PAGES 155-171 One of the most useful contributionsof rational choice theories to the sociology of religion has been the concept of the religious economy.However,this study argues that the rationalchoice view of the religiouseconomystill suffersfrom serious shortcomings. Here, I argue that the concept of rationality in economic action is more complex than rational choice theoristsgenerally recognize.Part of this complexity involves the multi-dimensionalnatureof the concept and part of it involves thefact that degrees of rationalityin individualactions mustbe understoodin relationto collective actions and contexts. One of the consequencesof the underdevelopedunderstanding of rationality is that theorists have tended to gloss over the processes by which individualsand groups makedecisions that create demandsfor specific types of religiousgoods. I attemptto approachtheseproblemby describingthe dimensions of rationality,by describing the relationsbetween rationalityat the individuallevel and at aggregate levels, and byprovidinga schematizationto suggest how supplyof religious goods and demandfor them interactat individualand collective levels. he rationalchoice approachto religion has become increasinglyinfluentialover the courseof the past decade,andit has been a sourceof substantialcontroversy(Sherkat and Ellison 1999; Williams 2000). Perhaps the most useful contribution of this approachto the study of religion has been the idea of the religious economy, an idea that has providedthe basis for a "newparadigm"in the sociology of religion (Iannaccone1992; Warner1993). While the rationalchoice idea of the religious economy has made valuable contributionsto the sociology of religion, the notion of rationalityemployed by its proponents is still theoretically under-developedand it is generally used with little precision. Closer analysis of this notion can yield a bettermodel of how religion can be said to function as an economy,andit can demonstratemore clearlyhow an economic perspectivemay explain religious behaviorwithoutimputinga uniformrationalityto all action. Rationalchoice theory,also called rationalaction theory,is a theoreticalmodel developed to account for the ways in which the actions of individuals yield aggregate consequences(Coleman1990;ColemanandFarraro1992;Hedstr6m1993;HechterandKanazawa 1997; Zafirovsky 1999). In this essay, I will concentrateon two fundamentalproblemsfor rationalchoice views of religion thatareimplicitin this theoreticalmodel. First,if one says thatreligious, beliefs, actions, and associationsare consequencesof the rationalchoices of individuals,one must define rationalityclearly,in a mannerthatis not tautologousand that takes into considerationthe varyinguses of the term. Second, one needs to be clear about the connectionbetweenindividualchoices and aggregatesocial phenomena.Religion, like other institutions,does not simply involve individualsmaking choices among a range of rT 155 Review of Religious Research commodities.It entailsindividualsbecomingpartsof social aggregatesthathave goals and internalpatternsof organizationof theirown andthatshapeboth the choices and the goals of the individuals.Therefore,afterI examinethe conceptof rationalityand attemptto present a plausible definition,I considerhow rationalityand the individuallevel may be connectedto rationalityas a collectivephenomenon.Finally,I attemptto makeclearthe relevance of my re-conceptualizationby discussing how rationality,as I have defined it at both the individualand the collective levels, may be relatedto the idea of the religious economy. RATIONALITY DEFINED: A MULTI-DIMENSIONAL CONCEPT Rational choice explanationsof religion often tend to offer ratherbrief definitions of rationality.This is troublingbecause the term is one that is often used in differentways, althoughin ways thatare generallyrelated.One of the most fundamentalcharacteristicsof rationalityis its teleologicalor goal-orientedcharacter.Traditionalismin the Weberiansense is not rational,in partbecause traditionalways of thinkingand behaving are producedby patternsreceivedfrom the past, ratherthanby considerationof goals (Weber[1922] 1978). Along these lines, Sherkat(1998) has found that traditionalsocializationfactors are predominantinfluences on contemporaryreligious beliefs and practices. The teleologicalcharacterof rationalityis the traitmost often identifiedby rationalchoice theoristsof religion (Boudon 1998) and it is often takenby these theoristsas the defining, or even the only trait.StarkandBainbridge(1987:113)proclaimthat"rationalityis marked by consistentgoal-orientedactivity."While socializationis undoubtedlyan importantinfluence on religious attachments,these attachmentscannotbe reducedto socializationalone. Explaininghumanphenomena,includingreligion, as orientedtowardgoals can be seen as a useful responseto whatWrong(1961) has termedthe "oversocialized"conceptof human nature,and it makes the valid point that, whateverone's ultimateposition on freedom of will, in practicaltermswe cannoteffectivelyunderstandhumanactionsby portrayinghuman beings as automata,since this would make it extremelydifficult to accountfor changes in individualand collective behavior(Spickard1998). A second trait,an orderedprocedurefor obtainingthe end, is implicit in the intentionality of rationality.An algorithm,a form of logic has to guide an actor or decision-maker to the goal. Syllogistic reasoning is the classic form of logic, but contemporaryrational choice theoristsaremore likely to emphasizethe cost-benefitanalysis, which incorporates syllogistic reasoningto comparethe efficiency of means in achieving ends. If (a,-E) representsa numericalvalue of a strengthof the relationshipbetween a given act anda desiredend (the syllogisticconnectionof the two), thenwe can qualifythis numerical value by dividing it by the cost (in effort or foregone opportunities)of the act. Since, undermost situations,a desiredend can be achievedby means otherthan a, (a2,a3,a4 ...), we need to comparemeansof achievinggoals to one another,with the value of each meansgoal associationqualifiedby the costs of the means. Equation1. (al-E)/c(al)_ n E(aiE)/c(a) (i=l) 156 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy When a, yields a greatervalue in this equation than any alternative,then the greatest gain has been achieved at the least cost, an outcome frequentlyidentified with rationality (Becker 1975; 1976; 1996; ColemanandFarraro1992). If the possible rangeof acts is constrainedby imperfect informationor understanding(as De Palma, Myers, and Papageorgiou 1994 have found), then this model can still work within the specified constraints:the numberand identity of ai will simply be limited (Bohman 1992). Indeed, since rational choice theory specifies thatindividualactions vary because of differingopportunitystructures (Coleman 1993), we can classify limitationsof informationas partof any available opportunitystructure.More seriously, in actual outcomes, the maximum possible value yielded by the equationcannotbe identified, eitherby actorsor observers,and actors will often settlefor less thanoptimization.For this reason,manyrationalchoice theorists,including rationalchoice theoristsof religion (Starkand Finke 2000), have leaned towardHerbert Simon's (1957) versions of means-end associations. In one version, Simon suggests thatactorsengage in "satisficing"ratherthanmaximizingoutcomes.The problemwith this suggestionis thatany subjectivelyacceptableresultcan be said to "satisfice,"meaningthat all goal-relatedbehaviorcan be seen as equally rational,regardlessof the amountor effectiveness of calculationinvolved. Rationalitythen contains only two values, "0" and "1," andfor those who explainall humanbehaviorin termsof goals, the second value is extended to all cases. In anotherversion,preferredby Starkand Finke (2000), Simon (1957) suggested thatindividualsengage in "subjectiverationality."Once again,however,this seems to reduce all action to a dichotomousmeasureof rationality,on which actions all tend to receive the same value. Reactingto earlierperspectivesthatcharacterizedreligion as irrational,comparedto science or otherendeavors,Starkand Bainbridge(1985; 1987), Starkand Finke (2000), and Stark(1996) portrayreligion as just as rationalas these other endeavors.Further,all religious commitments and behaviors are presentedas possessing the quality of rationality, including extreme acts of asceticism and martyrdom(see, particularly,Stark 1996). As Boudon (1998) has remarked,one way in which rational choice theorists can deal with behavioris by positinga deeperlevel of instrumentalism. This, apparentlynon-instrumental however,raises as many difficulties as it solves. There is something unsettling about a model of rationality that implicitly places the SummaTheologica of St. ThomasAcquinas on a par with the pillar-sittingof St. Simeon Stylites.Further,a theorythatessentiallydevelops a dichotomousvariableand then assigns all cases a value of "1" does not lend itself to any kind of verification.In orderto meaningfully thinkof religious behavioras rational,then, a theoristmust admit some degree of non-rationalityinto the evaluationof the behavior.The act in which an individualengages may have a value lower thanthe highest value yielded by the equationabove. This may be because traditionoutweighs calculationin the choice of behavior,or because the behavior is not determinedby calculationat all, but by emotion (Scheff 1992). One can see a given act or belief as "rational,"then, to the extentthatit is characterized by conscious choice to achieve a goal (as opposed to acceptanceof tradition)and to the extent that the act or belief involves systematic calculation to achieve the goal. Readers may note, though,thatthese firsttwo dimensionsinvolve actionsor beliefs directedtoward single goals. All individuals,though,have multiplegoals. They desirematerialgoods, social status,and even benefits that "areso beyond direct,this-worldlysatisfactionthat only the gods can provide them"(Starkand Bainbridge1985). 157 Review of Religious Research Heath (1976:79) makes a simplistic and erroneousclaim when he states that "rationality has nothingto do with ... goals."This overlooksthe fact thatgoals rarely,if ever, stand in isolation from othergoals. Every end is connectedto otherends, and these may be consistent or inconsistent.The rationalityof an end, then, is the degree to which it contributes to otherdesiredends. It follows thatto determinethe rationalityof an individual'sbehavior, we need to know not only the strengthof the relationshipbetween a specific act and a specific end, but also the strengthof the relationshipbetween that end and otherends. Since individualsdesire multiple ends, they may desire ends that are inconsistentwith each other.Piker(1972) offers an interestingexampleof the problemof consistencyin Thai religion. The Buddhistbelief in Kamma(Karma,in Sanskit),in which one receives good or evil as a consequenceof good or bad actions, seems to contradictthe widespreadbelief in magically efficacious amuletsamongThai Buddhists.We might note, though,thatthese believersattemptto rationalizetheirbeliefs; they attemptto come up with explanationsthat makeapparentlycontradictorybeliefs consistent.Piker(1972:24) suggeststhatthese uneasily juggled articlesof faith shouldbe understoodin termsof coherence,definedas "theconviction-however arrivedat, however supported-that one's guidingbeliefs aretrue,"but consistency is still a problemto the extent that adherentsconsciously considertheirvarying beliefs. When Piker asked Thai Buddhistsaboutmagic and moral causation,they did not simply shrugoff his questions.Instead,they attemptedto make theirbeliefs "rational" by creatinglines of reasoningaimed at consistency. One continuing problem of multiple goals is that short-termgoals may conflict with long-termgoals. The short-termrationalityof smoking a cigaretteto satisfy a cravingfor nicotine generallyhas a negative relationshipto the long-termgoal of avoiding an agonizing death from lung cancer (see Ainslie 1975). In religion, even more enticing physical pleasuresthan smoking may endangeropportunitiesfor salvation. I am arguing,then, thatrationalityconsists of at least threemajordimensions:teleology, systematizationof means,andconsistencyamonggoals. On all threedimensions,human actions can be interpretedin terms of degrees. Thoughts and behavior may be directed towardachieving goals, but they are also productsof socialization. Calculationaimed at goals is generally presentin human affairs,but it an be lessened by lack of clarity about ends, emotional excitement, and other influences. Individualswill hold some goals that contradictothers. I will arguebelow thatrecognizingthe multi-dimensionalcharacterof rationalitydoes not underminethe primaryargumentsof the religious economy model. On the contrary,it providesa basis for pointingout the similaritiesbetweenreligious goods and othersortsof goods. Purchasesof commoditiescan involve habit,impulsebuying,andconflictingdesires. However, neitherreligion nor the social venues customarilythoughtof as marketscan be understoodby referenceto individualprocesses alone. Understandingthe role of rational choice in religion necessitates a considerationof the connection between individual and collective rationality. INDIVIDUAL AND COLLECTIVE RATIONALITY At the aggregateas well as at the individuallevel, social behaviorcan possess degrees of rationalityon all threedimensions.Although structural-functionalist thought,following Parsons (1949), tends to present all social structuresas goal-oriented,social phenomena can be consciouslydirectedtowardachievinggoals to differentdegrees.For example,Cole158 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy man (1993:7) maintainedthatmodernsocieties had undergonea rationalization,which he describedas a shift away from primordialsocial organization,built chiefly on the inherited institutionof the family, and toward"purposivelyconstructedcorporateactors." Althoughit may be maintainedthatreligiousorganizationsin generalareorientedtoward goals, such as obtainingthe favor of the gods or salvationfor adherents,they differ in the extent to which they are purposivelyconstructed.The intentionaldecision to form a religious community, for example, is one of the characteristicsthat Warner(1994; 1998a; 1998b) has described as the "de facto congregationalism"of many immigrantreligious groupsin the United States.In the home countriesof many immigrants,accordingto Warner, religious groupingswere often based on place of residence or historicalheritage. One of the interesting implications of acknowledging intentional purposiveness as a dimension of collective as well as individual rationalityis the implication, found in the above-cited works of Warner,that complex, urbansocieties can be both more rationalon this dimensionand more religious thanruralsocieties. The conscious constructionof religious groups and organizationsfor sharedends can intensify commitmentand participation, a point thatis consistentwith the findingsof Finke and Stark(1988) andFinke, Guest, and Stark(1996). Aggregated social behavior can also possess degrees of systematic processes of optimizationof goal achievement,in the sense of meansexplicitly organizedaccordingto rules for the efficient realization of group outcomes. As Weber ([1922] 1978:987) observed, "bureaucracyis the means of transformingsocial action into rationallyorganizedaction." Coleman (1993), in the articlecited above, takes a Weberianview of the rationalizationof society as systematization.To the extent thatsocial action is guided towardspecified ends by well-defined and well-coordinatedsocial structures,we can considerthe action rationalized on the second dimension. The less a social group is organizedtowardachieving clearly identified goals, the less rationalit is. Traditionmay dominategroups,as well as individuals,to varyingdegrees. In addition, there are clear aggregate equivalents to non-calculatedemotional reactions by individuals.Scheff (1992:102)pointsout that"stockmarketpanics,famines,andwarsoften begin with impulsive,unaware,and/orout of controlbehavior."Less catastrophicoutcomes, such as unpredictablysky-rocketingdemandsfor scooters or furbiescan result from nonrationaltrendbehavior(Ormerod1998; Thaler 1991; 2000). Collectiverationalitymay also be a matterof consistencyamongends. Groupsandorganizations, as well as individuals,often have multiplegoals and these goals are frequentlyin conflict. This may be a particularlyimportantpoint in the sociology of religion because religious organizationsare generallyjustified on the basis of their pursuitof supernatural goals, but maintainingandpromotingorganizationstendsto committhem to seculargoals. Thus, Spinoza, in an epistolary debate on the spiritualauthorityof the Catholic Church, "readilygrantsthatit is singularlywell-organizedfor power and profit"(Israel2001:227). Starkand Bainbridge(1985) have seen this tendency towardthe secularization(the pull away from spiritualgoals) as a centralpartof the dynamicof religious organizations,since this form of secularizationdrivesthe formationof new, highly committedreligious groups. Multiple goals have also been a key issue in anotheruse of the word "secularization," in secularizationtheory,the view thatpluralisticsocieties, which incorporatenumerouscollective goals, tend to move away from religious belief. Berger (1969) in the past argued that modernizationtended to lead to general secularization.More recently,Berger (1997) 159 Review of Religious Research has abandonedthis view, acknowledgingthe continuingprevalenceof religion in modern societies. However, I think secularizationtheoristsmay have been correctin arguingthat thereare many aspects of modernsociety thatare inconsistentwith collective supernatural goals. The problemof secularizationtheorymay lie in the overly facile notion that growing inconsistency between secular and supernaturalgoals necessarily leads to the abandonmentof the latter.Instead, as I will arguein greaterdetail in looking at the religious marketplace,inconsistencycan introducean elementof irrationalityinto the marketof ideas thatcan actuallylead to proliferation. If one can use the word "rational"in similar ways when talking about individual and aggregatelevels, one must be carefulto avoid implying thatthese two levels arethe same. While aggregatephenomenaemerge from the decisions of individuals,the rationalchoices of individualsdo not necessarilyresultin the rationalorganizationof groupsor societies. Just as individualbehaviorcan be rationalin the shortrun and irrationalin the long run, behaviorcan be rationalfor individualsand irrationalfor groups,in the sense thatimmediate individualgoals may be at odds with sharedgoals. Frank(1999) has discussed how individualeffortsto maximizecompetitivenessin thejob marketcan shiftfundsfrominvestment to consumptionand diminishultimatecollective productivity. We can, in general,representthe relationshipbetween cumulativeindividualdecisions and collective outcomes as: Equation2. (al-E)/c(al) (al-E)/c(al) + (al-E)/c(al) ... + n E(a,E)/c(a,) n E(ajE)/c(a,) (i=l) (i=l) Ec n E(aE)/c(a) (i=l) whereEcrepresentsthe collective outcome, andthe ratiosrepresentthe rationalityvalue of each individualdecision.Now, it is possiblethatEccan have a high value (i.e., a high degree of desirabilityas a goal), even when the sum of the individual-levelratiosis low. Individuals can be socialized to sacrifice their own interestsfor the common good, for example. Further,widespreadacceptance of religious authorityon the basis of traditionalone can conceivably contributeto social order.It is also possible that the sum of individual-level ratios can be high, while Ec is low. This would be the case when the pursuitof individual goals is at variancewith a collective goal. Withregardto rationalchoice theoriesof religion, this means thatreligious choices can be collectively irrational(i.e., inconsistent with desired outcomes) even if they are individuallyrational,as well as individuallyirrational(or non-rational)andcollectively rational. Even if Christianitycontributedto the goals of individuals(as Stark 1996, maintains), we can still see it as destructiveto Roman society, a la EdwardGibbon.While many contemporaryhistorianswould be reluctantto see the RomanEmpire"falling"due to the triumphof Christianityandbarbarism,it is still plausibleto interpretthe spreadof Christianity as part of a ruling class withdrawalfrom the civic and familial obligations of public life (Brown 1988). Whetherwe see a particularreligious phenomenonas rationalor not, then, depends on whetherwe are seeing it in terms of individualor collective goals and on the associationbetween individualand collective goals in a specific situation. 160 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy Both aggregategoals and individualpursuitsof ends are consequences of the ways in which individualchoices affect and are affected by each other.The calculationsthat individuals make are based on the kinds of calculationsthey see othersmaking.Whateverthe supernaturalor secular goal realization value of Christianity,for Romans or for Roman society, as it became a more widespread religion and then the dominantreligion of the empire,people in the Thirdand FourthCenturyMediterraneanworld became more likely to choose Christianityas a solutionto theirsocial and spiritualproblems.In somewhatsimplified manner,this can be representedin the following terms: Equation3. (a,-E)/c(al) (al-E)/c(al) (al-E)/c(al) - n E(arE)/c(ai) (i-l) n a(a,E)/c(ao (i=l) E,Ec '... n (arE)/c(a;) (i=l) The rationalizationof society,in the sense meantby Coleman(1993), can be understood as the establishmentof a patternof correlationsamong individuals,so that the intentional decision-makingof individualsincreasesin value, resultingin an overallorientationtoward teleological behavior. Of course, the associations of individual decisions should not be understoodas a linear chain, but as a structuredpattern.Moreover,the increasein rationality simply meansthatindividualdecisions are moreclosely linkedto the outcome.It does not mean that the outcome is the best possible for the group. Coleman (1993) explicitly suggestedthatfavorableoutcomesmay sometimesbe the consequencesof primordialsocial organizations,characterizedby relatively low intentionality. Further,the amountof variationin individualgoal-seeking can be connectedto collective ends. Heckathorn(1993) has arguedthatwithin-groupheterogeneitycan contributeto collective action when the action's success is most problematic,such as when the temptation to free-ride is great or when the benefits of contributingare uncertain.Heckathorn maintains,however,thatgroupheterogeneityimpedes collective action when social cooperationis least problematic.If we take groupheterogeneityto mean variationin interests (goals), then we can see collective ends as relatedin varying ways to the standarddeviation in means-goalassociations,as well as to their sums. Thereis, then, yet anotherway in which individualgoal-seeking may result in collective goals: Equation4. (al-E)/c(al) (al E)/c(al) o~a~~~~~" ' n n E(a,E)/c(ai) E(a-E)/c(ai) (i=l) (i=l) (a,-E)/c(al) - Ec n E(a-E)/c(aj) (i=l) My discussion to this point suggests that the term "rationalchoice" is actually a much more complex concept thanis generallyrecognized.I have arguedthatusing the termin a 161 Review of Religious Research meaningfulfashionentailsrecognizingits multi-dimensionalcharacterandrecognizingthe fact thatrationalityis a matterof degree on all dimensions.In addition,I have maintained that rationalityis frequentlyused to describe both individual and aggregatephenomena. Further,I have attemptedto show the variablenatureof the relationshipbetween individual decisions with degrees of rationalityand aggregateoutcomes. This is a criticalpoint, since one of the goals of rationalchoice theoryis to explain how social aggregatesemerge from individualdecisions. However, the issue of how and why the cumulation,organization, and heterogeneity of individual decisions vary in their associations with collective outcomesremainsopen. In the following section,I will arguethatthe value of an economic model of religious behavior does not lie in a tautologous assumptionthat all religion is rational.Instead,I will arguethatan economic model can help us understandhow and why the systematicintentionalityof individualdecisions is relatedto collective outcomesin differing ways in differentsituations. RATIONALITY AND THE RELIGIOUS MARKET The Problem of Contexts The analysisof the concept of rationalitythatI have laid out above raises the following questionsaboutrationalchoice in religion:In what ways do individualreligious decisions vary in degrees of goal orientation,systematicmeans of achieving goals, and consistency among goals? How are variationsamong individualdecisions relatedto aggregatedifferences in explicit goal attainmentas a basis for groupexistence, the organizationof groups for the attainmentof ends, and to varietyamong goals? The first step to approachingthese difficult questions involves recognizing how aggregateentities function as both contexts and corporateactors and how individualactors operatewithin variouslevels of contexts. A numberof authorshave recognizedthe importanceof seeing the rationalityof behavior in termsof social contexts (Ellison andSherkat1995; Granovetter1985; 1993; Sherkat 1997; Sherkatand Wilson 1995). More generally, Victor Nee (1998) has seen "contextboundrationality"as a key characteristicof whathe termsthe new institutionalismin socican providea usefulway of approaching ology,andhis descriptionof thisnew institutionalism the problemof rationalityin individualand collective life. As Nee and Ingram(1998) see it, contexts are not imposed from withoutby a social structureexternalto the interactions of individuals,but arise from those interactionsby means of norms. One can createa frameworkfor thinkingabouteconomic behavior,and aboutreligions as economies, by adaptinga version of Nee and Ingram's schematizationof contextual embeddedness.I lay out this version of contextualeffects and actorsin Figure 1. Since I will be discussingthis below in termsof an economy,I referto the broadestconceptual level as the marketenvironment. This level describes the macroeconomic and macrosociologicalsetting of social behavior,within which both collective and individual actors exist. It includes such features as technological capacities, the tools available for social interaction;social and political structures,the institutionalframeworksfor social exchanges;and stability,the conditionsthat shape expectationsaboutthe future. The level of the marketenvironmentcan be illustratedby Stark's(1996) accountof the spreadof early Christianity.Withoutthe technology of literacy and withoutthe roads and Mediterraneanmaritimetransportation connectingthe partsof the RomanEmpire,it is difficult to see how widespreadconversioncould take place or how some standardof orthodoxy could be established.In Stark'saccount,moreover,the sociopolitical system of the 162 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy Figure 1. and Actors in the Production and Consumptionof Goods of Levels Contexts Conceptual Contexts Market Environment. Technological Features Large Scale Social/Political Structures Market Stability Formal Corporate Actors Informal Social Groups " Actors Individual Decisions Empireplayed a criticalpartin the rise of Christianity,since the existence of relativelyprivileged social classes in cities provided a source of potentialconverts.Expectationsabout the future,in the form of plagues and economic and political instability,also affectedreligious decisions. Withinthis setting, formally organizedcorporateactorstook various shapes and made and carriedout decisions. The Romanbureaucracycame into existence as an agent in the context of the Empireand enactedpersecutionsor maintainedperiodsof relativetolerance. The ChristianChurch,as an organization,graduallyemergedand became a partof life in the Mediterraneanworld. Formalorganizationsrespondedto a changing setting. The bureaucracyof the Empire was madepossible by its political and social hierarchyandby the interconnectionsof communicationand transformation.This bureaucracymay have been re-shapedin the era of Diocletian (245-313 C.E.) as a responseto changes in the economic and political environment of the Empire(Barnes1982;Williams, 1985). However,the functioningof the bureaucracy and otherpolitical structuresalso resultedfrom the interconnectionsof individuals, from the kinds of personal and family ties that Coleman (1993) referredto in the article discussed above. 163 Review of Religious Research Marketenvironmentsprovidecontextsfor formalorganizationsand those environments areshapedby the actionsof formalorganizations.Similarly,organizationsarebothcontexts for informalassociations of individualsand result from those informalassociations. The structuresof the ChristianChurchemergedfrom contactsamong groupsof Christians,but these structuresalso shapedinformalgroupconnections.It will be noted thatI have drawn an arrow,also, frommarketenvironmentsto informalgroups.Interpersonalassociations,as well as formalorganizations,dependon such generalenvironmentalfactorsas existingtechnologies of communication,sociopoliticalstructures,and influences on expectations. Finally,informalassociationsbothprovidecontextsfor the decisions of individualsand are derived from those decisions. Informalgroups also mediate all other levels of influences on individual decisions. If individuals perceive instability in an environment,for example, they do so because of the informationthey receive from their social contacts. Social class shapes decisions as a result of the experiences that people in differentsocial classes have with otherhumanbeings. Organizationsinfluenceindividualsby shapinginteractions.When individualsmake decisions, the information,tastes, and understandingthat make these decisions possible are all producedby specific social circumstances.Both formal organizationsand informal groups have dual characters.They are collective actors becausethey have goals andmeansof achievinggoals thatariseout of individualdecisions, and they are contexts because they provide settings for action. This brief discussion has attemptedto provide some basis for an examinationof individual and collective choices of action and for the contextualinfluences on those choices, while the precedingsections describedthe natureof rationalityin decision-making.Now, in orderto investigatehow contextuallyshapeddecisions in religionmay be seen as rational choices, I will turnto a more explicit descriptionof how religion may be seen as economic behavior. Religious Contextsand Actors as Economies: Supply and Demand Structures Sherkatand Ellison (1999) have observedthattheoristsof religion can be divided into those who approachthe religiousmarketplacefromthe supplyside andthose who approach it fromthe demandside.Takinga supplysideperspective,some of theforemostrationalchoice theoristsof religionhave arguedthatthe deregulationof religionincreasesreligiousactivity by increasingthe supply of religious goods (lannacone 1991, 1992; lannacone,Finke, and Stark 1996). In the words of Starkand Finke (2000:193), "religiousdemandis very stable A over time and ... religiouschangeis largelythe productof supply-sidetransformations." to of wide of can demands a plurality religiousinstitutions,by providing range choices, respond for supernatural goods in an efficient andmulti-facetedmanner.This supplyside view contrastswith the formulationsuggestedbut laterabandonedby PeterBerger,who maintained that competitionunderminedreligions as sources of meaningby challenginginstitutional claims to monopolisticcertainty.When therearemanyclaims to the truth,he argued(Berger 1968; 1969), no single claim can be convincingand all are weakened. The supply-sidevs. demand-sidedebateis a centralone in economicsin general,as well as in the economics of religion. Perhapsthe century's most influential economist, John MaynardKeynes (1936) advocatedan economic policy centeredaroundconsumerdemand as the drivingforce.Along similarlines, JohnKennethGalbraith(1958) observedthattechniques of productionin the economies of the West had outstrippeddistribution,resulting 164 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy in an unprecedentedquantityof goods availablefor consumption,even thoughthe buying power of individualsmight lag far behind this productivecapacity. One can begin to think about the interconnectionsof supply and demandby recognizing thatdemandis a matterof makingchoices. Consumerswith finite resourcesfor acquiring goods choose among the goods available to them. This suggests that a purely supply side approachto religiousactivitiesreallycannotalso be a rationalchoice approachbecause the formerwould consideronly the availabilityof goods and not how people make choices among them. In addition,an economic model of religion that looks only at supply tends to presenta top-down perspective, in which individuals are chiefly passive recipients of collectively createdgoods. This not only makesit difficultto examinehow individualsmaketheirchoices, it also drawsattentionaway from a centralgoal of rationalchoice theory:the explanation of how individualactions and decisions yield social aggregates. Empirically,it would be hardto reconcile a constantdistributionof religious demand with such occurrencesas the suddenpopularityin "bornagain"Christianityin the 1970s and 1980s (Warner1993). Theoretically,demandcannot be stable if many of the predictors of demandareunstable.Choice in religiousactivityand expressionis widely acknowledged to be affectedby social class ( Demerath1965; Roof andMcKinney 1987; Starkand Glock 1968), social mobility (Alston 1971; Lauer 1975; Nelsen and Snizek 1976 ), racial or ethnic minority status (Argyle and Beit-Hallahmi. 1975; Ellison and Sherkat 1995 ), socializationby family andpeers (SherkatandWilson 1995) andindividuallife events (Ellison 1991; Stark1996; Wallace 1975). None of these influencesaredistributedin a constant fashion across history or geography. An account of religion as an economy, then, can not simply assume that choices will automaticallyfollow goods that are somehow made available. Instead, such an account must explainhow individualchoices both respondto contextsand createcontexts.One can begin to do this by consideringhow individualsdecide what their wants are and how they will satisfy these wants. If we returnto Equation1, individualsdo act teleologically.They seek to achieve goals and, generally,they seek to achieve these goals as efficiently as possible by choosing the best possible means. The choice of the means is constrained,though,by both information and socialization (Sherkatand Wilson 1995; Sherkat1998). Both informationand socialization are productsof social contacts. Since social contactsresult from the influences of individualson one anotherthereis continualreciprocitybetweenindividualdecisions about goals and the means of achieving goals and social constraints. The social constraintsthat groups place on individualsmay vary.A primarysource of variationin social constraintsis participationin multiple groups.It is a standardsociological axiom thatpluralisticsocieties presentindividualswith varied, sometimes contradictory ends and that individualsmust choose among those ends. The more an individualis confrontedwith multiple groups,the less action is a matterof acceptanceof given means and goals and the more action is a matterof conscious choice and calculation.Individual choices, again, vary in rationality. The fact that a multiplicity of ends tends to increase the systematic and teleological character of social action means that there is a curious relation between the first two dimensions of rationality (goal-orientation and systematic means of achievement) and the third (consistency of goals). As possible goals increase in numberand in varia165 Review of Religious Research tion, individuals are faced with choosing among ends and with rationalizing apparent inconsistencies. Choosing a desiredproduct(a goal) often entailschoosing a social group.Even material products,such as homes or automobiles,often establish group membership.For social goods, such as clubs or churches,groupmembershipis generallyimplicitin the goods themselves. Becoming or remaininga Buddhist or a Mormonusually means associating with Buddhistsor Mormons.Groupmembership,in turn,reinforcesthe kinds of goods that are considereddesirableand helps to addressthe problemof inconsistencyraisedby a pluralistic society. SouthernBaptistsfaced with choosing between a belief in divine creationand acceptanceof Darwinianevolutionmay find the problemat least partlyresolvedby the resolute faith of fellow church-goers. Groupsreinforcereligious choices because religious goods, like virtuallyall products, are createdby collaboration.People create religious goods; such as beliefs, services, and practices;together.In this process of collaboration,they intensify the belief thatthe things they createareto be valued and desiredandthey help to re-defineuniversalhumandesires in termsof theirproducts.Religious preferencesare shapedand intensifiedthroughsocial contactsin the processof consumptionof religiousgoods (Sherkat1997).All humanbeings may well have desiresfor rewardsthatcannotbe suppliedby naturalisticmeans (Starkand Bainbridge1985). However,it is only throughsocial participationin a particularcommunity of production and consumption that these become defined as desires for Christian kerygma,BuddhistNirvana,or Muslim paradise. As communitiesof religious productioncontinue in existence, they tend to be institutionalized.Norms become more explicitly formalizedas rules and social positions become offices. This is a tendencyin any group,but is especially markedwhen the groupcomes to include a largernumberof people than can maintainface-to-face contact.As the production of social goods increasesandpersonalinteractionsfeed demandfor those goods, small firms become formalcorporateactorsand numbersof small firms mayjoin togetherwithin an emerging organizationalframework.Thus, after the death of the GautamaBuddha, the Buddhist sangha began to take shape among groups of Indian monks and Buddhist councils began to compose the Buddhistscripturesandto attemptto establishunified doctrines (Reat 1995; Skilton 1997). The expansionand integrationof corporateactorsis frequentlyreferredto as rationalization. J.P.Morganand his business associates, for example, tendedto see themselves as rationalizingAmericanbusinessby bringingdiversegroupswith diversegoals into an integratedcorporatestructure(Strouse 1999). This movement towardestablishingconsistency through the extension of formal corporatepower may be seen as a general trend of businesshistoryin the United Statesthroughoutthe late nineteenthandearlytwentiethcenturies (Chandler1970; Cochran1962; Sklar 1988). In religious history,we can see similar movements towardrationalization.The ThirdBuddhistCouncil, convened at Pataliputra about250 B.C.E. underthe EmperorAsoka, attemptedto rationalizeBuddhisminto a single corporateform (Reat 1995; Skilton 1997). The Council of Nicea, which openedin 325 C.E. underAsoka'sRomancounterpart, Constantine,was partof an ongoing seriesof efforts to establisha consistent,universalisticform of Christianity(Pelikan 1971). Among religious firms as well as business firms, then, efforts at rationalizationtend to reducevariationin goal-seekingamongandwithingroups.As variationwithingroupsorganized into formal corporatestructuresdecreases (that is, as the value of Equation4 goes 166 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy down for groups in corporatestructures),competition among the formal structuresmay decreasein intensityor the formalstructuresmay combinethroughmergers.In eithercase, thereis a tendencytowardmonopolization.The post-WorldWarII homogenizationof American religion that Sherkat(2001:1485) refers to as "the heyday of the liberal Protestant mainline"can be seen as trend towardreligious corporatizationand standardizationthat mirroredsimilartrendsin the society at large. Monopolies or quasi-monopoliesmay be helpful for the productionof a limited range of existing types of commodities.Economies of scale can enable a large automobilemanufacturerto produceautomobilesor for a churchto producemasses. But therearealso problems with this kind of mass production.First, as Coleman (1993) observed in the article discussed above, some kinds of productiveactivities are done betterby small groups,precisely because of the influence that the goal-seeking behaviorof individualshas on other individuals.Second, innovationis often more difficult for rigid, highly formalized,rationalized corporateentities thanit is for people workingin the flexibility of informalgroups. Therefore,wheneverthereis a demandfor productsthatrequirethe intensivecollaboration of small groups,small firms, with an emphasison groupinteractionsratherthanon formal organizationalstructure,tend to out-competethe largerfirms. One can see two expressionsof rationalityin this consolidationvs. competitionmodel. On the one hand,movementtowardmonopolizationcreatesgreateruniformityof goals and systematicmeans of achieving goals. On the otherhand, this very uniformityand systematizationtends to limit the element of choice on the partof individual consumers.While individualchoices, made in the context of groups,lead to the creationof formalcorporate actors,aggregaterationalizationcan ultimatelyconstrainthe choices of individuals.There is, then, a continualtension between the collective and individuallevels. This patternfits ratherneatly with Starkand Bainbridge's(1985) cycle of secularization, revival, and religious innovation.Again, however, I do not thinkthat we can assume stable demandfor religious goods, any more than we can for otherkinds of goods, given the recognized variationin influences on demand.Most of those influences are mattersof what I have termedthe "marketenvironment."Determinantsof religious mobility in the United States, for example, have shifted in importanceover time with succeeding historical cohorts (Sherkat2001). Operatingwithin social groups,individualsdevelop and communicateto one anotherdemandsfor religiousgoods as a resultof the commonexperiences of those individuals.lannaccone(1988) has proposedin a formalmodel thatsectarianreligions, with norms at odds with those of the largersociety, tend to appealto those with relatively low secularopportunities.When secularopportunitiesarediminishingor perceived to be low, one may expect pluralisticchallenges to dominantreligions to take the form of sectarianism.If, however,opportunitiesarerapidlychanging,this can createa differentsort of demand,yielding differentsortsof religious suppliers.If it is truethatcults appealto the relatively educated and privileged (Stark and Finke 2000), the demand for the kinds of goods producedby cults will increasein times of economic expansionand social optimism and producersof cult goods will flourishaccordingly. In additionto economic fluctuations,political structuresare aspects of the marketenvironmentthat influence supply and demandfor religious goods throughformal corporate actorsandthroughsocial groups.Centralizedor centralizingpolitical structuresoften favor the developmentof monopolies, whetherof economic or religious goods. The de-regulation of firms, though,not only increasessuppliesof goods, it also increasesdemand.When 167 Review of Religious Research formal corporateactorsand the informalgroupswithin them compete for customers,they createcustomersthroughsalesmanship.Pluralism,then,can stimulateconsumerism,a widespreaddesire for the abundanceof goods that re-orients the goals of individuals within social groups. CONCLUSION Rationalchoice theories of religion have fallen short of providingan adequatedefinition of rationality.A complex and multi-dimensionalconcept has been presentedas a relativelysimplematterof goal-seekingbehavior.Nevertheless,the economicmodelof religious behaviorproposedby rationalchoice theoristsis an extremelyuseful one and considering the kinds and degrees of rationalityinvolved in religious behaviorcan help us understand how individualchoices create and respondto collective phenomena. I have arguedthatrationalityshouldbe seen as a matterof goal-orientation,systematic means of goal attainment,andconsistencyamonggoals. These arecharacteristicsthatexist to differentdegreesin humanactivities,not qualitiesthatareeitherpresentor absent.Moreover, individualdecision making,characterizedby degrees of rationality,resultsin collective goal orientations, systematic means of collective goal attainment,and consistency among collective goals. The ways in which the dimensions of individual rationalityare related to each other and the ways in which individualrationalityis relatedto collective processes and outcomes depend on specific circumstances.I have arguedthat these circumstancescan be understoodin termsof a market,with supply and demandmediatedby conceptuallevels. While this supportsthe economic model of rationalchoice theoristsof religion, it revises this model by placing more emphasison the role of demand,as well as by offering a schematizationof how a multi-dimensionalrationalitymight functionat levels of contexts and actors. Address Correspondenceto: Carl L. BankstonIII, Departmentof Sociology, 220 Newcomb Hall, TulaneUniversity,New Orleans,LA 70118. [email protected] REFERENCES Ainslie, George. 1975. "Specious Reward:A BehavioralTheory of Impulsiveness and Impulse Control."Psychological Bulletin 82: 463-496. Alston, Jon P. 1971. "ReligiousMobility and Socioeconomic Status."Sociological Analysis 32:140-48. Argyle, Micheal and BenjaminBeit-Hallahmi 1975. The Social Psychology of Religion. London:Routledge & Kegan Paul. Barnes,TimothyD. 1982. TheNew Empireof Diocletian and Constantine.Cambridge,Mass.: HarvardUniversity Press. Becker, GaryS. 1975. Human Capital:A Theoreticaland EmpiricalAnalysis, with Special Referenceto Education. New York:ColumbiaUniversityPress. 1976. The EconomicApproachto HumanBehavior. Chicago:Universityof Chicago Press. 1996. Accountingfor Tastes.Cambridge,Mass.: HarvardUniversityPress. Berger,PeterL. 1968. "A Bleak Outlookis Seen for Religion."New YorkTimes,April 25, 3. 1969. The Sacred Canopy:Elementsof a Sociological Theoryof Religion. New York:Doubleday. 1997. "EpistemologicalModesty:An Interviewwith PeterBerger."ChristianCentury114 (October29):972975,978. Bohman,James. 1992. "TheLimits of RationalChoice Explanation."In JamesS. ColemanandThomasJ. Fararo (eds.), Rational Choice Theory:Advocacyand Critique,pp. 207-228. NewburyPark,Ca.: Sage Publications. Boudon,Raymond.1998. "Limitationsof RationalChoice Theory."AmericanJournalof Sociology 104:817-828. 168 Rationality,Choice, and the Religious Economy Brown,PeterR.L.1988. TheBody and Society:Men, Women,and SexualRenunciationin Early Christianity.New York:ColumbiaUniversity Press. Chandler,Alfred D. 1970. Scale & Scope: The Dynamics of IndustrialCapitalism.Cambridge,Mass.: Belknap Press of HarvardUniversityPress. Cochran,Thomas 1962. TheAmericanBusiness System,1900-1955. New York:Harper& Row. Coleman, James S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory.Cambridge,MA: The Belknap Press of HarvardUniversity Press. 1993. "The Rational Reconstruction of Society." American Sociological Review 58: 1-15. In JamesS. ColemanandThomasJ. Fararo(eds.), Coleman,JamesS. andThomasJ. Fararo.1992. "Introduction." Rational Choice Theory:Advocacyand Critique,pp. ix-xxii. Newbury Park,Ca.: Sage Publications. Demerath,N. J. 1965. Social Class in AmericanProtestantism.New York:RandMcNally. De Palma,Andre, GordonM. Myers, and YorgosY. Papageorgiou.1994. "RationalChoice under an Imperfect Ability to Choose."AmericanEconomic Review 84:419-40. Ellison, ChristopherG. 1991. "ReligiousInvolvementand SubjectiveWell-Being."Journalof Health and Social Behavior 32:80-99. Ellison, ChristopherG., and DarrenE. Sherkat. 1995. "The "Semi-InvoluntaryInstitution"Revisted:Regional Variationsin ChurchParticipationamong Black Americans."Social Forces 73: 1415-1437. Finke, Roger and Rodney Stark. 1988. "Religious Economies and Sacred Canopies:Religious Mobilization in AmericanCities, 1906."AmericanSociological Review 53-41-49. Finke, Roger,Avery M. Guest, and Rodney Stark. 1996. "MobilizingLocal Religious Markets:Religious Pluralism in the EmpireState, 1855-1865."AmericanSociological Review 61-203-218. Frank,RobertH. 1999. LuxuryFever: WhyMoney Fails to Satisfy in an Era of Excess. New York:Free Press. Galbraith,John K. 1958. TheAffluentSociety. Boston: HoughtonMifflin. Granovetter,Mark. 1985. "EconomicAction and Social Structure:The Problemof Embeddedness."American Journal of Sociology 91:481-510. 1993. "TheNatureof Economic Relationships."In RichardSwedberg(ed.), Explorationsin Economic Sociology, pp. 3-41 Russell Sage Foundation. Heath,Anthony. 1976. Rational Choice and Social Exchange.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress Hechter,Michael and Satoshi Kanazawa.1997. "Sociological RationalChoice Theory."AnnualReview of Sociology 23: 191-214. Heckathorn,Douglas D. 1993. "CollectiveAction and GroupHeterogeneity:VoluntaryProvisionVersusSelective Incentives."AmericanSociological Review 58:329-350. Hedstr6m,Peter. 1993. "Introductionto this Special Issue on RationalChoice Theory."Acta Sociologica 36:167. Iannaccone,LaurenceR 1988. "A FormalModel of Churchand Sect."AmericanJournal of Sociology 94:S241S268. 1991. "The Consequences of Religious MarketRegulation:Adam Smith and the Economics of Religion." Rationalityand Society 3:156-77. 1992. "ReligiousMarketsand the Economics of Religion." Social Compass39: 123-131. Iannacone,LaurenceR., RogerFinke,andRodneyStark.1996. "DeregulatingReligion:The Economicsof Church and State."EconomicInquiry35:350-64. Israel, Jonathan.2001. Radical Enlightenment:Philosophy and the Making of Modernity,1650-1750. Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress. Keynes, JohnMaynard.1936. TheGeneralTheoryof Employment,Interest,and Money.London:MacMillanand Co. Lauer,RobertH. 1975. "Occupationaland Religious Mobility in a Small City."Sociological Quarterly16:38092. Nee, Victor. 1998. "Sourcesof the New Institutionalism."In Victor Nee and Mary C. Brinton (eds.), The New Institutionalismin Sociology, pp. 1-16. New York:Russell Sage Foundation. Nee, Victor and Paul Ingram. 1998. Embeddednessand Beyond: Institutions,Exchange, and Social Structure." Pp. 19-45 in The New Institutionalismin Sociology, edited by Mary C. Brintonand Victor Nee. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Nelsen, HartM., andWilliamE. Snizek 1976. "MusicalPews: RuralandUrbanModels of Occupationaland Religious Mobility."Sociology and Social Research 60:279-89. Ormerod,Paul. 1998. ButterflyEconomics:A New GeneralTheoryof Social and EconomicBehavior.New York: PantheonBooks 169 Review of Religious Research Parsons,Talcott.1949. TheStructureof SocialAction:A Studyin Social Theorywith Special Referenceto a Group of RecentEuropeanWriters.Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press. Pelikan,JaroslavJ. 1971. The ChristianTradition:A History of the Developmentof Doctrine. Chicago:University of Chicago Press. Piker,Steven. 1972. "TheProblemof Consistencyin Thai Religion."Journalfor the ScientificStudyof Religion 11:211-229. Reat, Noble R. 1995. Buddhism:A History. Fremont,Ca.:Asian HumanitiesPress. Roof, Wade C. and William C. McKinney. 1987. AmericanMainline Religion: Its ChangingShape and Future. RutgersUniversityPress. Scheff, ThomasJ. 1992. "Rationalityand Emotion:Homage to NorbertElias."In JamesS. ColemanandThomas J. Fararo(eds.), Rational Choice Theory:Advocacy and Critique, pp. 101-119. Newbury Park, Ca.: Sage Publications. Sherkat,DarrenE. 1997. "EmbeddingReligious Choices: IntegratingPreferencesand Social Constraintsinto RationalChoice Theories of Religious Behavior."In LawrenceA. Young (ed.), Rational Choice Theoryand Religion: Summaryand Assessment,pp. 65-85. New York:Routledge. 1998. "Countercultureor Continuity?CompetingInfluences on Baby Boomers' Religious Orientationsand Participation."Social Forces 76:1087-1115. 2001. "Trackingthe Restructuringof AmericanReligion:ReligiousAffiliationandPatternsof ReligiousMobility, 1973-1998."Social Forces 79:1459-1493. Sherkat,DarrenE. and ChristopherG. Ellison. 1999. "RecentDevelopments and CurrentControversiesin the Sociology of Religion."AnnualReview of Sociology 25: 363-94. Sherkat,DarrenE., and JohnWilson. 1995. "Preferences,Constraints,and Choices in Religious Markets:An Examinationof Religious Switching andApostasy."Social Forces 73: 993-1026. Simon, HerbertA. 1957. Models of Man: Social and Rational. New York:JohnWiley & Sons. Skilton,Andrew.1997.A Concise History of Buddhism.Trumbull,CT:Weatherhill.York:Praeger. Sklar,Martin.1988.The CorporateReconstructionof AmericanCapitalism,1890-1916. New York:Cambridge UniversityPress. Spickard,JamesV. 1998. "RethinkingReligious Social Action: Whatis 'Rational'About Rational-ChoiceTheory?"Sociology of Religion 59: 99-115. Stark,Rodney. 1996. The Rise of Christianity:A Sociologist ReconsidersHistory. Princeton:PrincetonUniversity Press. Stark,Rodney and William S. Bainbridge.1985. The Futureof Religion: Secularization,Revival, and Cult Formation. Berkeley:Universityof CaliforniaPress. 1987. A Theoryof Religion. New Brunswick,N.J.: RutgersUniversityPress. Stark,Rodney and Roger Finke. 2000. Acts of Faith: Explainingthe HumanSide of Religion. Berkeley:University of CaliforniaPress. Stark,Rodney, and CharlesGlock. 1968. AmericanPiety: The Nature of Religious Commitment.University of CaliforniaPress. Strouse,Jean. 1999. Morgan:AmericanFinancier. New York:RandomHouse. Thaler,Richard.1991. Quasi-RationalEconomics.New York:Russell Sage Foundation. 2000. "FromHomo Economicusto Homo Sapiens."Journal of EconomicPerspectives 14:133-41. Wallace,RuthA. 1975. "A Model of Religious Affiliation."Journalfor the Scientific Studyof Religion 13:345355. Warner,R. Stephen. 1993. "Workin Progresstowarda New Paradigmfor the Sociological Study of Religion in the United States."AmericanJournal of Sociology 98:1044-93. 1994. "ThePlace of the Congregationin theAmericanReligious Configuration."In JamesP.Windand James W. Lewis (eds.), American Congregations,vol. 2, New Perspectives in the Studyof Congregations,pp. 54-99. Chicago:Universityof Chicago Press. 1998a "ApproachingReligious Diversity:Barriers,Byways, and Beginnings."Sociology of Religion 59:193215. 1998b. "Introduction:Immigrationand Religious Communitiesin the United States."In R. S. Warnerand J. G. Wittner(eds.), Gatheringsin Diaspora: Religious Communitiesand the New Immigration,pp. 3-34. Philadelphia,PA:TempleUniversityPress. Weber,Max. [1922] 1978. Economyand Society:An Outlineof InterpretiveSociology. Editedby GuentherRoth and Claus Wittich.Berkeley:University of CaliforniaPress. 170 Rationality, Choice, and the Religious Economy Wrong, Dennis. 1961. "The Oversocialized Conception of Man in Modern Sociology." AmericanSociological Review 26:183-193. Williams, Rhys H. 2000. "Review of Rational Choice Theoryand Religion, edited by LawrenceA Young."Sociology of Religion 61:105-106. Williams, Stephen. 1985. Diocletian and the RomanRecovery.London:B.T. Batsford. Zafirovsky,Milan. 1999. "Unificationof Sociological Theory by the RationalChoice Method: Conceiving the Relationshipbetween Economics and Sociology." Sociology 33: 495-513. 171
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz