Carl Schmitt's Political Theory of Representation Author(s): Duncan Kelly Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 65, No. 1 (Jan., 2004), pp. 113-134 Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3654285 Accessed: 04/12/2008 09:42 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upenn. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org Carl Schmitt's Political of Theory Representation Duncan Kelly I. Political Representation "Representation means the making present of something that is nevertheless not literally present."' This definition, provided by Hanna Pitkin in her celebrated book on the subject, contrasts strongly with most modem discussions of political representation which regularly delimit their focus to technical questions of election and accountability.2 Even theorists who see in representative government the classical virtues of a necessarily "chastened" (public) authority rely on impoverished notions of political representation in the sense of the definition outlined above.3 As Pitkin herself suggested, political representation explores the way in which "the people (or a constituency) are present in governmental action, even though they do not literally act for themselves."4 This paper examines Carl Schmitt's "solution" to this quandary of political representation, which suggests that representation can bring about the political unity of the state, but only if the state itself is properly "represented" by the figure or person of the sovereign.5 Hanna Pitkin, The Concept of Representation (Berkeley, 1967), 144. 2 Cf. BernardManin, Adam Przeworski and Susan Stokes (eds.), Democracy, Accountability and Representation(Cambridge,1999); Albert Weale, "Representation,Individualism and Collectivism,"Ethics, 91 (1981), 457-65; David Plotke, "Representationis Democracy," Constellations,4 (1999), 19-34. 3 George Kateb, The Inner Ocean (Ithaca, 1992), 36-56; cf. Nadia Urbinati, "Representation as Advocacy," Political Theory,28 (2000), 758-86. 4 Pitkin, Concept of Representation,221f; cf. EdmundBurke, "Speech to the Electors of Bristol"(1774), OnEmpire,Libertyand Reform,ed. David Bromwich(New Haven, 2000), 54f. 5 Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre(Berlin, [1928] 19938), 90; Carl Schmitt, The Conceptof the Political [1932 ed.], trans. George Schwab (Chicago, [1927] 1996), 19. 113 Copyright2004 by Journalof the Historyof Ideas,Inc. 114 Duncan Kelly In assessing and explaining the centrality of representation to Schmitt's political thought-an area often excluded from discussion6-I focus upon his attempted reconciliation of a starkly "personalist" and then Hobbesian account of representation that would justify support for the Reichsprasident under the Weimar Republic, with insights drawn from the constitutional republicanism of the Abbe Sieyes that placed the constituent power of the people at the basis of representative democracy. The argument develops and modifies Bockenfdrde's hypothesis, that Schmitt's well-known concept of the political-first presented in a lecture of 1927-provides the "key" to understanding his more substantial constitutional theory, Verfassungslehre, published the following year.7 Instead, Schmitt's concept of representation provides the key with which to understand his densely structured constitutional argumentation.8 Therefore, after outlining the early theological and personalist roots of Schmitt's account of representation in order to show his long-standing concern with the issue, the central arguments of Sieyes and Hobbes concerning representation are next outlined, and their impact on Schmitt's political and constitutional theory discussed.9 Such a structure places in sharp relief the political implications of his ideological appropriation of the language of modern representative democracy in order to justify support for the presidential leader. II. Capitalism, Rationality, and Representation: The Figure of the Representative In his 1923 essay "Roman Catholicism and Political Form," Schmitt claimed that the technical-economic rationality of moder capitalism and its dominant political expression, liberalism, stood at odds with the truly political power of 6 But see Renato Cristi, Carl Schmitt and AuthoritarianLiberalism (Cardiff, 1998), 81, 10ff, 116-25, 133, 135f; John P. McCormick, Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism (Cambridge, 1997), esp. ch. 4; PasqualePasquino,"PouvoirConstituantbei Sieyes und Schmitt,"in H. Quaritsch(ed.), ComplexioOppositorum(Berlin, 1985), 371-85; Stefan Breuer,"Nationalstaat und Pouvoir Constituant bei Schmitt und Sieyes," Archiv fur Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 70 (1984), 495-517. In the text, Sieyes is spelled without an accent, following the notes on orthographyoutlined by A. Mathiez, "L'orthographedu nom Sieyes," Annales historiquesde la RevolutionFrancaise, 2 (1925), 487. 7 Erst-Wolfgang Bockenf6rde,"TheConceptof the Political:A Key to UnderstandingCarl Schmitt's ConstitutionalTheory" (1986), in D. Dyzenhaus (ed.), Law as Politics (Durham, 1998), 37-55. 8Ibid., 49ff; cf. Ellen Kennedy,"Hostisnot Inimicus:Towardsa Theoryof the Public in the Workof CarlSchmitt,"CanadianJournal ofLaw and Jurisprudence,10 (1997), 35-47, esp. 4447 9 Quentin Skinner, "Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State,"Journal of Political Philosophy, 7 (1999), 1-29; David Runciman, "What Kind of Person is Hobbes's State? A Reply to Skinner,"Journal of Political Philosophy, 8 (2000), 268-78, are excellent recent discussions of this difficult aspect of Hobbes's thought. Carl Schmitt 115 the CatholicChurch.'0Schmittwas concernedto illuminatethe particularly"representative"characterof the Catholic Churchas a complexio oppositorum,in contradistinctionto its typicalappearanceas the unworldly"other"to an ascetic andindustriousProtestantism,so as to counterthe "anti-Romantemperthathas nourishedthe struggleagainstpopery,Jesuitismand clericalismwith a host of religiousandpoliticalforces,thathas impelledEuropeanhistoryfor centuries."" Even the "parliamentaryand democraticnineteenthcentury"was an era where Catholicismwas definedas "nothingmorethana limitlessopportunism." It was Schmitt'scontention,however,thatthis missed the fundamentalpoint of such a complex of opposites, which was that the "formalcharacterof Roman Catholicismis based on the strictrealisationof the principleof representation. In its particularitythis becomes most clear in its antithesisto the economictechnicalthinkingdominanttoday."12Schmittcontendedthat somethingpeculiar to Catholicrepresentationallowed it to "makepresent"the true essence of it. Moreover,because"theidea of representationis somethingby "representing" so completelygovernedby conceptionsof personalauthoritythatthe representative as well as the personrepresentedmust maintaina personaldignity-it is not a materialistconcept.To representin an eminentsense can only be done by a person ... an authoritativeperson or an idea which, if represented,also becomes personified.""3 Thus, althoughthe Catholic Churchhad cordialrelationshipswith a wide rangeof particularadministrations,andthoughit is even superficiallyattractive to "irrationalist" thought,it possesses its own "logic."It "is based on a particular mode of thinking whose method of proof is a specific juridical logic and whose focus of interestis the normativeguidanceof humansocial life."14The CatholicChurchhas its own rationality,one at odds not with particularregimes, but ratherwith the overwhelmingeconomic rationalityof moderncapitalism.'5 Indeed,"in sharpcontrastto this absoluteeconomic materiality,Catholicismis eminentlypolitical."'6In an argumentthat bore heavily on his wider thinking about the natureof the law and the limits to contemporarylegal formalism, Schmitteven suggested thatthe Churchwas the "trueheir of Romanjurispru- 10 Gary L. Ulmen, "Introduction,"Carl Schmitt, Roman Catholicismand Political Form [rev. 1925 ed.], trans. G. L. Ulmen (Westport, Conn., [1923] 1996), xix; cf. Gary Ulmen, "Politische theologie und Politische Okonomie,"in Quaritsch(ed.), Complexio Oppositorum, 350-60. " Schmitt,Roman Catholicism,3. 12 Ibid., 4, 8. Ibid., 21, 17. 14 Schmitt, Roman Catholicism, 12. 13 15Ibid., 24; cf. Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 41-42, n. 17. 16 Schmitt,Roman Catholicism, 16. 116 Duncan Kelly dence,"concernedwith a higherpurposethansimply the maintenanceof legality.17 The historicaldevelopmentof liberalism,thoughtSchmitt,showed an unawareness of the personalistcharacterof political representation.18 Schmitt's of that therefore the earlyconception representation suggested specific rationality of the CatholicChurch,as a complexiooppositorum,"restson the absolute realisationof authority"buttressedby a "powerto assumethis or any otherform only because it has the power of representation."'9 Additionally,this power of finds its locus in a form of representation particular personalauthority,an authoritythatimplies connotationsof dignity andvalue. His accountclearly links backto earliertheoriesof representationandthe "twobodies"of the sovereign,20 which underpinnedhis argumentthat "all significant concepts of the modern theoryof the stateare secularizedtheological concepts."21 Correlatively,Schmittsuggestedthat such substantiveor "eminent"representation"canonly proceedin the public sphere,"the spherewherethe locus of sovereignty lies.22The suggestion also built on his belief that the currentpredominance of technical-economic capitalist thinking was premised upon a "privatization"of individualaction.The first instanceof this privatizationconcernedindividualreligiousbelief. ForSchmitt,the interdependenceof liberalism andthe moder state-born out of the Reformationand disputesover religious toleration-corresponds with the rise of somethingapproachingthe theory of Schmittcoun"possessiveindividualism"latermade famousby MacPherson.23 teredthat"thejuridicalfoundationof the CatholicChurchin the public sphere, contrastedwith liberalism'sfoundationon the privatesphere."24 Furthermore, this was elaboratedon in his suggestion that it was Protestantismand early variantsof Calvinist resistance theory, which had in fact broughtabout such developments,robbingpolitics of its properlyrepresentativecharacter: 17 Schmitt, Roman Catholicism, 18. See also Carl Schmitt, Legalitdt und Legitimitit (1932), repr.in his VerfassungsrechtlicheAufsdtzeaus den Jahren 1924-1954 (Berlin, 19583), 263-350. 18Ibid. See also Carl Schmitt,"TheAge of Neutralizationsand Depoloticizations"[1929], trans.J. P. McCormickand M. Konzett, Telos, 96 (1993), 131: "The anti-religionoftechnicity has been put into practice on Russian soil." See also 131-35, for a precis of his general theory of history. 19See Schmitt,Roman Catholicism, 18-19; Verfassungslehre,208-12. See also Kennedy, "Hostis not Inimicus,"passim. 20ErnstKantorowicz,TheKing's Two Bodies (Princeton[1957], 1997), 192f, 207-32; cf. Francis Oakley, "NaturalLaw, the CorpusMysticum,and Consent in ConciliarThought from John of Paris to MatthiasUgonis," Speculum(1981), 786-810. 21 Carl Schmitt,Political Theology(1932 ed.), trans.George Schwab (Cambridge,Mass., [1922] 1985), 37. Emphasis added. 22 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,208. 23 See James Tully, "Afterthe MacPhersonthesis," in his Approachesto Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts(Cambridge,1993), 71-95. 24 Schmitt, Roman Catholicism,29. CarlSchmitt 117 The Churchcommandsrecognitionas the Brideof Christ[thepope was it representsChristreigning,rulingandconquering.Its claim its Vicar25]; to prestigeandhonorrests on the eminentidea of representation.26 As such, McCormickobserves,Weber'sargument"foreshadowsthe Schmittian thesis,"where"Catholicismhas to the presentday lookedupon Calvinismas its real opponent."27But the connectionis perhapseven closer. For althoughboth Weberand Schmittcould be said to agree thatthe rise of a particular"type"of Berufsmenschwas the result, in part, of the so-called Protestant"ethic,"both diagnosed the largely negative "unintendedconsequences"of its promotion. Schmitt,however, actuallytracedthe contemporarydepoliticizedperiodto the Whenappliedto the "distortions"of contemporary influenceof Protestantism.28 he representativegovernment, suggestedthat: The simple meaningof the principleof representationis thatthe membersof Parliamentarerepresentativesof the whole people andthushave an independentauthorityvis-a-vis the voters. Insteadof derivingtheir authorityfrom the individualvoter,they continueto derive it from the people. "The memberof Parliamentis not bound by instructionsand commandsand is answerableto his conscience alone".This meansthat the personificationof the people and the unity of Parliamentas their representativeat least implies the idea of a complexiooppositorum,that is, the unity of the pluralityof interestsand parties.It is conceived in representativeratherthaneconomic terms.29 Contemporaryparliamentarism,based on delegaterepresentationby partycandidates,illustrated-at leaston Schmitt'spresentation30-amovementawayfrom properlypoliticalrepresentation.It did so by negatingits necessarilypersonalor eminent character,and Schmittclaimed that the transformationof the modem stateinto a "Leviathan"meantthatit hadactuallycome to symbolizea body that "disappearsfrom the world of representations."This is because the theatrical HobbesianLeviathan,which held the populationin awe, had been transformed Schmitt, Roman Catholicism, 14. Schmitt, Roman Catholicism,31, 32. 27 See Schmitt,Roman Catholicism, 10; McCormick,Schmitt'sCritiqueof Liberalism,93, note 31; Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the "Spirit"of Capitalism [1904-5] trans. T. Parsons (London, 1994), 87. 28 Schmitt, "Age of Neutralizations,"135; Ellen Kennedy, "Introduction:Carl Schmitt's Parlamentarismusin Its Historical Context,"in Schmitt, ParliamentaryDemocracy, xxxix. 29 Schmitt, Roman Catholicism,26. 30Cf. Bernard Manin, The Principles of RepresentativeGovernment(Cambridge,1997). 25 26 118 Duncan Kelly by liberalism and capitalisminto a simple machine.31 As he suggested in the Verfassungslehre: Torepresentmeansto makevisible andpresentaninvisibleentitythrough an entitywhich is publiclypresent... This is not possible with any arbitraryentity,since a particularkind of being [Sein] is assumed.32 Liberalismsought "to eliminatethis remnant[the idea of parliamentaryrepresentationas a complexiooppositorum]of an age devoid of economic thinking." Instead,parliamentarismsimply "emphasisesthatparliamentarydelegates are only emissaries and agents."Here, the " 'whole' of the people is only an idea; the whole of the economic process, a materialreality."33 For Schmitt,this was of the at and claims these were furtherexentirely wrong way looking things, plored in his vastly more famous work on the historical-intellectualplight of There, Schmitt'sargumentsuggestedthatthis downgrading parliamentarism.34 of the centralrole of popularwill stood at odds with the generalprinciplesof popularsovereignty,andthattechnical-economiccapitalistrationalityhadradically distortedthe properfocus of representativegovernment.Indeed,he argued thatcontemporary wouldactuallyhaveto be representation representation against To understandhow such a positioncould be theoreticallyjustified, Parliament.35 though,in orderto supporta sovereignrepresentativefigure,an accountof how the people couldbe properlyrepresentedundera modem democraticstatebased on popularwill was required.And Schmittdevelopedsuchajustificationthrough an interpretationof the writingsof the Abbe Sieyes.36 III. Representation,pouvoir constituantand the Positive Constitution: The Abbe Sieyes At the beginning of his extraordinarywork on the subject of constituent power (pouvoirconstituant,VerfassunggebendeGewalt)andthe FrenchRevolution, Egon Zweig suggested that the debate over the origins of the concept 31 ChristopherPye, "The Sovereign, the Theater,and the Kingdome of Darknesse:Hobbes and the Spectacle of Power," Representations, 8 (1984), 91, explicitly discusses Hobbes's "theatrical"notion of representation.This relates to Schmitt's critiqueof political pluralismas well. See Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,209; Carl Schmitt,"Staatsethikund pluralistischerStaat," Kant-Studien,35 (1930), 28-42. 32 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,209. 33 Schmitt, Roman Catholicism,26-27, emphasis added. 34 Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of ParliamentaryDemocracy [1926 Ed.], trans.Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge,Mass., [1923] 1985). 35Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,314f. 36 See JohnP. McCormick,"Fear, Technology andthe State:CarlSchmitt,Leo Straussand the Revival of Hobbes in WeimarandNational Socialist Germany,"Political Theory,22 (1994), 626, 644-45. Carl Schmitt 119 need not be confined to the age of the American and FrenchRevolutions. Its beginningscould be tracedback to the works of Plato andAristotleand for one very specific reason;pouvoir constituantpresupposesa distinctionbetween an originaland foundationalconceptionof"law" (Grundgesetz),and everydaylegal ordinancesand rules (Gesetz).37This foundationalconception of law or a legal orderis to be understoodas a constitution(Verfassung).Clearly,the particular body or subject that possesses "constituentpower" is of considerable importanceto his analysis,andZweig was especially interestedin the impactof a conceptionof"reason"wroughtfromEnlightenmentprinciplesin general,and the FrenchRevolutionin particular,on modem discussionsof constituentpower. CarlSchmitt,too, was considerablyexercizedby the impactof the FrenchRevolution, but it is this formulationof a split between a positive "constitution"on the one hand,andconstitutionallaw on the other,thatbest representsthe fundamental basis of his constitutionalthought.It is a distinctionthat has considerable implicationsfor his accountof representationbecause: ... the distinctionbetween the "writtenandunwrittenconstitution"is in truththe opposition of the constitution(in its positive sense) and the constitutionallaw which is based on it.38 The distinctionsuggestedheremirrorsalmostexactlythe discussionof the Abbe Sieyes, who wrotethatthe "constitutionis not the workof the constitutedpower, but of the constituentpower,"which for Sieyes was the nation.39Sieyes's formulations of the interrelationshipbetween the nation and constituentpower had a profoundimpact on Schmitt'sdiscussion in his Verfassungslehre,providing a detailedtheoreticalancestryto those practicalargumentsaboutthe natureof the Weimarstate.However,most historicalandpolitical discussions of constituent power have tendedto examine the split between putativenotions of an "ancestral"or "ancient"constitutionon the one hand,anda "real"or writtendocument on the other.Relevant examples of such thinkingcan be found in the political thoughtof the post-SolonianGreeks,duringthe greatupheavalsin seventeenthcenturyEngland,and in the acerbicand quasi-Sieyesiancommentsof Thomas Paine in TheRights of Man, to note three exemplaryconstitutionalmoments.40 For Schmitt,the dichotomywas more fundamentalthanthis.41 37 Egon Zweig, Die Lehre vom Pouvoir Constituant(Tiibingen, 1904), 9. Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,386. 39EmmanuelSieyes, Qu'est-ce que le TiersEjtat?ed. R. Zapperi(Geneva, [1789] 1971), 180f. 40 Cf. Ernest Barker, Greek Political Theory (London, 1918), 51ff; J. G. A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitutionand the Feudal Law (Cambridge, 1987); Janelle Greenberg,The Radical Face of the Ancient Constitution(Cambridge,2000); Thomas Paine, TheRights of Man, in M. Foot and I. Kramnick(eds.), The ThomasPaine Reader (London, 1987), 285-307. 41 Erst-Rudolf Huber,"Verfassungund Verfassungswirklichkeitbei Carl Schmitt,"in his Bewahrung und Wandlung(Berlin, 1972), 19. 38 120 Duncan Kelly The "positive"constitutionis pureconstituentpower, and Schmittdefined "constituentpower" simply as "politicalwill." In practice, he continued, the power or authorityto take the "concreteand complete decision [Gesamtentscheidung]"concerningthe "type and form [ArtundForm]"of political existence is an expression of such "politicalwill." "Politicalwill" thereforedetermines the natureandformof the constitutionunderstoodin its "positive"sense. Moreover,"politicalwill" or constituentpower cannotbe justified by recourse to abstractor normativearguments.Rather,properlyunderstoodit signifies the essentially"existential"groundon which the validityof any constitutionnecessarily rests.42 Schmitt'scompresseddiscussions of the FrenchRevolution focused on its impacton bothpositive-lawthinkingaboutthe constitution,andon the idea of a convergence-in fact of a congruence-between the people andthe nation,the resultof which was a "nationaldemocracy."43 Accordingto Schmitt,the moder mixed constitution,with its liberaland democraticelements was bornwith the French Revolution. So too was the idea that the people are the "bearers"of constituentpower,who can "act"with a self-conscious political unity through the mediumof the nation-state.By the conceptof the "nation,"wrote Schmitt,is understoodan "individualpeoplecharacterisedby its specificpoliticalconsciousness."44The moder nationgives formto the people, andhence theirconstituent power,for the Volkareotherwiseunderstoodin democratictheoryas an unorganized "mass" or Hobbesian multitude, capable of making only "yes or no" acclamatorypoliticaldecisions.45Directlyrelatedto the earlierdiscussionof the necessity of the publicspherefor an adequateaccountof representation,Schmitt claimed that "thepeople is a concept that only exists in the public sphere."In fact, "the people appearsonly in a public, indeed, it first producesthe public. The people anda public areestablishedtogether."46 And developingthese ideas even further,every (Jede) constitution,wrote Schmitt,necessarilypresupposes the unity andindivisibilityof the constituentpower thatformsit, andafter 1789 this unityhas typicallybeen presentedas stemmingfroma people unifiedwithin a nation-state.7The equationcontinuesto formthe basis of most contemporary assumptionsaboutpopularsovereignty,nationalism,andthe constituentpower of the people.48Schmitt'sassessmentwas thatundera modem democraticconstitutionor state,therewere threepossible ways of conceiving the relationship between the people and the constitution.First,the people could exist "priorto" 42 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,75f. 43 Ibid., 231. Ibid., emphasis added. Ibid., 277, 251. 46 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,243; cf. Kennedy, "Hostis not Inimicus,"46. 47 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,49ff. 48 See BernardYack, "PopularSovereigntyand Nationalism,"Political Theory,29 (2001), 44 45 524. Carl Schmitt 121 and"above"the constitutionas pureconstituentpower.Second,they could exist "within"the constitutionas membersof an electorate,or third,the people could occupy a space "beside"the constitutionas bearersof constituentpower acting momentsof spontaneousformsof popularmobilization"within out"intermediary the normalpolitical order.49 These interrelationshipscorrespondwith and furtherdevelop Schmitt'sargumentthattherearein fact only two "principles"of politicalform-identity, or representation-andthatdifferentstateformsbroadlycorrespondto one or other of them.50Thus,identitypresupposesthe "unmediated"unity of a people. Representation,on the otherhand,assumes that althoughevery state form presupposes a structural"identity"betweenrulersandruled,such identitycan neverbe fully realizedin practice.Similarly,because therecould never be a "pure"system of representation,the state can only be understoodas a political unity because it "originated[beruhen]fromthe interrelationshipof these two opposing formalprinciples."51 Elaboratingon this thesis, Schmittwrote that: The state rests, as a political unity, on the combinationof [these] two opposed transformativeprinciples [Gestaltungsprinzipien]-the principle of identity(namelythe presenceof a people conscious of itself as a political unity, [a people] thathas the ability,because of the power of its own politicalconsciousnessandnationalwill, to distinguishbetween friendandfoe)-and the principleof representation,the powerof which is constitutedas political unity by the government.52 Representationcan "bringaboutpolitical unity as a whole," because the power of representationapplies here only to the body which governs (wer regiert).53 This relationshipbetween governingauthorityandthe power of representation was based on Schmitt's prior assumptionthat representation"belongs to the Thus,througha sphereof the political and is thereforesomethingexistential."54 secularizationof the principleof representation,Schmittlinkedthe necessarily substantivecriteriaof meaningfulrepresentationoutlinedin the previoussection to the modem state and the sphere of the political. Correspondingly,he also suggestedthatthereare, in fact, two principal"subjects"of constituentpower; either a monarch(whose power stemmed,originally,from God) or the people 49 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,238-52. Cf. AndreasKalyvas, "CarlSchmitt and The Three Moments of Democracy,"CardozoLaw Review, 21 (2000), 1530f, Wilfried, Nippel, "Ancient and modem republicanism:'mixed constitution'and 'ephors',"in B. Fontana(ed.), TheInvention of the Modern Republic (Cambridge,1994), 24-25. 50 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,204-8. 51 Ibid., 214. Ibid., parenthesesmine. 53Ibid., 205; cf. 212. 54Ibid., 211. 52 Duncan Kelly 122 (unifiedthroughthe nation).This relatesto two mainprinciplesof constitutional Thus,when a monarchis the subject legitimacy,eitherdynasticor democratic.55 of constituentpower,the "constitution"emanatesfromhis "fullnessof power," in the languageof medievalpoliticaltheologywhich Schmittlikedto employ.By contrast,if the people arethe subjectof constituentpower,the decision over the natureandformof political existence is determinedsolely by their(free) political will. The centralconsequence of the FrenchRevolution, therefore,was to enshrinedemocracyas the guidingpoliticalprincipleof the modem erawithina system of nation states-national sovereignty.Thus, "it belongs to the essence of democracythat every and all decisions which are taken are only valid for thosewho themselvesdecide.Thatthe outvotedminoritymustbe ignoredin this only causes theoreticaland superficialdifficulties."56 Schmittcited Rousseauto supporthis interpretationof the bindingcharacterof the volontegenerale, andit is crucialto his argumentationthatdemocracy ultimatelydependsuponthe "identity"of rulersandruled,although"thishomogeneity need not necessarilybe racialor ethnicin origin.In fact, the "substance of [democratic]equality[Gleichheit]can in differentdemocracies,andat different times, itself be different."57 Nevertheless,understandingthe nationas a poconscious and unified litically people certainlyprovidesthe main"substance"of democratichomogeneityto be found in Schmitt'swritings.This more abstract concept of the nation in Schmitt's thought built upon the work of the Abbe Sieyes. Discussing Sieyes's particularunderstandingof the relationshipbetween the nationand constituentpower, PasqualePasquinoquotes from a fascinating archivetext of a draftreview,by Sieyes, of his own famouspamphlet,Qu'est-ce que le tiers etat?, that he planned to send anonymouslyto the press. This is Sieyes's summaryof his position: ... what we must call a constitutionis by no means an attributeof the nation,butbelongsto its governmentalone.It is the government,not the nation which is constituted... I see too that the constitutedpower and the constituentpowercannotbe confused.Consequentlythe body of the ordinaryrepresentativesof the people, that is to say those who are entrustedwith ordinarylegislation, cannotwithout contradictionand absurdityinterferewith the constitution.5 55 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,77ff, 87-90, cf. 81ff. Schmitt, ParliamentaryDemocracy, 25. 57 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,228; cf. McCormick,Schmitt's Critiqueof Liberalism, 187, n. 35; Peter Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty and the Crisis of German ConstitutionalLaw (Durham,N.C., 1997), 102. 58 EmmanuelSieyes, "Compterendude Qu 'est-ce que le Tiers Etat? (1789)," in Pasquale Pasquino,Sieyes et l'invention de la constitutionen France (Paris, 1998), 167-70. 56 Carl Schmitt 123 Basedprincipallyon his studiesin politicaleconomy,Sieyes sharplydistinguished modem, commercialsociety from the society of the ancients.59Such a distinctionprovidedthejustificationfor his "politico-constitutional" assessmentof representation.Sieyes stressedthe elementaryincomparabilityand historicaldiscontinuitybetween the ancientsand the modems, outliningthe vastly different "elements"(contenu)of modernity,suchas the growthof commerce,agriculture and the rise of Europeanstates. He suggested that moder concerns with productionandconsumption,underpinnedby the divisionof labor,were fundamentally at odds with the ancients'conception of the "good life."60Yet, as Sewell asserts,therewas a correspondencebetween Sieyes's accountof the division of labor in the spheres of both "civil society" and the state. In the former,the "establishmentof representativelabor"is the basis of "the naturalincrease of liberty in society." In the strictly political sphere Sieyes pointed out that "for those who consult reason ratherthan books ... there can only be one form of legitimategovernment.It can manifestitself in two differentforms,"and these differenttypes stronglyresemblewhat Schmittcalled the twin principlesof political form.61The people can eithergovernthemselves in a state approachinga democratiebrute,or,based on the commonadvantagesprovidedby the division of labor,they can submit to a representativeconstitution,to professionalized andautonomousgovernment.Moreover,given the naturalprogression(andbenefits) of the division of labor, Sieyes thoughtthat "even in the smallest state" pure democracyis "farless appropriateto the needs of society, far less conducive to the objects of political union."62 Sieyes presagedmoder argumentsabouta "politicalclass,"whilstbuilding on Hobbes's desire to constructa new and "rational"account of political science, able to explain the "artifice"of political rule.63His idea of representative governmentas a mediatingelementbetweenmass-democracyandpoliticalrule conservedthe distancebetween governorsand governedin a moderncommercial society, whilst the avowed goal of the "social state"or etat social was to promoteindividuallibertythrougha political division of labor.64However, although he was clearly interestedin the representationof the people, Sieyes's 59See Marcel Dorigny, "La Formationde la Pensee lconomique de Sieyes d'apres ses Manuscrits(1770-1789)," Annales historiques de la RevolutionFrancaise, 60 (1988), 29-31. 60 Pasquale Pasquino, "EmmanuelSieyes, Benjamin Constantet le <<gouvemement des modemes>>. Contributiona l'histoire du concept de representationpolitique,"Revuefrancaise de science politique, 37 (1987), 219-20, 222-23; MurrayForsyth,Reason and Revolution:The PoliticalThoughtof theAbbeSieyes(New York,1987),138. 61 EmmanuelSieyes, quoted by William H. Sewell, A Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution: TheAbbeSieyesand Whatis the ThirdEstate?(Durham,N.C., 1994),90f. 62 Ibid. Forsyth,Reason and Revolution,66f; also Antony Black, "TheJuristicOriginsof Social ContractTheory,"History of Political Thought,14 (1993), 57-76. 64Emmanuel Sieyes, "Bases de l'Ordre Social" (1794/95), repr. in Pasquino, Sieyes et l'invention, esp. 185; Forsyth,Reason and Revolution,60-63, 142f. 63 124 Duncan Kelly argumentsdeveloped-in specific contrastto Rousseau'sdiscussionof the "generalwill"-a focus on commoninterest.65 Dependentupon a specific conception of the nation and the "natural"effects of the division of labor, Sieyes's argumentscan be locatedwithinthe contextof a long-runningdebateaboutnoblesse commerqanteandthe relationshipbetween"civic virtue"andthe nobilitybegun in pre-RevolutionaryFrance.66 These debatescontinuedafterthe Revolutionwith a transformationin the popularimageryof the ThirdEstatethat illustratedits restorativemission and its oppositionto a weak King and parasiticnobility.67From its miserableposition underthe ancien regime, Sieyes sought to reconstitutea fragmentedbody politic throughthe constituentpower of the nation.Utilizing both religious and technicalimagerySieyes effected a theoreticaltransferralof"the miracleof the body of the King,"to "the elective permanenceof the body of the represented nation."68This was underpinnedby his foundational discussion of pouvoir constituant. Sieyes distinguishedbetweenpouvoirconstituant,pouvoir commettant,and pouvoir constitue,the latterreferringto the regularactivitiesundertakenby the ordinaryrepresentativesof the people based on law. The function of pouvoir constitue,in particularits legislativeandexecutiveelements,involves the preparation(confection)of law. Pouvoir commettantandpouvoir constituant"putin place the ensembleof rules(the Constitution)which governthe politicalfoundations [ 'etablissement]of the nation (its government,in the pre-Rousseauean sense of the term), and ... guarantee,by a mechanism of authorisation,"the legitimationof, andobligationsto, the constitutedpower.69Pouvoir constituant concernsthe foundationandlegitimacyof the law andconstitution,whilepouvoir commettantis the power possessed solely by the "people,"as an active citizen body,over theirrepresentativesat the level of the government.It is the authorizing power of the whole citizen body to select theirrepresentatives.Of the three forms of power, constitue and commettanttypically refer to the ordinary,nor- 65 Colette Clavreul,"Sieyes et la genese de la representationmodeme," Droits, 6 (1986), 47. 66 Pasquino,Sieyes et l'inventionde la constitution,45; Jay M. Smith, "Social Categories, the Languageof Patriotismand the Originsof the FrenchRevolution:The Debate over noblesse commercante,"Journal of ModernHistory, 72 (2000), 339-74, esp. 357ff; RichardWhatmore, Republicanismand the French Revolution(Oxford, 2000). 67 On the imagery, Antoine de Baecque, The Body Politic: CorporealMetaphor in RevolutionaryFrance, 1770-1800, trans. CharlotteMandell (Stanford[1993], 1997) is superb. See also ChristopherHodson," 'In Praise of the ThirdEstate':Religious and Social Imageryin the EarlyFrenchRevolution,"Eighteenth-CenturyStudies,34 (2001), 337-62; Antoine de Baecque, "TheCitizen in Caricature:Past andPresent,"in R. Waldinger,P. Dawson, andI. Woloch (eds.), The French Revolutionand the Meaning of Citizenship(Westport,Conn., 1993), esp. 66. 68de Baecque, The Body Politic, 101. 69 Pasquino, "Sieyes, Constant,"225. Carl Schmitt 125 mal legal order. Pouvoir constituant, however, only appears in the exceptional or extraordinary situation, either in the formation of the nation, or in the selection of "extraordinary" representatives to represent the nation in the Third Estate. Through the (electoral) authorization of pouvoir commettant, the people limit their own power (se borner) by selecting those delegates who will execute real laws. This is the basis of legislative representation, the only form of legitimate representation according to Sieyes. The exceptional act of founding the nation, in terms of its position as "the underlying compacted unity of free individuals that established or constituted a public order" is, therefore, pouvoir constituant itself in its purest form. Furthermore, this formation of the nation is a result of "natural law," in terms of its basis in the division of labor and freedom of (political) association that Sieyes perceived to be at the root of political life.70Hence, the nation could not be subject to a "positive constitution," for the nation is, in essence, the constitution itself, incapable of acting against itself because it would be logically contradictory to act against its own will.71 Private, individual liberty is the result of representative government because the "social state does not establish an unjust inequality of rights by the side of a natural inequality of means."72 In fact, "on the contrary, it protects the equality of rights against the natural but harmful inequality of means."73Alongside the distinction between active and passive citizenship, such reasoning differentiated Sieyes's focus on the nation from that of the Jacobins, and underscored his concern with "re-presentation" of the "re-publique," as opposed to the "re-totale," the retotalization of society by any one particular regime.74 In common fashion, his republicanism feared the imposition of an "ancient" republican model onto a modem, post-revolutionary France, a position justified through his own science sociale.75 Schmitt took these ideas up almost verbatim in terms of his discussion of the foundation of the Weimar Republic. The people, he wrote, had abrogated the 70 See 71 Forsyth,Reason and Revolution,esp. 74-77. Ibid. 72 Emmanuel Sieyes, "FragmentsPolitiques," Des Manuscrits de Sieyes, ed. Christian Faure (Paris, 1999), 471. 73 See Jeremy Jennings, "The Declaration des Droits de l'Homme et du Citoyen and its Critics in France:Reaction and Ideologie," Historical Journal, 35 (1992), 842. 74 Istvan Hont, "ThePermanentCrisis of a Divided Mankind:'ContemporaryCrisis of the Nation State' in Historical Perspective,"in J. Dunn (ed.), ContemporaryCrisis of the Nation State? (Oxford, 1994), 166-231, esp. 203-6; EmmanuelSieyes, "Contrela Re-totale,"in Pasquino, Sieyes et l'invention, 175-76; RobertWokler,"ContextualizingHegel's Phenomenology of the French Revolution,"Political Theory,26 (1998), 42f. 75 Whatmore, Republicanismand the French Revolution, esp. 23-31; Hont, "'ContemporaryCrisis of the Nation State',"204ff; Forsyth,Reason and Revolution,177ff; KeithMichael Baker, "Transformationsof Classical Republicanismin Eighteenth-CenturyFrance,"Journal of Modern History, 73 (2001), 32-53. 126 Duncan Kelly monarchicalprinciple (whose classical illustrationwas the 1814 Preambleto the RestorationBourbonConstitution)regnantpriorto the GermanRevolution, so that the subject ofpouvoir constituanthad consequentlychanged. At root, the German"type"of constitutionalmonarchy-whether understoodas organism or as a "juristic"person statedthat the power of the monarchwithin the state clearly stood opposed to the democraticprinciple.76Indeed,B6ckenforde writes that "atbottom the monarchicalprinciplewas simply a historicalfact," albeit one which, after 1918 no longer "stoodup as a political formalprinciple carryingits own legitimacywithinit."77Thetransformation ofpouvoirconstituant after the GermanRevolution for Schmitt, therefore,was to be understoodin much the same way as Sieyes had theorized the transformationof the Third Estatefrom"nothing,"to its new positionas "everything."The ThirdEstateand its membersin the constituentNational Assembly exemplified what has (in a slightlydifferentcontext)beenreferredto as the attempted"abolitionof feudality" in revolutionaryFrance.Feudalityin this contextreferredto the political domination of king and nobility, whose hereditarypower could never truly "represent"the will of the people.78 Herewas a clearprecedentfor Schmitt"sdiscussionof the foundationof the WeimarRepublic in the NationalAssembly elections of January1919, whose delegateshe saw as representingthe constituentpowerof the people. He did not fail to discuss the theoreticalimplications in his Verfassungslehre.79 Schmitt wrote-again echoing Sieyes-that "theconstitutionin its positive sense originates throughan act of constituentpower,"and it was such constituentpower thatlay behindthe choice for a democratic,as opposedto monarchical,constitution madeby the Germanpeople.80With"threeor perhapsfourconstitutions"in the period 9 November 1918 until August 1919, the confusions of the situation recalledthe positionof Francein 1793 andGermanyin 1848.81The specific idea thatthe positive constitutionreflected the democraticprinciplewas illustrated for Schmittin the Preambleto the WeimarConstitution,which statedthat the Germanpeople had "given itself" the constitution,and that all state authority 76 Ernst-WolfgangBockenforde, "The German Type of ConstitutionalMonarchy in the Nineteenth- Century,"State, Society and Liberty, trans. J. A. Underwood (Leamington Spa, 1991), 87-114; Phillipe Lauvaux,"Le principemonarchiqueen Allemagne,"in O. Beaud and P. Wachsmann(eds.), La sciencejuridiquefranfaise et la sciencejuridique allemande 1870-1914 (Strasbourg,1997), 65-78; ChristophSch6nberger,Das Parlament im Anstaltstaat(Frankfurt am Main, 1997), 70-82. 77 B6ckenfdrde,"GermanType of ConstitutionalMonarchy,"89, 93, 95, 103, 111. 78 Forsyth,Reason and Revolution,89; JeremyJennings,"Conceptionsof Englandand its Constitutionin Nineteenth-CenturyFrench Political Thought,"Historical Journal, 29 (1986), 65-85, esp. 79f; Pasquino, Sieyes et I'invention,88. 79 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,57; cf RobertoZapperi,"Sieyes et l'abolition de feodalite," Annales historiquesde la RevolutionFranfaise, 44 (1972), 321-51. 80 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,21, though cf. 93, emphasis added. 81 Carl Schmitt,Die Diktatur (Berlin [1921, rev. 1928], 19784),205. 127 Carl Schmitt emanatedfromthem.82However, only the figure of the sovereignwould be capable of representingthe state as the "politicalunity of a people,"and accounting for the natureof thatrepresentativewas to necessitateSchmitt'sreturnto the writingsof Hobbes. IV. Hobbes and the Personof the State MurrayForsythhas arguedthatHobbes's accountof the modem statewas, like Sieyes's, basedon the "constituentpowerof the people"andunderpinnedby If Sieyes built on Hobbes, though, Schmittdetera concept of representation.83 minedto combinethe two writers,andto fully understandSchmitt'saccountof the moder state,Hobbes'saccountof representationmustbe clearlyoutlined.It is a particularlyHobbesian argumentthat Schmitt employs underWeimarto supportthe powers of the Reichsprasidentas the bearerof state sovereignty,but one which appearsto place constituentpowerwith the body of the people. Here, his accountof the sovereignis boundup with his conflationof the conceptof the state with that of the political, illustratedin the tautology suggesting that "the stateis an entity,andin fact the decisive entity,"because it "restsupon its political character."84 As the state is premisedon an accountof the political, properly understoodthe two are coterminous,as the sphere of the political is where is delineatedthe precise authoritythatis able to take decisions aboutwho or what constitutes a threatto the state, the political and public sphere.85Hence: "the enemy is hostis, not inimicusin the broadersense."86 Schmitt's concept of the political built on his discussions of romanticism and sovereignty.87For it is to the moment of decision that his writings are attuned, and his argumentis positioned at the intersectionof constituentpower andthenormallegal order,because"onlywhenthe decisionof a sovereignpeople ha[s] been expressed could one strive to regulate its formulationand execution."88As Schmitt'sformulationin Political Theologymade clear,"sovereign 82 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,58; see Elmar M. Hucko (ed.), The Democratic Tradition: Four German Constitutions(LeamingtonSpa, 1987), 149-90. 83 MurrayForsyth, "ThomasHobbes and the ConstituentPower of the People," Political Studies, 29 (1981), 191-203, esp. 193; Skinner,"ArtificialPerson,"4, n. 12. David Runciman, Pluralism and the Personality of the State (Cambridge, 1997), 12-13, n. 13, and Skinner, "ArtificialPerson,"21, criticize his ascriptionof a "latent"group personalityto the state. 84 Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 44. 85 Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 33; Meier, Schmittand Strauss, 23f. 86 Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 28f. and n. 9; cf. Simon Critchley, "The Other's Decision in Me (WhatAre the Politics of Friendship?),"Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity(London, 1999), 254-86; Kennedy, "Hostis not Inimicus,"esp. 44-47. 87 Carl Schmitt,Political Romanticism,trans.G. Oakes (Cambridge,Mass., [1919] 1991). 88 Cristi, AuthoritarianLiberalism, 121; Caldwell, Popular Sovereignty, 227 n. 109: "[Schmitt]could only imagine the alternativesof bourgeois Rechtsstaat and communist revolution." 128 Duncan Kelly is he who decidesuponthe stateof exception,"endowingthe figureof the sovereign with the capacity of making the public decision between friends and enmoment.Yet,thereis clearlyan emies, of decidinguponthe extra-constitutional elision here,betweenthe conceptof the stateandthe personof the sovereignthat seems remarkablysimilarto the way Hobbes's sovereign is often discussed as being synonymouswith the state.Furthermore,althoughSchmittattachedgreat importanceto the fact thatthe state is the highest form of political association, and although he thought that the unity of the contemporarystate was under threat,it is clearthatthe entityknown as "thestate"cannot"act"in any obvious sense. It is an artifice,an abstraction.Nevertheless, somethingcalled the state patentlyexists. And given his suggestion that all modem concepts of the state aresecularizedtheologicalconcepts,it shouldcome as no surprisethathe turned to Hobbes's discussion of"that MortallGod"to which we owe ourearthlyallegiance for guidance.89 For Hobbes, properlyaccountingfor the actions of the representativesovereignallows the characterof the statebe ascertained.The centralquestionhere is how the state-as mere artifice-can be authorizedto act in the name of the people, a question raised in fact in the frontispiece to Leviathan.90And on Hobbes'smost famous account,"APERSON,is he, whose wordsor actions are considered, either as his own, or as representingthe works or actions of an other man, or of any other thing to whom they are attributed,whetherTrulyor byFiction."Moreover,"whenthey are consideredas his owne, then is he called a NaturallPerson: And when they areconsideredas representingthe words and actions of an other,then is he a Feigned orArtificiallperson."91Some "Persons Artificiall,"Hobbesnoted,"havetheirwordsandactionsOwnedby those whom they represent.And then the Person is the Actor; and he thatowneth his words and actions, is the AUTHOR:In which case the Actor actethby AuthorityFor that which in speakingof goods and possessions, is called an Owner."Therefore, if an actor"owns"the actionsperformed,he has "authority,"by which "is alwayes understooda Right of doing any act, so thatif an Actor maketha Covenantby authority,he bindeththerebytheAuthor,no lesse thanif he hadmade it himself."92In otherwords, a person: ... is the same that an Actor is, both on the Stage and in common Conversation; and to Personate, is to Act, or Representhimselfe, or an other;andhe thatactethanother,is saidto bearehis Person,or act in his name.93 89 Schmitt, Political Theology, 37. 90 Noel Malcolm, "The Titlepage of Leviathan, Seen in a Curious Perspective," The SeventeenthCentury, 13 (1998), 124-59, esp. 148. 91Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan,ed. RichardTuck (Cambridge[1651], 1996), 111. 92 Ibid. 93Ibid., 112. Carl Schmitt 129 If one makes a covenantwith an actoror representer,the authorityof the actor binds one as an authorof the action,so thatone can only be boundby a covenant when one is an author.Such authorization,which is necessarilyrepresentation, entails an obligationto fulfil the termsof the covenantin termsof the criteriaof justice establishedby the civil law.94This is becauseall covenantsbetweenmen, as naturalpersonsareartificialconstructs,andbindingin termsof"CivilleLawes" only when a "coercivepower"exists, "andsuch power thereis none before the erectionof a Common-wealth."95 Althoughcivil laws entrencha generaldesire forpeacefulandcommodiousliving, only a sovereignpowercan oblige (through the authorityof theirown actionsin establishinga commonwealth)men to obey them.96Thus, the libertythatmen "denythemselves"upon authorizingthe actions of the personof the Commonwealth-a resultof theircovenantto escape the stateof nature-is therebytransformedinto an obligationto obey the sovereign power, for men themselves have authorizedits actions. Even "covenants enteredinto by fear,in the conditionof meer Nature,are obligatory."97 The principalconclusion of Hobbes's discussion of attributedaction is that such actionas is performedby a representativecountsas the actionof the author even if the authordoes not physically undertakea particularaction. Indeed,the point is that an authoris "underobligation to take responsibilityfor its occurrence,"because they "own the consequences of the action as if they had performedit themselves."98Here,therearetwo majorareasof interest.First,when discussing artificialpersons(of which the state is one), one of Hobbes's principal tasks was to show how such persons are capableof being represented.For, althoughable to "speakand act,"these artificialpersonsare "incapableof acting as authors in the distinctive manner of natural persons, and hence of authorisingtheir own representatives."They cannot covenant. Second, therefore, "it is possible for them [to speakandact] ... only if theirwords and actions can validlybe attributedto themon the basis of theirperformanceby some other personor collectivity licensed to act in theirname."99 Althoughit is clearthatHobbes's accountis so broadthatalmost any entity can be a person, his account of what constitutesa "natural"person is actually quitelimited.Therefore,in his discussionsof artificialpersons-in DavidCopp's terms, those persons who perform"secondaryactions"100-thedistinctionbeHobbes, Leviathan, 112. 100f. 96Ibid., 185. 97 Ibid., 150. Cf. A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, 1979). On Hobbes's theory of volition, see Patrick Riley, Will and Political Legitimacy (Cambridge,Mass., 1982), 23-60, esp. 58. 98 Hobbes, Leviathan, 10. 9 Ibid., 14. 100David Copp, "Hobbeson Artificial Persons and Collective Actions," ThePhilosophical Review, 89 (1980), 579-906, esp. 583. 94 95 Ibid., Duncan Kelly 130 tween the two main types of attributedaction, "whethertruly or by fiction,"is crucial.The theatricalallusions within Hobbes's accountof attributionby fiction have often been discussed.101However, as Skinnerargues, it is of paramountimportanceto Hobbes's argumentthatthe actions of the state, however, be trulyattributedto it. OnHobbes'saccount,artificialpersons-such as bridges and hospitals-can be trulyrepresented"by a Rector,Masteror Overseer"(or in the case of the state,a sovereign),commissionedandgiven the authorityto act on their behalf.102This is a voluntary transferof right, and "once you have covenanted,you must leave it to your representative,who is now in possession of yourrightof action,to exercise it at his discretionwhen actingyourname."103 To use Copp's helpful phrasing,this type of artificialperson "is an agent that has actions attributedto it on the basis of acts of otheragents. Collectives that The state on this readingis a personthatperforms act are artificialpersons."104 secondary actions. Yet there remains the problem of how such authorization takes place given the inanimatestatusof the artificialperson in particular,and the fact thatthe state-rather unlike a bridge-does not even exist priorto the mutual covenants of the multitude.For Skinner,Hobbes's proposed solution was the suggestion that the authorizationrequiredfor actions to be truly (and not fictionally) attributedto artificialpersonsrequiresthat"suchacts of authorizationmust standin some appropriaterelationshipof dominionor ownership And of all the illustrawith respectto the purelyartificialpersonconcerned."105 tions Hobbes came up with in this regard-of "ownership"as possession of property,as the relationshipof a governorto his charge,as maternaldominion over children,or as the dominionof the state-the latteris of paramountimportance. For the essence of the commonwealthis embodied in the figure of the sovereign.106 This is surely also what Schmitt meant when he suggested that through representationpoliticalunitycould be achieved,becausewithoutsuchrepresentationalunity the naturalexistence of diverse human groups cannot have the specificallypoliticalqualityof sovereignty,andwithoutsuchunitythe sphereof the politicalitself is threatened.107As Hobbeshadargued,in the formationof the state: 101 Skinner, "Artificial Person," 15f; cf. Runciman, "What Kind of Person is Hobbes's State?"268-78, esp. 275f; Pye, "Sovereign, Theater,"passim. 102 Copp, "ArtificialPersons and Collective Actions," esp. 589-93. 103 Skinner, "Artificial Person," 9. 104Copp, "ArtificialPersons and Collective Actions," 583, 595. 105Skinner,"ArtificialPerson," 17f, emphasis added. 106 In general, see Horst Bredekamp,ThomasHobbes Visuelle Strategien (Berlin, 1999), esp. 18-26. 107 Schmitt, Verfassungslehre,210. Carl Schmitt 131 One Person, of whose Acts a great Multitude,by mutuall Covenants one with another,have made themselvesevery one the Author,to the end he may use the strengthand means of them all, as he shall think expedient,for their Peace and CommonDefence. And he that carryeththis Person, is called SOVERAIGNE,and saidto have SoveraignePower; andevery one besides,his SUBJECT.108 However, as Skinnerpoints out, there is still a difficultpoint at issue here. For the "nameof the personengenderedby the transformationof the multitudeinto one personthroughtheiragreementto appointa representativeis not the sovereign but the state,"and the state is an artificialperson. Therefore,Hobbes argued that the commonwealthis an artificialperson, and "he that carryeththis Person, is called SOVERAIGNE,and said to have SoveraignePower."'09The sovereign in effect personates or representsthe artificialperson of the state. Because the statecannotauthorizeits own representative,a representativemust be authorizedby those who stand in an appropriaterelationshipof dominion, and who (as naturalpersons) possess the right to undertakethe actions they authorize,to covenant.And it is clear thatin the Hobbesiancommonwealthby institution,only if the public acts of sovereigns (as representativesof the state) have been authorizedby the mutualcovenantsof the multitudeto formthe commonwealth,can the actions of the sovereignbe trulyascribedto the people. As Runcimannotes, the case of stateformationin Leviathanallows "ownership[of action]to reside in the thingto be represented,"in this case the state.Therefore, the mutualcovenantsof the multitudemakes "possiblethe fiction thatthey can act as a unit, and commit themselves to the real actions that can maintainthat fiction.""0How though could the actions of the state to be truly attributableto the people who effectively own these actions, if the state is a personby fiction? Copp's analysismakes clearthis difficultpoint, suggestingthat"someartificial personsperformactions of which they arenot authors.Thatis, some may have actions attributedto them on the basis of actions of persons even though the formerhave not authorizedthe latter.""'This capturesprecisely the position of the stateor commonwealthin Hobbes's schema.It relatesdirectlyto a common sense understandingthat althoughthe actions of the state are truly attributable to those who authorizeits actions,the state is not the type of person,at least not accordingto Hobbes, that can authorizeits own actions. Withouta sovereign, 108Hobbes, Leviathan, 121, 120. 109Skinner, "Artificial Person," 20, 19; Runciman, "What Kind of Person is Hobbes's State?"272; Hobbes, Leviathan, 120-21. 110 Ibid., 273. 1" Copp, "ArtificialPersons and Collective Actions," 593. 132 Duncan Kelly the state is incapable of acting, indeed it cannot "doe anything"because the sovereignis the "sole legislator."'12 Schmitthad suggested that if Parliament"personifies"the nationbefore a "higher"representative,such as a monarch,then it would be substantivelyor politically representational.However, if parliamentaryrepresentationmerely referredto the division of seats in a chamberon the basis of votes cast, if it is simply a competitionbetween elites for numericalsuperiority,then such a type of representationis nothing"distinctive"-and distinctivenessis a definingfeature of legitimaterepresentation.113 Once again, the circularityof his argument is noticeable.Sovereigntystemsfromthe personalauthorityembodiedin a ruler; sovereigntyis tied to the political;the sovereignrepresentsthe politicalunity of a people; personalistrepresentationthereforebrings aboutpolitical unity.This type of argument,which conjoineda critiqueof the influence of technical-economic thinking on parliamentarismwith a deep-seatedbelief in the natureof representationas a substantialand personalform of authority,enabled Schmitt to justify his supportfor the figure of a strongReichsprasidenton the basis of Article 48 of the WeimarConstitution.114 He justified these argumentstheoretically, by adaptingthe writings of Hobbes and Sieyes to suggest that only the figure of the sovereign could properlyrepresentthe political unity of a people. Such unity was broughtaboutthroughthe idea of an interrelationshipbetween the constituentpower of the people and political representationproperlyconceived-a tense relationshipwhose implicationsare still much debatedin contemporarypolitical theory.15 V. Carl Schmitt'sPolitical Theoryof Representation Theoretically,SchmittsuggestedthatSieyes offereda "democratic"theory of the constituentpowerof the people, stemmingfromhis oppositionto absolute monarchy,whichwas simultaneouslycombinedwith an "anti-democratic" theory of representationand indirectsovereignty.The nub of what Schmitttook from Sieyes's theoryof representationwas thereforequite general.I have suggested those pointsof referencethatwere particularlyimportantfor Schmitt'sinterpretation and constitutionaltheory.And althoughSieyes's thoughtis not best understoodin isolation from the debatesin which it was conducted,Schmittcertainly abstractedfrom these debates to pull out the centralpoints at issue for 12 Hobbes, Leviathan, 184. Schmitt, Roman Catholicism,25. 114 See Duncan Kelly, TheState of the Political: ConceptionsofPolitics and the State in the Thoughtof Max Weber,Carl Schmittand Franz Neumann(Oxford,2003), ch. 4; David Dyzenhaus, "Legal Theory in the Collapse of Weimar:ContemporaryLessons?"AmericanPolitical Science Review, 91 (1997), 121-34. 115Anne Phillips, The Politics of Presence (Oxford, 1995). 113 Carl Schmitt 133 him.116This involved a focus the representativecharacterof a constitutionor statebased on the constituentpower of the people quanation.Equally,although Schmitt was certainlynot an advocate of the direct popularrule, neitherwas Sieyes. As Sonenscherhas argued,Sieyes pushedfor a "seizureof powerby the representativesof the ThirdEstate in the name of the sovereign union,"a case (neatlylinkedto discussionsof the Frenchfiscal deficit) of puttingthe stateback in credit.l7 Moreover,when Sieyes himself developedHobbes'saccountof representation, he presenteda powerfulcombinationof argumentsthatcontinueto underpin many assumptionsaboutthe characterof the modem nation-state.According to Wokler,Hobbes's accountof "theunity of the representer"in Leviathan paved the way for the understandingof the modem state outlined by Sieyes duringthe FrenchRevolution,which "requiresthatthe represented-that is, the people as a whole-be a moralpersonas well.""' More concretely,Sonenscher calls Sieyes's concept of the nation a "synonym for Hobbes's 'state' and Rousseau's 'general will,' that is to say, that the nation was "an abstraction representedby a body.""19But Sieyes adamantlyopposed Rousseaueancriticisms of representation,and "it was of the essence of his plan thatthe nationin assembly spoke for all the people and must never be silenced by the people themselves."120 Sieyes's concepts of the state and the nation underpinnedby constituent popular powerinformedSchmitt'saccountof the modem stateas the "politicalunity of a people." For this reasonthe notion of representationplays an incrediblyimportantpartin Schmitt'saccountof the state, and thereforein his wider political theory.Schmitt'spolitical argumentwas precisely that contemporary"liberalismis not the best realisation"of the principleof representation. "Onthe contrary,it is the very violationof it."'21His subsequentdefense of 116See Michael Sonenscher,"TheNation's Debt andthe Birthof the Modem Republic:The French Fiscal Deficit and the Politics of the Revolution of 1789. Part II," History of Political Thought, 18 (1997), 289. 17 Michael Sonenscher,"The Nation's Debt and the Birth of the Modem Republic: The French Fiscal Deficit and the Politics of the Revolution of 1789. Part I," History of Political Thought, 18 (1997), 70. Emphasis added. See also Sonenscher,"The Nation"s Debt, Part II," 305-8. 118Robert Wokler, "The EnlightenmentProject,the Nation State and the PrimalPatricide of Modernity,"in R. Wokler and N. Geras (eds.), The Enlightenmentand Modernity(London, 2000), 178. "l9Sonenscher,"The Nation's Debt, Part II," 313, 314; cf. Tracy Strong, "How to Write Scripture:Words,Authority,and Politics in Thomas Hobbes,"CriticalInquiry,20 (1993), esp. 156ff. 120 Wokler, "Enlightenment,Nation-State,"178; cf. GregoryDart,Rousseau, Robespierre and English Romanticism(Cambridge, 1999), 25-29. 121 McCormick,Schmitt's Critique, 187; cf. Volker Neumann,Der Staat im Biirgerkrieg (Frankfurtam Main, 1980), 25. 134 Duncan Kelly the representativefigureof the political leader(the Reichsprisident)who could unify the body of the stateagainsta weak andliberal"totalstate"was derivedin largepartfromthe work of Hobbes.He could only develop this argument,however, afterhe had cementedhis ideas aboutpolitical representationin the language of modem constitutionalismthroughhis engagementwith Sieyes. The Universityof Sheffield.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz