No Reason At All, Or Why Meaning Is Not Normative In The Reason-Implying Sense Joanna Klimczyk (University of Szczecin) A popular and deemed innocent argument for the claim that meaning is normative says that what an expression, or a word means provide the subject with some, though not necessarily decisive, reason to employ it in certain ways (Whiting 2009: 537). The same argument often takes the following form: that a word, or expression has conditions for its correct use, speaks in favor, or counts in favor of using it in a certain way. Among philosophers who believe that what this argument holds is true in quite an embarrassingly obvious way are Daniel Whiting (2007; 2009) and Ralph Wedgwood (2007) among others. It is interesting to notice that the considered argument builds on the favoring relation account of a normative reason, and its success in the debate over normativity of meaning, depends on the success of the very theory of a normative reason that underlies the argument in question. The philosopher who has brought the favoring relation account of a reason into the philosophical attention, and who contributed strongly to its upcoming fame was Thomas Scanlon in his seminal book What We Owe To Each Other (1998). In this paper I shall argue against the thesis that meaning is normative in the reason-implying sense by means of attacking the Scanlonian account of a reason. The idea behind my argumentative strategy is quite simple: if favoring relation account of a reason is the correct theory of a normative reason, then its applicability to the area of semantics should not be problematic. On the other hand, if we can prove that this account of a reason fails tout court, the thesis that the lexical meaning of an expression provides us with any reason to employ it in a certain way, will be untenable. Briefly, if the favoring relation account of a reason is a good theory of a normative reason, then, I contend, it is supposed to work when applied to any case at hand, be it from moral, epistemic or semantic field. It should be stressed that despite its initial appeal, the Scanlonian account of a normative reason has been the object of heavy criticisms in the recent years. The objections that have been raised against it revolve around the issues falling under three categories: conceptual, ontological and functional. According to a complaint belonging to the first category of the charges, it is far from clear why we would think that the notion of a reason is a notion intrinsically normatively loaded. What specifically stands in a need of explanation is why we would assume that whenever one encounters a reason, a normative relation between the considerations taken to be reason-giving and action, or attitude is to follow straightforwardly. The objection as it stands does not deny that the notion of a reason can be normatively interpreted, what it denies is rather that ‘a reason’ allows for one and only normative reading. The second objection touches the problem regarding the metaphysical status of the favoring relation, and recently it was meticulously discussed by Jonas Olson under the label of ‘the extensional fallacy’ (Olson 2011). Olson observes that the problem with this format of a normative reason account is that it generates theoretical commitments it cannot give account of. Briefly, if a reason is to be cashed out in terms of a favoring relation, then this favoring relation must be shown to be ‘real’, meaning it must refer to something in the world. The problem with the Scanlonian account is not that he understands a reason along the realistic lines, as something which as its extension has any natural fact, but rather that he leaves us in the dark when it comes to understanding what the relation of speaking in favor stands for. Finally, the last 1 objection takes as its target what is often regarded as perhaps the main advantage of Scanlon’s theory of a reason, namely its intuitive attractiveness. Scanlon seems to connect the intuitive appeal of his theory with the quietist assumption with regard to what a reason is on which it is based. In the opening statement of the first chapter of his book, he writes the following: I will take the idea of a reason as primitive. Any attempt to explain what it is to be a reason for something seems to me to lead back to the same idea: a consideration that counts in favor of it. “Counts in favor how?” one might ask. “By providing a reason for it” seems to be the only answer. So I will presuppose the idea of a reason, and presuppose also that my readers are rational in the minimal but fundamental sense that I will presently explain (Scanlon 1998:17). In his further considerations Scanlon does not elaborate on the feature of primitiveness that he ascribes to the notion of a reason, taking it probably as easily decipherable, or at least sufficiently suggestive to speak for itself. Since Scanlon’s account of a reason strikes me as neither intuitively compelling, nor true, I shall offer my own interpretation of the primitiveness at stake. For the purpose of my argument, I shall grant that the idea of a reason is primitive in the relevant sense, if it is graspable as such by an ordinary agent who is rational in Scanlon’s minimal sense of being rational. I shall also add two more “ifs” to my working definition of the primitiveness we are after. A reason is primitive in the relevant sense, if an ordinary agent who possess the idea of a reason in the primitive sense, thinks of this reason as straightforwardly related to action or attitude as Scanlon assumes, and if a consideration recognized as a reason does the job any normative reason is supposed to do, whatever the details of one’s favorite theory of a normative reason are. The last condition on a normative reason states simply that any normative reason to deserve that name, be it construed primitively or not, must fulfil three requirements: 1) explain why the agent has a normative reason for action, or attitude; 2) be effectively action-guiding in the sense of playing a certain role in the agent’s motivation, finally 3) offer a justification for action, or attitude that is of genuine help when an agent tries to work out what it is that she ought to do in similar circumstances in future. I grant that the above-mentioned conditions on a normative reason are pretty uncontroversial, insofar as we think of a normative reason through the function, or functions it is to serve in our thinking. Hence, a normative reason, on any account, I contend, must do well in any of the roles that are constitutive of it. The problem with a Scanlonian account of a reason, as I shall further argue, and quite aside from the conceptual and ontological worries it invites, which I will not discuss in the paper due to the limited space, is that it conflicts with the idea of primitiveness, which is supposed to be its cornerstone. The favoring relation account of a reason turns out to be neither intuitively evident for a creature’s being minimally rational in Scanlonian sense, nor workable. Its main flaw consists in its failure to satisfy the constitutive constrains on a normative reason. That’s for the general framework of my aim in the paper, now come the details. That the Scanlonian account of a reason does not work as a theory of a reason will be shown on the example of the normativist argument for the normativity of meaning. If semantic norm speaks in favor of a certain linguistic behavior, hence is a normative reason as the adherents of semantic normativism hold, then it must do the job of a normative reason, and satisfy the constitutive requirements on a reason I have put forward. The problem is that the bare fact about the meaning of an expression does 2 badly in the role of a reason. It neither explains why the subject applied the term correctly, according with its meaning, when she did so, nor genuinely guides the subject’s future uses of that term. Moreover, it is based on a controversial assumption that reasons are factive. Suppose for the moment that my objections are in place, and that meaning facts fail as candidates for normative reasons along the favoring relation format of a reason that semantic normativists argue for. That need not entail a devastating blow for the normativist position. Semantic norms may prove to be only apparent reasons on one theory of a normative reason, and true normative reasons according to some other. Anyway, we have quite a good deal of other theories of a normative reason, and perhaps one of them fares well as an account of a semantic normative reason. If that were the case, then our objection would turn out to be misaddressed. It would not threaten semantic normativism as a tenable view, but at best would demonstrate that the adherents of semantic normativism have chosen badly on the market of theories of a reason. However, I shall show that things are not so. Meaning norm fails in the role of reason also on the rival accounts of a reason as defended by Broome (2004), or Hieronymi (2005, 2011, 2012). What is wrong with it on these alternative accounts is that it proves to be either seriously explanatory defective (the Broomean account), or gives rise to the well-known the wrong kind of reason problem (Hieronymi). Taking all these things together, I shall conclude with an obvious observation that, if some alleged reason does not pass the test for being a reason as provided by the existing theories of a reason, then simply it is not a reason. Or, at least those who think otherwise failed terribly in their task of making us believe it is. References: Broome, J. (2004). ‘Reasons’. In: R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, M. Smith (eds.). Reason and Value. Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 28-55. Glüer, K., and Å. Wikforss. (2008). Against Normativity Again: Reply to Whiting, MS, http://people.su.se/%7Ekgl/Reply%20to%20Whiting.pdf Glüer, K., and Å. Wikforss. (2009). ‘The Normativity of Meaning and Content.’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaningnormativity/ Hattiangadi, A. 2009. ‘Some More Thoughts on Oughts and Thoughts: A Reply to Daniel Whiting.’ Analysis. Volume 69, Number 1: 54-63. Hieronymi, P. (2005). ‘The Wrong Kind of Reason,’ The Journal of Philosophy, 102 (9): 437-457. Hieronymi, P. (2011). ‘Reasons For Action,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 111: 407-427. Hieronymi, P. (2012). The Wrong Kind of Reason, Revisited (MS). Olson, J. (2009). ‘Reasons and The New Nonnaturalism’. In: S. Robertson (ed.). Spheres of Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 164-182. Scanlon, T. (1998). What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Wedgwood, R. (2007). The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Whiting, D. (2007). ‘The Normativity of Meaning Defended,’ Analysis 67: 130-140. Whiting, D. (2009). ‘Is Meaning Fraught With Ought?’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (4): 535-555. 3
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz