From Society to Self (and Back) Through Place: Habit in Transactional Context Malcolm P. Cutchin Key words: John Dewey, habit, place, landscape Abstract This argument extends the efforts of scholars of occupation and habit in several ways. It extends previous examinations of John Dewey’s perspective on habit by bringing to the forefront his view of the social and moral dimensions of habit in the context of his larger metaphysical ground-map. That view suggests a habit process involving the transaction of the social and the individual, with habit as central to that transaction. Dewey’s view is further enhanced with a portrayal of how it operates in the material experience of place and landscape. Examples from several scales of place are discussed to illustrate the essential role of material landscapes in this habit process. Using these analyses, the concept of rehabilitation is reconsidered. I have recently come to the conclusion that most of my social science colleagues and I have missed something important by overlooking the power and importance of habit in our subject matter. However, that criticism can be reversed to say that social and geographical aspects of experience play a more important and complex role in habits than has yet been realized by non-social science scholars. Although several scholars, particularly those who have presented arguments in this journal, such as David Swartz (2002), Kathy Charmaz (2002), Graham Rowles (2000), and David Seamon (2002), have articulated complex and useful social or geographical dimensions of habits, we must be honest: as a scholarly community, we have only begun to scratch the surface and meaning of those realms as they pertain to the habitual. As participants in the American Occupational Therapy Foundation conferences have recognized, the thinking on habit as a concept needs to continue, and it should do so by considering different perspectives on the concept and its implications. In this article, I attempt to bring several perspectives—philosophical, social theoretical, and geographical—to bear on the problem of habit and its significance. The ultimate goals are to provoke thought and to arrive at a synthesis that advances current thought on habit and on rehabilitation. I have several points to make along this path of provocation and synthesis. The first is to suggest how a Deweyan understanding of habit, in its broadest sense, allows us to view what are typically taken as personal predispositions (habits) more broadly as natural, social, transactive, and moral phenomena. Taking a transactional view allows us to focus on habit and its significance in a way that unifies it with individual, social, and material experience. The second point emphasizes the way that habits, perhaps the most taken-for-granted aspect of human life, cannot be fully understood without more careful consideration of how humans “in-habit” the natural world. A particular understanding of places—another taken-for-granted element of human experience—as cultural landscapes that are scalar in character clarifies how the mediation of self and society occurs and brings habits to the forefront of our thinking. If we think of ourselves as inhabiting places in the transactive sense that I suggest here, rehabilitation takes on a deeper and more extensive meaning. My third, briefer point suggests what the meaning of rehabilitation is in light of the argument presented, and what implications it has for personal well-being, Malcolm P. Cutchin, PhD, is Associate Professor, Division of Occupational Science, Department of Allied Health Sciences, School of Medicine, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill, North Carolina. Presented in part at Habit and Rehabilitation: Promoting Participation, January 31-February 4, 2007, Pacific Grove, California. Address correspondence to Malcolm Cutchin at [email protected]. 50S OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health society, and those who construct interventions to address either. The Transactional Nature of Habit Once known as America’s most significant philosopher (Hickman, 1998), John Dewey is one of the few theorists to take habit seriously as a foundation for understanding human action, experience, and meaning. Dewey’s well-known definition of habit as “an acquired predisposition to ways or modes of response” comes from his book Human Nature and Conduct.1 Dewey’s most important treatment of habit was issued in the same year as Adolph Meyer’s (1922) essay so often cited in the occupational therapy literature as a foundation for the profession. At least two dimensions of Dewey’s argument about habit in that text have been relatively overlooked in developing discourse on habit, occupation, and well-being. First, the subtitle, An Introduction to Social Psychology, is indicative of the in-depth treatment Dewey gave to habits as social or cultural phenomena that entail social relations, social classes, institutions, and customs. Dewey began and ended that book with a discussion of morals as a full component of habit and its significance. Both of these aspects, together with the larger and later shape of Dewey’s philosophy, are necessary to my argument here and will be introduced in due course. Dewey’s philosophy was, and remains, creative and full of potentialities. His anti-foundationalist (or anti-essentialist) worldview orients us to focus on process, the fallibility of knowledge, pluralism, and a critique of enlightenment philosophy. An overriding motive in Dewey’s work was the reconstruction of philosophy through, among other things, expunging what he called “the philosophic fallacy”: creation or acceptance of pervasive dualisms that effectively create a gap between philosophy and experience. Among these dualisms that Dewey discusses in his writings are subject/object, mind/body, ideal/material, science/common sense, ontology/epistemology, and knower/known. Although Dewey was consistent throughout his career in his critique of the philosophic fallacy, it was not until the last 25 years of his life that he clearly articulated what he called a “metaphysical ground-map.” It is important to note that Dewey did not interpret the term “metaphysics” in the same way as philosophers of his time. He strongly critiqued philosophical positions based on an a priori understanding of re1 Emphasis here and elsewhere is reproduced from the original source unless otherwise noted. Fall 2007, Volume 27, Supplement ality, such as materialism, idealism, empiricism, and logical positivism. Dewey was a “reluctant metaphysician” (Boisvert, 1998, p. 159) who did not feel entirely comfortable with the term “metaphysics” because it threatened a distancing from the world as experienced (Campbell, 1995). Garrison (2005) explained that Dewey’s “ground-map” was an intentional metaphor for his metaphysics used to describe the tool that enables inquiry about worldly experience. Dewey was first and foremost a philosopher, but he also was a social theorist. However, his social theory was built on his naturalistic metaphysics. Nature came to take such an important role in Dewey’s thinking that he viewed the human–nature relationship as a continuous, organic one from which sociality and human affairs emerged. This form of continuity became a key principle on which Dewey based his concept of experience. Dewey therefore saw experience as continuous and unified with nature, and it is from this relational continuity that all understanding of the world comes. He wrote that “experience is of as well as in nature. . . . Experience thus reaches down into nature; it has depth” (Dewey, 1929/1989, p. 4). A Deweyan scholar summed up the continuity of experience and nature in the following way: Nature has a life of its own, undergoing its own relatings, which in turn become what we experience. Our own transaction with the affairs of nature cuts across the givenness of nature and our ways of relating. This is how we experience what we experience (McDermott, 1973, p. xxv). Moreover, Dewey wanted to explain the consequence of these natural relations and transactions. We do not experience nature in a vague, abstract way. The world and our transaction with it are concrete and limited by space and time: In actual experience, there is never any such isolated singular object or event; an object or event is always a special part, phase or aspect of an environing experienced world—a situation. The singular object stands out conspicuously because of its especially focal and crucial position at a given time in determination of some problem of use or enjoyment which the total complex environment presents (Dewey, 1938/1986, p. 72). Situations are examples of the “qualitative unity of continuously developing experience,” as Alexander (1987, p. 105) stated, and they provide the specific and material context for understanding experience. Situations also provide a way to understand the social nature of selves in Dewey’s pragmatism. Our situations make us part of others’ worlds and socially connect us, to various degrees, with others. How- 51S ever, Dewey’s view of sociality is one that comprises more than social relations and networks. The social is pervasive in the formation of selves and action: The stuff of belief and proposition is not originated by us. It comes to us from others, by education, tradition and the suggestion of the environment. Our intelligence is bound up, so far as its materials are concerned, with the community life of which we are a part. We know what it communicates to us, and know according to the habits it forms in us (Dewey, 1922/1957, p. 287). Garrison (2002, p. 11S) translates this to mean that “culture has us before we have it.” Dewey hastened to make the social an integral part of the natural in his metaphysics: Upon the hypothesis of continuity. . .the social, in spite of whatever may be said regarding the temporal and spatial limitation of its manifestations, furnishes philosophically the inclusive idea. . . . [T]he ulterior meaning of the mental as well as the physical and vital is revealed in this form of associational interaction (Dewey, 1928/1984, pp. 45, 49). Near the end of his philosophical journey, Dewey characterized the combination of continuity and action in the world as “transaction” (Dewey & Bentley, 1949; Garrison, 2001). Consistent with his metaphysics, Dewey’s transactional view means that elements we are used to conceiving as separate from each other are really part of each other. More than being part of one another, things such as person and environment are considered co-defining and co-constitutive (Sullivan, 2001). Garrison (2001) argued that Dewey’s transactional view is based on the functional relationship between the person and the world. Those relations continually change through the ongoing transactions that occur or because of other uncertainties and instabilities inherent in a changing and changeable world. Much of the purpose of transaction, then, is to functionally coordinate or re-coordinate relations for the benefit of the entities that constitute it. For example, functional coordination is apparent in the way that a person and society may share a positive relationship (survival, adjustments, development) through processes of education, work, and leisure. Through those processes (relations), the person and society are co-constitutive. Dewey’s metaphysical ground-map was present, but not explicit, in his fullest theorization of habits in Human Nature and Conduct; it wasn’t until 3 years later, in Experience and Nature, that he articulated it in detail. Nonetheless, the natural, situated, social, and transactional senses of how he believes that habits arise, continue, and change can be gleaned from his 52S earlier text. Because Garrison (2002) has powerfully described much of this, my initial explanation will be truncated and derivative, but some unexplained aspects of Dewey’s ideas require further elaboration. As Garrison explained, Dewey’s theory of habit was tightly interwoven with his larger philosophy. In other words, Dewey did not depart from his metaphysical ground-map in his theorization of habit, and it is important to understand that ground-map to understand his view of habit. Garrison clearly depicts Dewey’s “organism-in-environment-as-a-whole” as coordinated by means of habits as functions. Habits are functions acquired from both natural and social dimensions of our habitats that provide the means to an end. They are social tools— “sub-functions of their habitat”—that are at the ready as potentialities and only actualized through transactional coordination with a situation. In this last sense, Garrison rightfully understands Dewey’s multiple senses of habit both as tools that are ready to use and as components of creative acts. All of these aspects of habit arise because of Dewey’s detailed and distinct metaphysical ground-map. Although Garrison’s argument is rich, powerful, and persuasive, he did not fully convey two important parts of Dewey’s position on habit that I must add here. First, Dewey makes it clear that institutions, particularly social customs, are what shape our individual habits. Although we often take our habits for granted or even fail to realize their power, our shared situations bring out similar predispositions that recreate previously existing customs. Dewey is clear about this point, and I quote him at length: The family into which one is born is a family in a village or city which interacts with other more or less integrated systems of activity, and which includes a diversity of groupings within itself, say, churches, political parties, clubs, cliques, partnerships, trade-unions, corporations, etc. If we start with the traditional notion of mind as something complete in itself, then we may well be perplexed by the problem of how a common mind, common ways of feeling and believing and purposing, comes into existence and then forms these groups. The case is quite otherwise if we recognize that in any case we must start with grouped action, that is, with some fairly settled system of interaction among individuals. The problem of origin and development of the various groupings, or definite customs, in existence at any particular time in any particular place is not solved by reference to psychic causes, elements, forces. It is to be solved by reference to facts of action, demand for food, for houses, for a mate, for some one to talk to and to listen to one talk, for control of others, demands which are all intensified by the fact already mentioned that each person begins [life] a helpless, dependent creature (Dewey, 1922/1957, p. 58). OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health In this one statement, Dewey packs numerous interrelated significances. First, entrenched social customs (collective habits) from the past create individual habits, not the other way around. Second, this process emerges in concrete, specifiable situations. Third, because custom has us before we have it, our minds and behaviors and, therefore, our relations with the social are fundamentally structured (although still co-constitutive) through the patterning of habits. Fourth, there is a source of power located at both the social and the individual through the basis of habits and their structuring. Taken together, we should understand Dewey as explaining a habit process and what habit is as a functional tool (Fig. 1). Because Dewey understands habits as the building blocks of all thought and action, including reflective, intelligent, creative action, this primordial, transactive relationship between the social and the individual becomes the most important we can conceive of if we are interested in any notions of meaning, choice, change, and a better world. Dewey is not about to leave habit at that, however. The continual interplay of the social and the individual in situations contains an ongoing tension. That tension is the moral dimension. Dewey puts it the following way: Reason, moral principles, cannot in any case be shoved behind these affairs, for reason and morality grow out of them. But they have grown into them as well as out of them. They are there as part of them. No one can escape them if he wants to. He cannot escape the problem of how to engage in life, since in any case he must engage in it in some way or other—or else quit and get out. In short, the choice is not between a moral authority outside custom and one within it. It is between adopting more or less intelligent and significant customs (Dewey, 1922/1957, p. 75). Dewey avoids the trap of human experience as fully structured. As strongly as he argues that the social conditions and limits us, Dewey also takes care to explain that the social generates the tools—habits—that allow us to act with the insight of morals to change the world. Dewey’s innovative insight about ethics was that they entail a situated use of general moral principles (Pappas, 1998). Perhaps less well understood is how he infused an understanding of habits with morals and vice versa. Swartz (2002) notes that Bourdieu’s concept of habitus has been compared with Dewey’s concept of habit and found remarkably similar. My reading of Bourdieu and Swartz leads me to agree, with the notable exception that Dewey’s view of habits is infused with an ethical tension and a concern for social reconstruction Fall 2007, Volume 27, Supplement Figure 1. The habit process. over and above the description of how habits arise and work in individuals and society. Place, Landscape, and Materialization of the Habit Process Place A ground-map is one thing; the ground itself is another. The concepts of the social, individual, and moral are abstract ideas, but we live and experience on the ground in material circumstances. What then, of the family in a village or city that Dewey mentions? We need to ask how the abstract social, habitual, and moral basis of experience happens on the ground or, in other words, in the real world. My contention in this section is that without understanding how, at least in part, the process of habits operates between the social and the individual through material places, we cannot really understand how we might concretely intervene to rehabilitate our affairs when things go wrong. A Deweyan understanding of place is somewhat different from conventional understandings. “Place” is the Deweyan sense of a situation—in an empirical manifestation—as the merging of the natural and the social in an area on the Earth’s surface. In one sense, place is the local, or nearby, situation, and even in an era of globalization, proximity is a key feature of relatedness. This is especially true if we consider social relations, practices, and institutions to be important—as they are in habit. Nevertheless, place also is shaped through situational relations and transactions with other places—economic ties, policy influence, or cultural media. All that goes on in our place is the basis of our situated experience, but place is also extensive beyond the area associated with it because of connections to other places. Moreover, place is durational in that the past is expressed in place. The place-as-situation, therefore, always includes local (within-place) transactions and transactions that extend to other places. Because of these and other 53S Figure 2. Place and landscape in the habit process. types of dynamism, place problems are always arising and serve as examples of what Dewey termed “problematic situations” (Cutchin, 2004a). This concept of place is difficult to understand, in part, because it suggests an unclearly bounded area or community. For instance, Houston, Texas, is not just Houston as we see it on the map. Houston is that area plus the manifold external influences that help to transform that area and experience in an ongoing manner, such as oil companies, Mexican immigrants, and Southern Baptist pronouncements. Furthermore, such places are always viewed as scalar. “Scale” is a corollary concept that denotes how places are nested within larger places. Humans experience those different scales of places at different times, or simultaneously, as place-to-place transactions are felt along with local experiences. For example, if you shop at a local Wal-Mart, you will share that experience with people from your community who are working and shopping there, but you also enter into transactions with management in Bentonville, Arkansas, as well as with the workers who originally produced the goods in China, Mexico, or wherever. Landscape Another, related way to consider places and place processes is through the framework of cultural geography. Cultural geography has traditionally focused on the bidirectional interaction of culture and environment that makes places. Humans are understood to have shaped their environments to survive and flourish, but they also needed to adjust to environmental challenges to try and establish a balance in the relationship. The outcome of that interaction is called the “cultural landscape,” the natural world around us that has transformed and been transformed by human activity in a continuous fashion. The cultural landscape is rich with symbolic meaning. Cultural geography has evolved with time, however, and additional understandings of the cultural 54S landscape have emerged. Schein’s (1997) work is of particular interest. He argues that the traditional view in cultural geography in which landscapes are interpreted as purely empirical (positivist) sources of information about a local or broader culture is useful, but problematic. Schein proposes that the landscape also provides a materialized discourse among varying institutions, groups, agents, and other sources of power, and that this discourse effectively creates a landscape that is written and overwritten in a fashion similar to a palimpsest. This more critical interpretation of cultural landscapes as discourse materialized is important to this argument because it provides a particularly good way to understand how place mediates the social conditioning of habit and resultant action (e.g., occupation) that affects the well-being of individuals and groups. The cultural landscapes of places are the statements of collective habits that, in many different ways, shape our individual habits and, thus, our experience in our ongoing transactions with place (Fig. 2). To use the earlier example, the old Houston is found in, over, and alongside the current Houston in the cultural landscape, in the form of buildings and neighborhoods, road networks, industrial zones, and so on. Some more concrete examples should help to convey this point and its variations more convincingly. Empirical Examples of Materialization of the Habit Process Several years ago, I conducted research on the role of community-based places of care for older adults (adult day centers and assisted living residences, in particular) in the experience of aging-in-place (Cutchin, 2003, 2004a; Cutchin, Chang, & Owen, 2005; Cutchin, Owen, & Chang, 2003). Among our findings from sites in Vermont and Massachusetts, we noted how each place of care entailed a unique sociocultural–physical milieu through which experience and habit were shaped. Although much of this insight was already present in earlier analyses, I am rethinking and recasting it here in terms of habit and landscape. In other words, the combined external and internal dimensions of those places created a material and symbolic landscape that mediated the social and individual habit process. The managing organization and the geographic setting (e.g., bucolic mountainside, town green, and lower-income urban neighborhood) are external influences on the place and landscape of each care setting. In addition, the buildings in which care is provided become an integral part of the habit process. Symbolism contained in the style of architecture and OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health the age and quality of buildings in which services are delivered are results of social customs that communicate meaning to those using them. One resident told me that she felt disgusted by the 100-year-old chiseled sign on her assisted living residence that said ‘‘Home for the Aged.’’ Although the residence was newly refurbished and plush on the inside, the old elements that remained on the outside retained a social custom that was offensive to some. It is plausible that others read this message, even if subconsciously, and in response formed habits of thought or behavior akin to 19th-century social notions of “the aged.” Each place of care sends messages—whether realized consciously and interpreted accurately or not—about social custom. Those landscape messages symbolize social custom and are taken up as habits of thought and behavior. The internal dimensions of care and residence places—the more proximal, micro-scale aspects of the landscape—also influence habit. A staff member at an adult day center explained her care place as a “non-institutional” environment that suffers from overcrowding: The physical setting just simply being less stainless steel and marble hallways. I think here, even though we’re a little crowded, if you look at the inside of the building it’s furnished pretty nicely, you know, we have nice wallpaper and nice woodwork. There are two points about this observation to note. One is about crowding—that people, their number, their characteristics, and their behavior are elements of the landscape, resulting from social processes and affecting habits. Crowding often leads to distractions and discomforts for older adults and challenges for staff, both of which direct habit formation and expression. The second point is that such interior landscapes can communicate “institutional” or homelike values and expectations that shape both care receivers’ and care providers’ habits. It probably needs no explanation, but in the same way that our homes differ from our workplaces, the difference in such landscapes of care communicate the social customs of that place and suggest different habits of feeling, thinking, and behaving. On a larger scale, places of great interest in current public health research—neighborhoods—can also be readily understood as landscapes that influence habit through the material manifestation of social institutions, customs, and resources. That is not to say that current researchers understand or use habit as important to their work—they do not. However, considering landscape and habit processes could be valuable. Two popular (and related) issues within the Fall 2007, Volume 27, Supplement neighborhoods and health literature, diet and obesity, can help illustrate this point. The primary premises of research on these issues are that neighborhood resources for a better diet (e.g., higher-quality groceries and less fast food) and more opportunities for exercise (e.g., sidewalks and lower crime rates) improve health and well-being. Research is finding such associations (Alter & Eny, 2005; Doyle, KellySchwartz, Schlossberg, & Stockard, 2006; GordonLarsen, Nelson, & Popkin, 2002; Morland, Wing, & Diez-Roux, 2006), but the “mechanisms” by which the associations occur are not yet understood. If we think of neighborhoods as landscapes that communicate social norms and thereby influence habit development and use, however, we can begin to fill this gap in understanding. It is not just that access to opportunities for a better diet and more exercise will make people in a neighborhood healthier; the habits of seeing, thinking about, and actually conducting acts of eating fresh fruits and vegetables or walking on a path in a park must be developed. The landscape must offer opportunities and expectations for such behavior, which then becomes habit. Without an array of interrelated, structured habits, the health outcomes will not follow. This is a social process that involves people embedded in a place and a landscape, as well as the extralocal forces that condition the location of such opportunities in a neighborhood. Local places and landscapes often are contingent on external forces, such as corporations or public institutions. Although we might prefer to be in control of structuring our places and landscapes to suit our needs, capital in other places may prevent us from having the landscapes we envision for ourselves. These landscape and habit processes also apply to what is perhaps our most common use of place, to denote a town or city. I would like to briefly illustrate additional dynamics of landscape and habit at this scale through my research experience with a stress and health study in Texas City, Texas (see Cutchin, 2007, for a more detailed explanation of the research and place). Texas City is an incorporated place along the Gulf Coast that is most well known for its large petrochemical refineries and the terrible explosion and loss of life that occurred in 1947—the worst industrial disaster in U.S. history. The landscape has largely been shaped by that event and the economic activity of oil refining. In that respect, like any place, the landscape becomes an articulation of local identity and thereby personal identity. Because of lack of space, I cannot go into more detail, but for more on this particular process, see Proshansky, Fabian, and Kaminoff (1983) and Rowles (1983). 55S In Texas City, the landscape is part of this identity—and habit—process in various ways. Several parks and other sites memorialize the events and lives lost in 1947. Another dimension of the landscape is the infrastructure of the refineries. They are visible from almost every part of the city and depict the productivity and basis for the town’s existence. That infrastructure also communicates the presence and connection to global corporations, such as British Petroleum. Other landscape features, such as a city water storage structure, display symbols to inspire citizens: All-American City status and a high school football championship. Such symbols of local pride are mixed with state and national patriotism through the display of Texas and U.S. flags seen throughout the landscape. What influences on habit do these landscape features have? In addition to influencing how residents think about their place and their identity as members of that place, the Texas City landscape promotes local pride—a focus on the good side of Texas City. In this way, the habit of thinking positively about the place—and its role in state and national affairs, as well as the global economy, as one of the largest producers of gasoline—is encouraged. The landscape also promotes positive thinking about the petrochemical firms that put so much money into the local treasury. The landscape message is equivalent to Chamber of Commerce statements, such as, “The petrochemical industry has been very kind to Texas City” (Texas City. . ., 2006). These elements of the landscape turn attention away from the risk associated with living near refineries; they suggest habits of denial. The landscape of Texas City communicates those positive social beliefs and values. Those messages, however, cannot be clearly separated from more negative messages that create correspondingly negative habits. Risk associated with living near massive facilities that are physically imposing, loud, visibly polluting, foul-smelling, and occasionally explosive is ever-present in the Texas City landscape. Habits related to this risk, worry, or fear can have effects on health and well-being. As one resident who has lived near the petrochemical plants for 32 years stated, “I think we’re sitting on a time bomb. . . . I think living here, next to this. . .It’s very dangerous. With those chemicals, you just don’t know what you’re around” (McDonald, 2007). A woman who lives in public housing near the plants in Texas City told a reporter, “I pray I can give this up. I want to move out of Texas City” (Timms, 2000). Another resident explained the experience of living in such a place (near the plants) this way: 56S They [refiners] say their flares [large towers that burn off excess combustibles from petrochemical processing]. . .can prevent accidents. Well, they sure do make a lot of noise, and I call the police and say they are disturbing the peace by having those flares rumbling and all that noise. . . . [M]y cyclone fence is all rusted from the chemical pollution. A lot of times the pollution is so bad, I have to turn the air conditioner off because of the smell that comes from the refineries. (Gross, 2005, p. 66) Habits of worry, fear, frustration, and complaining are types of coping behaviors, but stress and its sequelae are still likely. Other residents, particularly older adults, seem to be too attached to their place to leave. Rowles’ (1983) research on older adults in an Appalachian community is suggestive of how and why this process of attachment outweighs other rational reasons to move. The habit of staying in place, or believing that you have no other option, compounds the situation. One habit of thought in this context was alluded to by a resident: “At our age, where can you start over? What would you do? Where would we move? This house is paid for” (McDonald, 2007). It is difficult to disentangle more tangible barriers to action caused by habitual ways of thinking from other obstacles, but the problem in such a case is that the place has not created the social institution or custom that would encourage sufficient means (including habits) of response. The result is a population trapped in “landscapes of despair” (Dear & Wolch, 1987). It is no coincidence that racial and ethnic minorities, particularly African Americans, dominate these landscapes of despair near the petrochemical plants. Social customs of the past—segregation, location of public housing in undesirable areas, and location of working-class housing near the factories—play a large role in the Texas City landscape and in minority lives. Resulting habits of distrust, hopelessness, poverty, and so on are common in the predominantly African-American neighborhoods in Texas City. Bourdieu’s theory of habitus as generative of social hierarchies and self-fulfilling prophecies (Swartz, 2002) is pertinent in the context in which lower-class minority experience is structured this way. Similar to most other American towns and cities, however, collective habits or social customs push the rest of us to form the habit of accepting such situations as given and unchangeable. I think Dewey would agree that such landscapes or situations pose particularly vital moral problems. I will conclude this article by extending the argument to the concepts of rehabilitation and participation. OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health Rethinking Rehabilitation and Participation Places and landscapes are laden with past habits that provide the matter for current habits, but as with individual habits themselves, places and landscapes also are continually in the making—they are a central part of the ongoing transactions that bind people, society, and nature. Places and landscapes cannot be taken out of the equation; individuals or societies cannot exist without place, nor can we usefully consider them without considering place. If habits are the “ground-pattern” for all action and feeling, as Dewey suggested (Dewey, 1976), then the pattern on the ground—landscape—is the bedrock of the ground pattern.2 Such consideration, as Dewey argued, should include moral thinking. This logic leads us to the conclusion that the individual, the social, and place are fully implicated in habit and ethics. Because place is essential to an understanding of habit, place becomes moral by default. Although Dewey did not often write about place, he came to a similar conclusion: The best we can accomplish for posterity is to transmit unimpaired and with some increment of meaning the environment that makes it possible to maintain the habits of decent and refined life. Our individual habits are links in forming the endless chain of humanity. Their significance depends upon the environment inherited from our forerunners, and it is enhanced as we foresee the fruits of our labors in the world in which our successors live (Dewey, 1922/1957, p. 23). Dewey’s statement is profound because it folds into one process the individual, social, habitual, and ethical, and it integrates that process with a context that can be viewed as place or landscape. But what of crowded, institutional places of care for older adults? What of neighborhoods devoid of opportunities for exercise or places to buy healthy food? And what about landscapes of despair in the shadows of massive oil refineries? These are difficult situations faced by millions of people the world over. Dewey suggests that we should care because of the need for improvement, for growth for us and for others, but also because the future demands it. He also suggests that we can solve such problematic situations because “we are active participants in an unfinished and unfinishable universe” (Garrison, 2005, p. 835). But what should we do? The first step is to think more clearly about these situations as places in need of rehabilitation. Places and 2 I came to this motif of Dewey’s through the excellent work of Kestenbaum (1997). Fall 2007, Volume 27, Supplement Figure 3. Rehabilitation reconstrued using the habit process. landscapes are in the making—they are to be made and remade; we can intervene in places to improve them, to restore landscapes of despair into landscapes of hope. Changing place and landscape changes the social and, through that process, can positively influence habits, both individual and collective. Without rehabilitation of place and landscape, habits will continue as before, for better or worse—we cannot escape the social as it presents itself to us every day in the landscape. Such place rehabilitation, although difficult, is the most effective route to habit change and improvement in well-being. However, such action cannot be attempted without an understanding of habit, its foundations in the social, and the landscape as the product and medium of social custom and habit (Fig. 3). These concepts, as presented, are tools for critical thinking as we create new groundmaps for rehabilitation and participation. Conclusion The typical way of conceptualizing rehabilitation is to focus on the individual. Thinking about occupation has also focused primarily on the individual (Dickie, Cutchin, & Humphry, 2006). A Deweyan understanding of habit provides a powerful challenge to such thought. In my view, it compels us to consider that occupation, as complex as it may be, is constituted of habits that originate first and foremost from the social, and the social is encountered most significantly in the places and landscapes in which we live as a materialized discourse. These are not habits that make us automatons; they are abilities that are reassembled relative to the situation to act in the best way possible toward moral ends. This underpins an understanding of occupation as a transaction, where intervention or rehabilitation has new meaning. That meaning is most fully funded where the transactive individual–so- 57S cial relationship happens—in places and landscapes of experience. Habit, thus conceived, makes us moral participants in place processes before we even know it. The cultural landscape has us before we have it. Our moral responsibility for our successors is to rehabilitate our places and landscapes to enhance their occupations and well-being through the enhancement of their habits. To understand this is to begin to address our oversight of the power and importance of habit in life. Acknowledgments The author thanks Virginia Dickie for feedback on an earlier draft of this manuscript and Beccy Aldrich, Antoine Bailliard, and Sue Coppola for stimulating seminar discussion and insights on the concept of habit. Research reported in this article was funded by the National Institute on Aging (R15 AG17028) and the National Cancer Institute (P50 CA105631) grant for the UTMB Center for Population Health and Health Disparities. References Alexander, T. (1987). John Dewey’s theory of art, experience and nature: The horizons of feeling. Albany: State University of New York Press. Alter, D. A., & Eny, E. (2005). The relationship between the supply of fast-food chains and cardiovascular outcomes. Canadian Journal of Public Health, 96, 173-177. Boisvert, R. (1998). Dewey’s metaphysics: Ground-map of the prototypically real. In L. A. Hickman (Ed.), Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a postmodern generation (pp. 149-165). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Campbell, J. (1995). Understanding John Dewey: Nature and cooperative intelligence. Chicago: Open Court. Charmaz, K. (2002). The self as habit: The reconstruction of self in chronic illness. The Occupational Therapy Journal of Research, 22, 31S-41S. Cutchin, M. P. (2003). The process of mediated aging-in-place: A theoretically and empirically-based model. Social Science and Medicine, 57, 1077-1090. Cutchin, M. P. (2004a). Using Deweyan philosophy to rename and reframe adaptation-to-environment. American Journal of Occupational Therapy, 58, 303-312. Cutchin, M. P. (2004b). A Deweyan case for the study of uncertainty in health geography. Health & Place, 10, 203-213. Cutchin, M. P. (2007). The need for the “new health geography” in epidemiologic studies of environment and health. Health & Place, 13, 725-742. Cutchin, M. P., Chang, P. F., & Owen, S. V. (2005). Expanding our understanding of the assisted living experience. Journal of Housing for the Elderly, 19, 5-22. Cutchin, M. P., Owen, S. V., & Chang, P. F. (2003). Becoming “at-home” in assisted living residences: Exploring place integration processes. Journal of Gerontology: Social Sciences, 58B, S234-S243. Dear, M., & Wolch, J. (1987). Landscapes of despair: From deinstitutionalization to homelessness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 58S Dewey, J. (1957). Human nature and conduct: An introduction to social psychology. New York: The Modern Library. (Original work published in 1922). Dewey, J. (1976). Interpretation of savage mind. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey, The middle works, 1899-1924 (vol. 2, pp. 39-52). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work published in 1902). Dewey, J. (1984). The inclusive philosophic idea. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey, The later works, 1925-1953 (vol. 3, pp. 41-54). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work published in 1928). Dewey, J. (1986). Logic: The theory of inquiry. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey, The later works, 1925-1953 (vol. 12, pp. 1-529). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work published in 1938). Dewey, J. (1989). Experience and nature (2nd ed.). LaSalle, IL: Open Court. (Original work published in 1929). Dewey, J., & Bentley, A. (1949). Knowing and the known. Boston: Beacon Press. Dickie, V., Cutchin, M. P., & Humphry, R. (2006). Occupation as transactional experience: A critique of individualism in occupational science. Journal of Occupational Science, 13, 83-93. Doyle, S., Kelly-Schwartz, A., Schlossberg, M., & Stockard, J. (2006). Active community environments and health. Journal of the American Planning Association, 72, 19-31. Garrison, J. (2001). An introduction to Dewey’s theory of functional “trans-action”: An alternative paradigm for activity theory. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 8, 275-296. Garrison, J. (2002). Habits as social tools in context. The Occupational Therapy Journal of Research, 22, 11S-17S. Garrison, J. (2005). Dewey on metaphysics, meaning making, and maps. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 41, 818-844. Gordon-Larsen, P., Nelson, M. C., Page, P., & Popkin, B. M. (2006). Inequality in the built environment underlies key health disparities in physical activity and obesity. Pediatrics, 117, 417-424. Gross, Neal R. & Co. (2005). United States of America Chemical Safety and Hazard Investigation Board Public Meeting on BP Texas City Refinery Investigation, Thursday, October 27, 2005. Transcript accessed June 12, 2006, from http:// www.csb.gov/completed_investigations/docs/10.27. 2005CSBBPCommunityMeetingTranscript.pdf. Hickman, L. A. (1998). Introduction. In L. A. Hickman (Ed.), Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a postmodern generation (pp. ix-xxi). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Kestenbaum, V. (1977). The phenomenological sense of John Dewey: Habit and meaning. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. McDermott, J. J. (1973). John Dewey: A biographical sketch. In J. J. McDermott (Ed.), The philosophy of John Dewey (Vol. 1). New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons. McDonald, S. (2007, January 17). BP’s neighbors aware of danger. Galveston Daily News. Meyer, A. (1922). The philosophy of occupation therapy. Archives of Occupational Therapy, 1, 1-10. Morland, K., Wing, S., & Diez-Roux, A. (2002). The contextual effect of the local food environment on residents’ diets: The atherosclerosis risk in communities study. American Journal of Public Health, 92, 1761-1767. Pappas, G. F. (1998). Dewey’s ethics: Morality as experience. OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health In L. A. Hickman (Ed.), Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a postmodern generation (pp. 100-123). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Seamon, D. (2002). Physical comminglings: Body, habit, and space transformed into place. The Occupational Therapy Journal of Research, 22, 42S-51S. Proshansky, H. M., Fabian, A. K., & Kaminoff, R. (1983). Placeidentity: Physical world socialization of the self. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 3, 57-83. Sullivan, S. (2001). Living across and through skins: Transactional bodies, pragmatism and feminism. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Rowles, G. D. (1983). Place and personal identity in old age: Observations from Appalachia. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 3, 299-313. Swartz, D. L. (2002). The sociology of habit: The perspective of Pierre Bourdieu. The Occupational Therapy Journal of Research, 22, 61S-69S. Rowles, G. D. (2000). Habituation and being in place. The Occupational Therapy Journal of Research, 20, 52S-67S. Texas City shrugs off refining risks after 15 die at BP plant. (2006, April 27). Retrieved June 4, 2006, from http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news. Schein, R. (1997). The place of landscape: A conceptual framework for interpreting an American scene. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 87, 660–680. Fall 2007, Volume 27, Supplement Timms, E. (2000, October 3). Toxic traps: The Texas problem (series). Racial patterns. Dallas Morning News, A1. 59S
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz