Classical Receptions Journal Vol 9. Iss. 2 (2017) pp. 237–267 Direct democracy and the search for identity for colonized people: the contemporary meanings of C.L.R. James’s classical Athens Matthew Quest* C.L.R. James, author of The Black Jacobins, a historical study of the Haitian Revolution, is often seen as a paradoxical Pan-African activist with embarrassing Eurocentric tendencies. A major aspect of this perception is his perennial engagement with classical Athens. He regarded it as a model for direct democracy, which could inform workers’ self-management, and the search for identity among colonized people. These intellectual legacies began in Correspondence, an obscure Marxist journal in the US of the 1950s, and became the subject of global debate in the 1960s and 1970s. At the centre of the dispute was James’s insistence, to Black Power audiences, that classical Athens was the greatest civilization the world had ever known. Objections that classical Athenian civilization was characterized by slavery and exclusions of women obscure the fact that James always acknowledged the limits of Athenian society and implored his audiences to question their own elitism and improve on the direct democratic model for modern politics. Increasingly, the clash of so-called Western civilization and the Third World in the post-colonial era undermined the potential of James’s Athens as a productive thought experiment, although African American and Caribbean activists did try to grapple with this argument, and some found it valuable. Introduction Contemporary scholarship on ancient Greece and Rome is alert to attempts to appropriate the ideas, images, and cultures of the past in order to authenticate the present. It has been well demonstrated that classical Athens has been an important presence in the modern world variously used to underscore or oppose arguments for social and political change, and both to assert and challenge values and identities. The latest scholarship interrogates uses and abuses of the classical past, and analyses the complex dialogues between classical antiquity and the present.1 Particularly *Correspondence: Department of African-American Studies, Georgia State University. [email protected] 1 See some of the latest scholarship on the Classics concerned with the intersection of democratic, anti-racist, and colonial themes in the following edited volumes: Hardwick and Harrison (2013), Orrells, Bhambra, and Roynon (2011), Bradley (2010), Stephens ß The Author 2016. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] doi:10.1093/crj/clw010 MATTHEW QUEST sensitive in this field of inquiry are studies that have challenged Aryan models of the classical world in the spirit of the racial vindication of peoples of African descent. However, these studies also make clear that, for complicated reasons, decolonizing and de-racing the field of Classics is no easy task. C.L.R. James, often seen as a paradoxical Pan-African activist, with a perceived embarrassing Eurocentric disposition, especially by those he mentored in the Black Power era, approached the classical world somewhat differently. Scholars of James’s life and work disagree over how to evaluate James’s approach to race, and civilization, in the context of his professed Eurocentrism. John Bracey reminds us that James characterized himself as ‘a Black European in training, and in outlook’ without apology.2 Paul Buhle has seen James as paradoxical for being a PanAfrican with an appreciation for the Western classics. John Henrik Clarke and Yosef Ben-Jochanan view James as embracing Eurocentrism through his Marxism. While Farrukh Dhondy, in contrast to the former, seems pleased with this Eurocentrism, John McClendon sees James as a non-racialist whose Pan-Africanism was a constellation of political interests not so much an outlook on identity or culture. Paget Henry has argued that, over the long arc of his career, James struggled to shift his aspiring philosophical conception of heroic self-government from a Greek to an African identity.3 Almost all of these commentators appear to have a restricted sense of democracy compared to the highest ideals James developed in his politics. This should be kept in mind as we consider criticism of James on cultural and civilizational matters. Direct democracy and national liberation struggles C.L.R. James, native of Trinidad, best known as the author of The Black Jacobins,4 the classic history of the Haitian Revolution, is recognized as the mentor of prominent anti-colonial activists and post-colonial statesmen, such as Ghana’s Kwame Nkrumah and Trinidad’s Eric Williams, and is also recalled as an independent socialist. James wrote original visions of direct democracy and workers’ self-management. These culminated in Facing Reality (1958), a book very influential, not merely in Europe and the USA, but in the post-independence Anglophone Caribbean and among certain African-Americans engaged in post-Black Power movement criticism. Facing Reality argued not ‘since the Greek city-state’ had the world seen the proper combination of technology, access to information, and and Vasunia (2010), Goff and Simpson (2008), Hardwick and Gillespie (2007), and Goff (2005). 2 Bracey (1994: 53–54). Bracey recalls James’s lectures at Northwestern University in 1968 ranging from Aristotle, Aeschylus, and Sophocles to slaves in the Haitian Revolution and peasants in Julius Nyerere’s Tanzania. 3 Buhle (1994: 158–66), Dhondy (2001: x–xi, 42), Clarke and Ben-Jochanan (1991: 43–50), McClendon III (2005:15–19), Henry (2000: 47–67). 4 James (1963 [orig.1938]). 238 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS ordinary people ready to overcome elites, whether in the name of capitalism or communism, who wished to suppress a democracy based on popular councils and committees. This potential was exemplified by the Hungarian Revolution of 1956. Yet, Facing Reality had a bifurcated nature. The direct democratic politics were not written with peripheral nations or people of colour particularly in mind—for in 1958 James still accepted the nation-state, elite party politics, and representative government for the colonized first achieving full citizenship rights through popular mobilizations. But James never missed an educational opportunity to take a swipe at the absurdities of these hierarchical institutions and social relationships.5 Ken Lawrence explains that James imbued in his followers an appreciation for autonomous and spontaneous labour movements in modern industrial nations and colonial revolt in peripheral nations. Yet he failed to reconcile these movements in one organization dedicated to world revolution as he wished and this mutual appreciation could be a thin sentiment. This was a result of many Black Power era activists having a concern with blind spots of the white American and European working classes, and Third World nations (but also those in more imperial positions) only being understood at a distance through great personalities above society and vulgar political economy.6 Eusi Kwayana illustrates that Caribbean colleagues were not necessarily bothered by James’s affinity for the direct democracy of Athens. James’s European cultural references did not disturb for he could speak credibly about Africa as well. Kwayana and others of the African Diaspora were inspired by James’s direct democratic vision and applied this to post-independence politics. Still, Kwayana argues, it is mistaken to assume that James was inconsistent if he did not always apply the same political perspectives to imperial centres and underdeveloped territories.7 Aware of these contours, it has been among my research projects to interrogate the contours of direct democracy and national liberation in James’s political thought. This has meant centring James’s direct democratic politics for the first time in scholarly literature, and documenting where people of colour, inspired by James, fostered a vision of popular self-management. Yet upon further examination, and consistent with Kwayana’s own experience as documented in his The Bauxite Strike and the Old Politics, it is apparent that popular self-emancipation and self-determination were often defined in such a way that race vindication trumped a deeper sense of Black labour’s autonomy at the post-independence moment.8 There was a widespread desire to prove that middle and professional classes of colour were equal to the tasks of elite representative government as defined by the retreating colonizer. This sentiment could not evaporate overnight, and was far more of a historical breakthrough for most (the defeat of white supremacy—one form of hierarchy) than the critique of hierarchical government in itself. James’s Athenian criticism about 5 6 7 8 James, G.L. Boggs, and Castoriadis (1958: 66–68). Lawrence (2013: 138–76). Kwayana (2013: 199–227). Quest (2013a: 374–91) and Quest (2013b). 239 MATTHEW QUEST the limits of representative government for those in the process of experiencing colonial freedom or civil rights for the first time, was perhaps rooted in classical references, but was attempting to prefigure the next democratic breakthrough. Movements of wildcat strikes, in factories and fields, animated by visions of direct democracy and workers’ self-management among people of colour and the formerly colonized in the African world, did emerge in the 1970s. It is only in recent years, however, that historians have begun to pay serious attention to these trends.9 James had difficulty teaching about Athens as a direct democratic model, both because it was seen as a ‘white’ model, but also because many anti-colonial radicals saw colonized and post-colonial wage labour as people to be managed but not people who could directly govern. This was a conceit that could be found in many forms of Black Nationalist aspiration and Marxist economic planning whether Athens was present as a thought-experiment or not. C.L.R. James and George G.M. James It is instructive to compare and contrast C.L.R. James’s recourse to the classics with that of another Caribbean scholar, George G.M. James, a native of Guyana and an intellectual forerunner of contemporary disputes between Afrocentrism and the Western classics. George G. M. James proposed a ‘stolen legacy’ thesis, in which he argued that there were uncredited borrowings from Africa by the Greeks and that white supremacist doctrine had further played down and obscured cultural exchange between ancient Greek civilization and ancient African civilizations.10 Although C.L.R. James mobilized classical Athens in very different ways, I would like to suggest that James’s direct democratic interpretation of Athens belongs to a larger history of Black Nationalism to the extent it has also contributed to the search for identity among colonized people. George G.M. James’s Stolen Legacy, raises an unexamined historical problem at the centre of African-American popular history. If Greece borrowed aspects of philosophy, religion, art, and intellectual culture from Egypt, the mere fact of Egyptian provenance does not necessarily recommend these ideas and systems to modern black nationalisms and identity formations. Notwithstanding these tensions, before the official turn to Black Studies, Africana Studies, or Classical Reception Studies as mainstream trends in scholarship in university life, George G.M. James wished to establish that African peoples should be concerned with the role of affirming their own cultures for identity and community formation. At the 9 Quest (2015: 132–62), Edwards (2014), Quest (2013c: 105–32), Kwayana (2012). In all of these sources evidence can be found of peoples of African descent engaging James’s direct democratic legacy and awareness of his premise that ‘every cook can govern’. Plys (2016: 1–27) has recently surveyed workers’ self-management as a broad historical trend in the Third World in the years 1952–1979. 10 See G.G.M. James (1988) and Crawford (2004: 111–35). 240 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS contemporary moment George G.M. James is also revered by those interested in ancient Kemet as a basis of a moral philosophy which observes nature.11 For all the differences, between these two Jameses from the Caribbean, C.L.R. James did not appear to be concerned with George G.M. James’s specific project of cultural nationalism in his Athenian meditations. In the first volume of Black Athena, Martin Bernal located George G.M. James among the ‘old scrappers’, including Jacob Carrouthers and Chancellor Williams, who contributed to underlining the problems of race and civilization in intellectual history.12 C.L.R. James exists uneasily but genuinely among race vindicationists, and is appreciated for his anti-colonial nationalism. But he is perhaps the most original Marxist dissenter of peoples of African descent, and as he was dedicated to founding his own autonomous doctrine in that field with his colleagues, he is a foundational pillar of Black radicalism. Patrice D. Rankine has argued that, so long as imperial forces seek to degrade the colonized, in terms of race, colour, and civilization, the study of classical receptions will have to grapple with the various nationalisms, whether imperial or anti-colonial, which have appropriated Greek and Roman classics.13 Michele V. Ronnick, the scholar of Black classicist William Sanders Scarborough, notes that African American engagement with the classics was not approached, even in the nineteenth century, without doubts as to whether peoples of African descent could or even should study Greek and Latin. Further they did not see such engagement as imitation of white schooling for they were aware of whites who had poorer schooling than themselves and even no schooling despite Black people’s social subordination.14 This is an appropriate consideration for C.L.R. James’s colonial education in the Caribbean, though lingering thoughts of British civilization’s link to the Western canon still shadowed him until his first trip to the UK in 1932. In Selwyn Cudjoe’s Beyond Boundaries, a study of nineteenth century intellectual trends in the colonial Trinidad into which C.L.R. James was born, the popular press often took up the critical framework of Socrates and an Athenian philosophical type which appeared dedicated to exposing shortcomings of society.15 11 See Moses (1998) for a sympathetic treatment of African-American popular history by an outstanding scholar of African-American intellectual history. Popular history is not public history, the history of popular culture, or intellectual history as most academics know it. Rather it is a discourse which intersects marginal scholars often with a community base larger than university scholars, social movements, and street organizations. It is remarkable how what in one generation is considered beyond the boundaries of acceptable academic discourse later becomes grandfathered in as a plausible perspective which must be engaged. 12 Bernal (1987: 401, 435–36). 13 Rankine (2011: 40–56). 14 Ronnick (2006: xxvii). 15 Cudjoe (2003: 221). 241 MATTHEW QUEST These seemingly disparate commentaries, taken together, tell us of historical problems often neglected for understanding James as the purported paradoxical Pan-African who engaged the classics. Where people of colour and the colonized were placed outside the trappings of civilization and self-government, and where these latter were constructed in European terms, sustaining the deportment of selfreliance meant mastering traditions institutionally placed outside one’s authority. While having to search for one’s identity hidden in the colonizer’s models of the world could be a false start for Black autonomous aspirations, James’s audacity was always greater. James speaking of Athens’s relevance to workers and the colonized search for self-government, his race vindication project (to the extent he always consciously had one) was telling Europeans they misunderstood the democratic heritage of their own civilization, and as a result it was in decline. The consequence was not simply the degradation of the colonized. Europeans, explained James, with thin understandings of Athens, had also falsified their own heritage and degraded their own human capacities (the democratic potential of the working class).16 Lorna Hardwick approaches the issue of classical receptions in a different but complementary way to Rankine, Ronnick, and Cudjoe, and offers a pertinent reexamination of the concept of ‘democracy’ in the context of classical reception. Reception studies must begin to challenge the idea that these texts have produced a singular ‘meaning’ no matter who or what project appropriates them, and their intended ethic. James originally proposed to posit ‘the contemporary meaning’ of classical Athens. Yet even within that project’s own legacies there was consciously, even for James, more than one contemporary meaning. In most instances, whether fascist or anti-colonial, those who ascribe authoritative meanings to their identities and civilizations through the classics desire to fuse visions of self-government with notions of high culture which may also have repressive connotations. Further, the writings of the classical world also invented myths and created identities for themselves, which however attractive, can be revealed as less than democratic. Therefore, we cannot simply be concerned with classical legacies as stolen or appropriated. Consequently, democratizing James’s black radical interpretation of Athenian democracy is an intricate task. Hardwick reminds us that the classical world’s authors and their archaic texts were preoccupied with manufacturing authenticity, especially where democracy 16 It is crucial to understand that consistent with James’s The Black Jacobins, Beyond A Boundary and Minty Alley, he is concerned with vindicating the self-emancipating capacity of all toilers and he created narratives that focused on marginal workers of colour specifically. Within this project, James’s anti-racism never discards the white working class as permanently damaged. He believed all human beings are not what they should be, for society is organized improperly. But they bring their limitations to freedom struggles and are transformed by them. James’s Athenian narratives are about reminding readers that government in the modern world is not organized properly for self-directed liberating outcomes to flourish. 242 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS appears to be a concern. For projects of self-government engaging these historical and literary materials can be both inspiring and paper over exclusions.17 Hardwick’s insight is crucial for this study, for where James constructs or claims essences of direct democracy and colonial freedom in, or inspired by the classical world, he may be found to be both creative, rooted among authoritative scholarship for his generation, and still imprecise. Several scholars have addressed James’s dialogue with the classics. Emily Greenwood has examined C.L.R. James’s and Eric Williams’s contrasting approaches to Athens in Trinidad’s anti-colonial politics; Kent Worcester has seen Athens’ role in James’s engagement of the Western canon as an opportunity to reflect on a way of seeing popular government that is in decline; and Frank Rosengarten has inquired about James’s Athens as primarily an aesthetic meditation preoccupied with Aristotle’s poetics. By using primary sources and archives, this article will offer a more thoroughgoing analysis of the activist political context for James’s famous interpretation of Athenian democracy.18 We shall examine the contours of James’s use of ‘Athens’ as a trope for his advocacy of both direct democracy and movements against empire. In a certain way the aesthetics of Athenian selfgovernment is a school for designing a society in the present. We will explore more closely how James’s discourse emerged from within his small revolutionary organizations and influenced radical social movements and hitherto unexamined contours of intellectual history. We will copiously document the secondary scholarship that helped construct James’s Athenian project from the 1920s to the 1940s, and suggest some more contemporary critical outlooks which might help us to rethink some of James’s assumptions. Athens: thought experiment and political project C.L.R. James approached classical Athens as a thought-experiment that could reinvigorate radical social movements in search of workers’ self-management and a liberating identity for colonized people. Mobilizing what he knew of democracy in classical Athens, James used narratives of its history and culture as devices for meditating on popular self-government. The self-emancipation of labor and freedom from empire became evolving tropes and interpretations of ‘Athens’ which James and his partners-in-conversation struggled to reconcile. While the exclusive qualities of Athenian democracy of the fifth century BCE were enabled by imperial rule over other Greek states, unfolding tensions in the dialogue were of more contemporary concern. What began as a small article on Athens in Correspondence, an obscure journal of a small Marxist group in the USA led by James in the 1950s in the transitional period from the Age of the 17 Hardwick (2013: 15–32). See also Hardwick (2003). 18 Greenwood (2010: 188–225), Rosengarten (2008: 178–81), Worcester (1992: 215–16). 243 MATTHEW QUEST CIO to the Third World national liberation epoch, became the basis for arguments in the Black Power and Caribbean freedom movements of the 1960s and 1970s.19 As intellectual and social movement history moved forward in the twentieth century there were shifts for many in the importance of emphasizing class, race, and gender as lenses to observe the past and present. We must also be aware that while there is a substantive basis for James concluding that there was direct democracy in classical Athens, ‘every cook can govern’ is also a notion he took from Lenin, and the latter fused this with a strategy for how the Bolsheviks could retain state power. For C.L.R. James, classical Athens of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E. is a city-state increasingly distinguished by an integrated humanism and an enlarged concept of citizenship. As recorded in his famous essay and pamphlet Every Cook Can Govern, Athens was a direct democracy of popular councils and assemblies taking responsibility for economic planning, judicial and military affairs, foreign policy, and educational and cultural matters as well. The vast majority of government officials engaged in these organizational forms were chosen by a random process of ‘sortition’ (selection by lot).20 This mode of governance was also distinguished by a high level of scrutiny and accountability for conduct in office. James interpreted this as a process of instant recall. For James, classical Athens was a conscious rejection of representative government. In James’s account, there were ‘no experts’ and no group was given the status of a professional class above society.21 19 C.L.R. James, with Raya Dunayevskaya and Grace Lee Boggs, led the Johnson-Forest Tendency (1940–51) of the American Trotskyist movement. At the most their collective had 75 members at any one time. In 1951 they became the Correspondence group and started a periodical by the same name. Dunayevskaya split and founded the News & Letters group in 1955 taking half the organization. C.L.R. James, Selma James, and Martin Glaberman led a faction that split with the Correspondence Group, now led by James Boggs and Grace Lee Boggs, to form the Facing Reality group (1962–70). The following are selected publications from some of the collective’s other members. Dunayevskaya (1998 [orig. 1958]), G.L. Boggs (1999), Glaberman (2002), J. Boggs (2011), S. James (2012). While James’s first American sojourn was as an underground man and an illegal immigrant during the Age of the CIO (1938–53), his second American sojourn was as a public intellectual, professor, and elder mentor of the Black Power and Black Studies movements (1969–79). Two important projects bridge these periods. He engaged Trinidad party politics and the project of Caribbean federation (1958–62, 1965–1966). This was also the period where he celebrated Ghana’s independence but increasingly offered public criticism of Kwame Nkrumah, whom he mentored as a youth. His theorizing of direct democracy and workers’ self-management (1947–58), where Athens was a later constituent element, began to fade as the search for identity for colonized people was increasingly underscored. The irony was that as Athens shifted to a metaphor for Caribbean nationalism in James’s speeches, soon the Caribbean New Left generation (1968–83) re-appropriated aspects of James’s Athenian direct democracy for post-independence politics. 20 James (1992: 8). 21 Ibid., pp. 9, 11. 244 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS Athenian direct democracy was marked by its professed ethic of social equality and the claim that anyone who did not wish to directly participate in political life was foolish.22 James observes the contributions of personalities like Solon, Cleisthenes, and Pericles to advancing the democracy. Yet he takes special notice of the emergence of ordinary artisan craftsmen and the power of rowers in Athens’ emerging Navy, and ‘the proletarians’ at the port of Piraeus.23 Nevertheless, slaves and women were excluded from the status of citizenship, and we may question whether the majority of Athenians with citizenship status actually directly governed. It is mistaken to suggest that James did not think the status of women and slavery blemished classical Athens. Still, he insisted that the Athenian city-state was the greatest civilization the world had ever known. This is a bold claim based on the totality of the framework of ‘civilization’, an assessment of a society based on notions of progress, culture, and development which are almost always exclusionary. Yet James’s essay Every Cook Can Govern, which was first published in Correspondence in June 1956, actually had its origins in a contribution to his political organization’s internal bulletin a year before.24 It was explicitly part of a study intended to give added philosophical and historical justification to his autonomous Marxist group’s rejection of the vanguard party. Later it became a part of discussions among the Caribbean and African Americans in the Black Power and PanAfrican movements. Let us examine James’s original intentions more closely. An accurate historicizing of James’s Every Cook Can Govern requires an engagement with contemporary literature on classical Athens, and scholarly works that influenced James in the first half of the twentieth century. It also requires acknowledgment of ambiguities and discontents he had with the classical world even as he undoubtedly was quite fond of it. James’s early imperfect Athens: clashing with slavery and African civilization In a documentary on his autobiographical memoir Beyond A Boundary (1963), produced by Mike Dibb, James argued that Athens, as he received it as a young colonial student in Trinidad, and an instructor at Queens Royal College in the 1920s, gave him a vision of an integrated whole: the people appearing to directly govern, the Olympic Games, and Greek tragedy. If James went back in time and visited that society on the ground, he knew certain currents found there would not please or amuse. But the Athens in his mind’s eye gave him critical foundations for imagining a new self-emancipating society to build on.25 22 Ibid., p. 9. 23 Ibid., p. 30. 24 See ‘The Continuation of Democracy in Greece’ in the awkwardly labelled ‘Bulletin: Vol. I.’ Dated 26 July 1955. It is a six page manuscript. It essentially is the first draft of what became ‘Every Cook Can Govern’. C.L.R. James Collection. Schomburg Research Library, New York City, NY. 25 James (1992), Dibb(1976). 245 MATTHEW QUEST James’s critical engagement with classical antiquity is evident in an episode uncovered by Christian Høgsbjerg’s C.L.R. James in Imperial Britain, involving a public dispute in 1933 between the art critic Stanley Casson, an expert on Greek art who condemned an African art exhibition in Britain as backward and childish, and the supposed Eurocentric James, who thrashed Casson for not understanding the most cutting-edge anthropology or art criticism which reflected well on African self-governing and civilizational capacities.26 James’s concern with the public manipulation of Greek ideals and the story of Greek slavery appeared in his political journalism more than a decade before Every Cook Can Govern. In a polemic with Max Lerner, author of his own study of American civilization, James seemed to chastise Lerner on the same basis for which he would later be criticized himself. James argued: ‘Democracy is of many kinds. In Greece, in its best days, there was truly a wonderful democracy – if you were a free man. The famous Greek democracy rested on the merciless exploitation of hundreds of thousands of slaves.’ James takes Lerner to task for calling Greek slave owners ‘basically democratic’ as part of a larger discourse on contemporary politics in Germany: ‘That is exactly what they were not. They were basically slaveowners, just as the democracies of Britain, France, and America were and are ‘‘basically capitalistic’’ ’.27 Could James have a valid basis for reversing this claim? Was he being opportunist here? His evolving studies of Athens may have led him to see more contours in the history. Athens as Hegelian social motion: a philosophy of history In correspondence of August 9 and 18 of 1948, with his second wife Constance Webb, later the first biographer of Richard Wright, James reveals he was studying closely Michael Rostovtzeff’s A History of the Ancient World (Vol. 1), which focused on ‘the Orient and Greece’.28 This is remarkable for our meditation on the sources which contributed to Every Cook Can Govern for a number of reasons. First, James was working on his Notes on Dialectics in 1947–48. This study of the intersection of Hegel and Lenin as applied to revolutionary history and international labour movements was rooted in speculation on the historical leaps by popular movements. These leaps were most often ruptures with hierarchy and domination and presented in embryo new phases of political economy, democracy, and socialism not generally associated with the historical epochs in which they emerged. Consequently, aspects of ‘direct democracy’ and ‘socialism’ were found in the Puritan Revolution and French Revolution by James as expressed in spontaneous popular mobilizations and upheavals.29 26 Høgsbjerg (2014: 71–74). See also Casson (1922). 27 James (1943: 4). 28 James (1996: 319–21). These James letters to Constance Webb were of 9 and 18 August 1948. 29 Quest (2016: 105–31). 246 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS It may disturb observers that in classical Athens James might have found a hidden depth to a direct democracy or a latent essence of socialism which that stage of political economy could never have produced, as measured by a post-scarcity modern welfare state. But, for James, the essence of socialism was surfacing as a direct democracy, not a modern political economy of a certain type. Thus James spoke of the limits of the socialism Athens could have possibly produced in economic terms. In his reading of the intellectual legacies of Rostovtzeff, the Marxist ancient historian G.E.M. de Ste Croix points to aspects of Rostovtzeff’s reading of classical antiquity that remind me of James’s reading of classical Athens. A History of the Ancient World had a way of illuminating contemporary political challenges by a speculative reading projected onto the classical world as Hegelian essences which were yet to come to fruition but were nonetheless present. De Ste Croix, while aware that contemporary historians of an empiricist bent rejected such speculative philosophies of history, and not uncritical of Rostovtzeff while focusing primarily on the latter’s treatment of Rome, offers a subtle rebuke to those who might reject his methods. In de Ste Croix’s argument, if modern ideologies are not present in the classical world it does not mean that ‘the unconsciousness of it, or complete lack of interest, is the same as absence of ideology’. Both de Ste Croix and James make similar warnings against those who decry teleology: just because the lives of working people or oppressed people have no transparent ideology doesn’t meant they desire their lives to have no meaning at all. Objectivity often is merely acceptance of the prevailing ideology with which we have been raised transposed onto our historical studies.30 James’s Every Cook Can Govern suggests that it was astonishing that, given the power of the assembly in classical Athens, they never attempted to carry out socialist doctrines. Still whatever they might have attempted may have had a limited economic basis.31 What are we to make of these seemingly countervailing tendencies in James’s analysis? These seem strange projections for economic history given a society which was primarily rooted in what has been assumed to be slavery and feudal modes of production. But James learned from Rostovtzeff that not merely commerce but ‘capitalism’ was present in that society. It may seem peculiar to us but according to Rostovtzeff, mass production in factories was present ‘but the factory system was never adopted’. This implies a combined and uneven development as a transitional process. Industrial activity in Athens was based predominantly on slave labour. Slaves also participated in trade and banking. Through Rostovtzeff, James concludes that the Athenian slave had an essentially proletarian experience, in a political economy designed not to favour them (though James wished to see the democracy as affirming). Rostovtzeff and James conclude that most Athenian slaves generally lived like 30 de Ste. Croix. (1998: 33–34). 31 James (1992: 23, 31). 247 MATTHEW QUEST the rest of the population, certainly not as an especially degraded caste.32 The transition to capitalism was made easier by the existence of slavery in classical Athens, something Atlantic World scholars generally accept for modes of production over two thousand years later, and that capitalist enterprise was limited by the state. Rostovtzeff even speaks of the ‘socialist tendencies’ of classical Athenian government in the fourth century BCE.33 Frank Rosengarten has noted that James travelled to Greece in the Fall of 1954 and this sparked some aesthetic meditations on sculpture but also a sense of the integrated nature of that civilization.34 But James was not merely concerned with art, but the politics and journalistic methods of his revolutionary organization. Athens and the vanguard party In a letter of 26 July 1955, six pages in length, we see a partial draft of Every Cook Can Govern, which was originally published in Correspondence the following June. But it was not merely the narrative that we have come to know, for in the letter didactic commentary about revolutionary political organization is found among the crisp fragments of concise Greek history. James was working out perspectives which continued his journey beyond the vanguard party idea towards a condemnation of representative government and advocacy of direct democracy as the basis of social revolution for the 1950s. The following passage of the letter should not be misread as boorish but marked by reference to a Hegelian dialectical discourse with which his comrades were familiar. Let me repeat, for you may think you understand this and that you accept it. In reality you don’t. The conception is too foreign to modern thought and also too easily misrepresented. The Greeks did not say and did not think that anyone could write plays like Aeschylus. They did not think that anyone could be a philosopher like Aristotle. They did not think that anyone could be a political head of state like Pericles. But. . . as far as the daily administration of the government was concerned, something which was not the work of an artist or a genius, but ordinary everyday affairs, every man was as good as any other man; and in particular, the judgment of a lot. . . or a section of ordinary men chosen to represent the community, was better than that of any single individual, however gifted. . . and certain to be less mischievous. 35 This passage has many contours. In certain respects, James reminds his comrades in the Correspondence group that they do not really understand or accept a society could do without representative government. Yet James also reminded them of the 32 33 34 35 Rostovtzeff (1945: 289–91). Ibid., 316–18, 320. Rosengarten (2008: 189–90). James (1955: 1). C.L.R. James Collection. Schomburg Research Library, New York, NY. This letter was labelled ‘Bulletin: Vol. I Continuation of Democracy in Greece’ but it does not appear to be part of a conscious series or internally consistent journal. 248 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS fluidity of Hegel’s categories of cognition where essences of historical things disappear and reappear. James also underlines the point that the Athenian civilization was marked by artistry and genius which were achievements of great individual personalities. So he was not emphasizing, as he would elsewhere, that there was creativity among ordinary people for political leadership. What we see then is that James is interpreting direct democracy in Athens as a process of government and administration where citizens could not make policy but could judge it. There is a type of carry-over of James’s Leninism, where the judgment of popular councils of citizens could exist side by side with the state power or city-state. Simultaneously, James insisted that government did not need experts. Greek history was an archive for meditation where contemporary politics could be formulated. James insisted there was something in the Greek model which could help his revolutionary organization capture American proletarian sentiments when these insights were applied to how Correspondence was edited in 1955. James continued: That is the stage of society at which we have reached today [1955]. What we have to smash to pieces [is this] idea that the ordinary man can only vote for people to represent him but the actual work of government must be done by experts. That is the enemy. And that is why we have to absorb and internalize; and get rid of this fetish of representative government so that we, who produce the paper, can begin to think in terms of direct democracy. Don’t worry so much about convincing other people. Convince yourselves first and the rest will follow.36 We must note James’s prescribed methodology. One did not do political education, agitation, and propaganda work to raise consciousness. Rather, the revolutionary who mediates uprisings and enhances others’ politics had to get their own mind right. Instead of seeing themselves as a vanguard, his comrades had to develop a method consistent with the belief that every cook could govern. Still, James reminded his group that while they wanted to project direct democratic perspectives, this should not be taken as an endorsement of anarchy or direct democracy as a process inside his Leninist organization. And by the way, do not commit the foolishness of believing that what applies to the varied classes. . . occupations. . . personalities of a city, which is an economic entity, also applies to thirty people. We have some very intelligent people among us, but that does not prevent an idiot in the modern, not the Greek, sense, turning up every now and then, and turning up in the person of the very intelligent.37 It appears that James believed direct democracy could work in a small Athenian citystate (even a large country like the USA), because while it was too technologically primitive to produce a socialist economy, it had a cross section of classes and talents to draw on to produce this integrated humanism rupturing with representative 36 Ibid., p. 2. 37 Ibid., p. 3. 249 MATTHEW QUEST government. In contrast, for James, a small revolutionary political organization needed to be centrally directed. But if we read James’s further commentary in the letter carefully we see an overlap between his account of Greek history, his advocacy of direct democracy, and his Leninism. It is not the break with representative government James claims it to be, even if we account separately for who was excluded from the Greek polity. James Boggs, an African-American autoworker with Alabama sharecropper roots, who later with his wife Grace Lee Boggs, the Chinese-American philosopher, profoundly influenced the Black Power movement in Detroit, in an unpublished ‘Worker’s Report’ of 1956, detailed ordinary toilers’ reactions to the Correspondence newspaper during the Cold War. Boggs, mentored by C.L.R. James, felt his popular approach to classical Athens, Herman Melville, and Shakespeare were equally valuable. C.L.R. had shown ordinary people were decisive for the development of direct democracy in Athens and Boggs felt such concise treatments should be the model for their circle’s historical and political journalism. Yet Boggs also noted that the workers with whom he came in contact in Detroit factories and neighbourhoods asked why to focus on democratic origins in Greece. Why couldn’t the philosophical meditation have been on Egypt or China?38 Historical problems of slavery and civilization Though he must have been aware of C.L.R. James’s essay and views on Athens, Orlando Patterson, author of the critically acclaimed Freedom in the Making of Western Culture and a member of the famous London study group with James of 1964–65, which included Walter Rodney, did not address Every Cook Can Govern in his volume which analysed how liberty came to be constructed in Western culture and Athens in particular. However, Patterson is in complete disagreement with an apparent Jamesian notion. Freedom may be the character of the non-slave population in Athens but cannot be attributed to the city-state as a whole. Patterson asserts that the condition of slaves and women in Athens could not make liberty the common property of all.39 38 J. Boggs (1956: 7,11,15) ‘Workers Report.’ Undated unpublished manuscript. CLR James Collection. Schomburg Research Library, New York, NY. This document acknowledges the publication of ‘Every Cook Can Govern’ in Correspondence in June 1956. It does not acknowledge the presence of the Hungarian Revolution, central to the group’s politics, which emerged later in the year. Those later events advanced the group’s analysis of direct democracy further into the contemporary world. 39 Patterson (1991: 55, 66–67, 70–71). Patterson does take note of a remarkable development in Solon’s Athens which appears to strengthen James’s Athenian Exceptionalism. In Solon’s Athens, a substantial and successful effort was made to ‘buy back’ slaves of Athenian descent from across the known world. Solon had wanted Athenian identity, at least at that juncture in the city-state’s history, not to be degraded by slavery and be distinguished by self-reliant workers—really a relative autonomy from their own elite. This moment of anti-slavery imperative cannot be confused with the idea that Athens was opposed to slavery for those born elsewhere. For classical references to this claim see 250 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS Walter Rodney’s original objection to James, insisting that classical Athens was the greatest civilization the world had ever known, at the famous Black Writers Congress in Montreal in 1968, was sanitized in his famous book The Groundings with my Brothers (1969). David Austin has restored this challenge in a new transcript of ‘African History in the Service of Black Liberation’; Rodney questioned how Greece could be a great civilization if it was marked by slavery, and he also inquired as to whether the very term civilization had outlived its usefulness.40 Yet the dilemma of Black Power era activists, most whom did not conduct independent research on classical Athens, was that they increasingly rejected engagement with European history as a thought experiment relevant to the African world. James’s meditation was not meant to be an uncritical defence of Western civilization but part of teasing out self-emancipating possibilities for ordinary people with an enlarged concept of citizenship. Athens as awkward metaphor for black power and labour’s self-emancipation Modibo Kadalie, a member of Detroit’s League of Revolutionary Black Workers (1969–71) who for a time was in dialogue with C.L.R. James, recalls that Every Cook Can Govern was read by members of this proletarian-oriented Black Power organization in the midst of disputes as to whether the League should become a vanguard party. Certain of the more Black Nationalist members were not fond of exploring a European society as a case study, and most who discussed it were not impressed by the overall logic of the pamphlet. Still, Every Cook Can Govern had a way of helping certain League members to fight for greater democracy within the organization, and to be more alert to the limits of representative government and party politics which were previously accepted uncritically. This was particularly so when the conflicting tendencies inside the League came to a head in 1971, when those who opposed the increasing vanguard and undemocratic tendencies in the group were purged.41 Emily Greenwood’s study of how Athens functioned in James’s anti-colonial nationalism of 1958–62 deserves special consideration here. In a study of uses of classics in Anglophone Caribbean intellectual history in the twentieth century, Greenwood observes ways in which James, and his protégée Eric Williams, were able to mobilize and reinvent the legacy of Athens in the context of Trinidad. Aristotle (1930: 12.4) and West (1989 and 1992). It is remarkable that in a long oral history dedicated to Patterson’s intellectual development as a historical sociologist, he acknowledges James’s influence on his anti-colonial nationalism, and treatment of slavery in his book Slavery and Social Death but reveals no perspective on James’s direct democratic reading of classical Athens, the critique of which is central to Freedom. See Scott (2013: 96–242). 40 Rodney (2001:66–80); (1969: 51–59). The original rendering can be found as ‘African History in the Service of Black Revolution.’ 41 Kadalie (2013: 25–26). 251 MATTHEW QUEST Instead of being intimidated by the classics, James and Williams saw it as a source of movable tropes and changeable analogies which could blur different forms of government, and co-opt Athenian democracy into anti-colonial nationalism. They also borrowed the tropes of classical Athenian rhetoric used in crowd politics before popular assemblies, which maintained that, as a collective, ordinary citizens had the wisdom to understand things that professional intellectuals could not. This obscured what could be an unequal social contract between orator and crowd. It is also notable that Williams, with James’s assistance in this period, was pursuing a Fabian welfare state, not a direct democratic city-state.42 James pushed further in 1965–66 in both Trinidad and Guyana. He used the citystate of Athens (and Renaissance Italy) as a model to question elite party politics and even marshalled Heraclitus in a discussion with Indo-Trinidadian sugar workers whose independent labour action precipitated James being placed under house arrest during a declared state of emergency by Williams. This peculiar moment of James’s career, the only time he ran for electoral office with the Workers and Farmers Party in Trinidad, ended up becoming a touchstone for the direct democratic tendency of the Caribbean New Left (1968–83).43 The basic thread in the original essay about Athens continued to be present in his shift from anti-colonial middle class politics to labour agitation at the post-independence moment. Ordinary people, without formal scholarly training, had the wisdom to understand and govern in a manner that professional intellectuals could never understand. Why did Athens fail? Classical Athens failed in James’s eyes as a result of not taking into account how humanity laboured. He was not concerned primarily that they did not implement a socialist society, however primitive, such a political economy could produce.44 Rather, he believed that slavery and subordination of women ultimately killed the democracy. At the same time, James emphasizes that, while most critics, some radical, ‘sneer’ and take a swipe at the form of democracy present in classical Athenian institutions, as a result of the exclusion of women and slaves from citizenship, behind this condemnation for the city-state as a whole is a lack of commitment to actually extending these ideals of citizenship in the contemporary world. This assertion is profound and still valid if we keep in mind that James’s intention was to selectively mine archives of political thought to advance future struggles. While fully aware of the limits of Western civilization, James believed, he could engage fruitfully with it without getting caught in the web of its exclusions and subordination of the human. Following W.H. Auden’s view of classical Athens found in Auden’s introduction to the Portable Greek Reader, James’s American Civilization explains that modern society is distinguished by great works of culture, progress, and development, but 42 Greenwood (2010: 210–14, 220). 43 James (1966) and Quest (2008: 206–07). 44 James (1992: 31). 252 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS there are no well-rounded civilized persons. Instead, there are specialists, artists who know little of natural science, scientists with no wisdom about art and literature, philosophers who have no interest in religion, clergy who are unconcerned with politics, and politicians who know only politics, and ‘a very superficial’ conception of that. Through James’s optics, under direct democracy the average classical Athenian citizen engaged fully in a politics that encompassed philosophical, literary, and cultural matters.45 Thus James is impressed with the fact that classical theatre and the dramas of Aeschylus and Euripides were popular, mass art forms where the assembled democracy decided which plays should win prizes, through ten nonexpert judges who were selected by lot.46 The organization of Athenian governance, in James’s outlook, was such that an integrated humanism constituted a national purpose which justified whatever hierarchy and bureaucracy was present. However, besides the subordination of women and slaves, James was insufficiently aware of how this society was divided by masses and elites. These elites, facilitators and legislators of government, often shaped the popular will through a type of crowd politics. They were often privileged with a well-rounded education and skilled in persuasive oratory, if not officially given the status of a class above society.47 Though James was aware that intellectuals such as Aristotle and Plato opposed what he terms a direct democracy, he inadequately takes issue with a subtle discourse of guardianship in the Athenian national ethos, as best represented by Pericles’ famous Funeral Oration. Pericles famously argued that although all could not make government policy, the character of Athenian citizens was such that all were competent to judge it.48 This seems a very profound limitation to be found in a government of popular assemblies and committees where, not merely theoretically but structurally, citizens are purportedly meant to be directly sovereign.49 The riddle of ‘the Black Plato’ In James’s reflections on Athens, his condemnation of the average contemporary trade union bureaucrat or parliamentarian for scoffing at ordinary working people’s potential to directly govern society, appears to have a dual character. On one hand, it 45 James (1993: 153), Auden (1977 [orig 1948]:5). 46 James (1992: 13–15). 47 Ober (1989: 156–91), especially Chapter 4 ‘Ability and Education: The Power of Persuasion’. More recently Ober has revisited the question of the balance of knowledge between mass and elite in democratic Athens, arguing for the more successful distribution, sharing, and exchange of knowledge between demos and the elite through the institutions of Athenian government. See Ober (2008). 48 The relevant passage for Pericles’s Funeral Oration can be found in Thucydides History 2.40.2. 49 James (1992: 24–25). See Popper (1963) for critical discussion of the ethos of both Plato and Pericles in relation to narratives of a self-governing society. 253 MATTHEW QUEST was a swift condemnation of the fraud of representative government;50 however, on the other hand it could also function as a cautionary tale for progressive guardians elevated above society. James, nicknamed ‘the Black Plato’ by the London Times, often posed as a critical dialogic mentor for those who aspired to govern above society, particularly in peripheral nations. The London Times’ labelling of James as ‘the Black Plato’ must be perceived as that annoying Eurocentric disposition to categorize Black achievement in the shadow of assumed precursors of Western Civilization, instead of appreciating Black autonomy and originality. James was not annoyed, and in some respects subtly embraced this moniker, for he felt that the newspaper was saying he had authored a certain body of work of social significance. However, this nickname becomes prescient when speculation about his tendency to advise ‘Black Jacobins’ or philosopher-statesmen, and not everyday people, comes into focus. James believed Plato’s Republic endeavoured through a speculative methodology to arrive at a theoretical model for an ideal society which could replace direct democracy. This was a process where Plato means to advise those who would rule above it, and thus for James had totalitarian implications. Yet James also believed that, as a result of his rhetorical dialogic method, Plato ultimately concluded that the direct democratic form was the best type for classical Athens.51 Curiously, James argues, originally addressing an American audience, that ‘in the past’ there was justification for intellectuals considering the merits of Plato’s speculations. In modern industrial societies James concludes that there is no longer any reason to avoid direct government by the common people. However, in peripheral colonized nations, James had a different outlook, which is why it is worth revisiting this matter of ‘the Black Plato’.52 James’s classical Athenian city-state is a type of project of democratic order, a metaphor of what the Caribbean and Africa can be under the proper leadership of progressive guardians. In James’s view, intellectuals, artists, and political leaders of the Third World who reflect the popular forces from which they emerge, should not be confused with the actual capacities of ordinary people, and expose the fraud of meritocracy of governance in a world distinguished by white supremacy and colonialism.53 50 51 52 53 James (1992: 8–9). Ibid., pp. 26–27. Ibid., pp. 8, 26. Abdullah (2005). I am indebted to a conversation with the Oilfield Workers Trade Union education secretary, which helped to clarify this perennial Jamesian reading of classical Athens. It nevertheless re-frames its contemporary meaning for peripheral nations as aspiring to less than a direct democracy. In James’s personal copy of Werner Jaeger’s Paideia he underlined: ‘if the Greeks were united they could rule the world’. In the margin James wrote ‘W.I.’ for the West Indies. There is nothing direct democratic about this passage. Jaeger (3:1945:289), C.L.R. James Collection, West Indiana Collection, Alma Jordan Library, University of West Indies Trinidad & Tobago. I will subsequently refer to James’s personal copies of Jaeger’s three volumes. 254 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS In this context, James, speaking to a Caribbean audience in Modern Politics, raises the spectre of Aristotle and asks, ‘What is the good life?’ Notably when he speaks to an American audience about ‘the struggle for happiness’, James proclaims freedom is ‘on the road’ to being ‘lost’—that is a conception of democracy independent of the state. But for his Caribbean audience, as a result of the present condition of statecraft, ‘the good life’, where ‘the individual must have community with the state’,— ‘that today is impossible’. Where his Athenian ideals to save American civilization explicitly evoke direct democracy, in a peripheral nation such as Trinidad, James’s Athenian lesson is that the masses’ creativity is significant when the state properly organizes society. On this basis, a post-colonial regime led by the national bourgeoisie under certain conditions can be said to represent the interests of everyday people for a time.54 Still, James also drew a different analogy between classical Athenian city states and Caribbean islands. These islands really had no isolated rural areas in comparison to Latin American or African societies. The high level of social density, particularly in Trinidad, suggested a relative urbanity for the entire country. With constant contact with the outer world, modern systems of communication, high levels of literacy, and productivity which approximated industrial life even under the plantation order, James’s fusion of Athenianism and Marxism could suggest, at least to some of his admirers, that the ordinary working people of the Caribbean were in fact modern enough to directly govern. The outstanding Caribbean New Left organization that propagated this as a consistent vision was Bukka Rennie’s New Beginning Movement based in Trinidad. Tim Hector’s Antigua Caribbean Liberation Movement also for a time advocated this type of direct democratic vision. Both tried to modify the Athenian vision by placing it in conversation with the AfroCaribbean and Indo-Caribbean cultural heritage.55 Can ‘Athens’ be used as an instrument of social control? James’s discourse on direct democracy in classical Athens may not be what it at first appears. The model of direct democracy might be construed as an instrument of politics that must generate or invent a body of ideal or worthy citizens distinguished by their capacity for self-reliance. It might also function, perhaps beyond James’s awareness, as an instrument of social control, since the imperfection of human nature makes it questionable how such large numbers of self-governing citizens, who are said to be the essence of such a unique society, shall be manufactured. The city-state may strive to create a shared identity through discourse that will encourage exemplary citizens. In this scenario, perhaps the state can take credit for the intellectual and political capacities of certain individuals among the masses, as representative of the type of society the ruling elite is cultivating. The state may advance a type of education which affords citizens the opportunity to pursue a higher level of 54 James (1973: 103); (1993: 107). 55 Rennie (1980: 99). See also Quest (2007: 211–32). 255 MATTHEW QUEST self-development—imagined, somewhat Platonically, in terms of aspiring to the perfection of beauty.56 We are aware that James knew of Hegel’s meditations on Greek art as a basis for thinking about the city-state’s self-governing capacities.57 Philip Kain’s analysis of Greek aesthetic ideals and myths about wholeness of personality and spontaneous self-governing instincts present in Hegel and Marx speaks to concerns of James scholars. Kain notices that Hegel and Marx believed, like James, that these human capacities were on the road to being lost in the modern world. This leads James to assert that Marx was pushing not for greater material production but dynamic humanistic development as the meaning of progress. Yet Kain recognizes in Marx a dual character. First, there is an assertion by Marx that ‘socialism’ will be a holistic selfemancipating experience of labour located in their workplaces where the shadow of state power will not be over ordinary people. Second, another implied approach to government is present where their personality will increasingly be culturally developed outside their workplaces in their leisure time by a certain type of state. Thus Kain suggests that the marshaling of Athenian ideals in Marx can place labour and the state in conflict, a possibility with which James’s interpretation does not appear to be concerned.58 James is aware that the aesthetic dimension of the Athenian city state is partially an invented one. One way of seeing Athens was as a beautiful totality. But James acknowledged early and later in his public life that Athens historically was not an absolute masterpiece. Though as a framework of political philosophy it helped him to imagine a new society, and posit an evolving heritage where it had been unfolding. James personal copies of Werner Jaeger’s Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture (3 volumes) are well marked up and give an indication of this alertness to political aesthetics and his attentiveness to other matters. In the front of Volume 1, James noted Jaeger is ‘a defeated aristocrat’ but nevertheless finds his scholarship valuable. James underlined Jaeger’s reflection that Aristotle defined the relation of art to nature by suggesting that art imitated nature. Art was invented to compensate for its defects. This view assumes that nature has an all-pervading purpose, and it sees in nature art’s prototype. Jaeger reinforced the idea of popular instinctive genius James found in Rousseau and Michelet when he argued: ‘since nature herself does what is right without having learn[ed] how, she must possess the genius of selfeducation . . . [and] she develops her masterly skill by using it directly on the task on which she is concerned’.59 This concern was the creation of the Athenian city-state in ideal terms. 56 57 58 59 Dynneson (2008: xii–xiii, 1–5, 194–98). See Hegel (1920). Kain (1980: 236–37, 249–51); (1982). Jaeger (3:1945: 28–29). 256 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS An Athenian ideal of culture: the perfect state comes from within self-development Jaeger argued, and James enthusiastically underlined, that the fourth century BCE is the classical epoch in the history of paideia, ‘if we take that to mean the development of a conscious ideal of education and culture’. From an intellectual point of view, the fourth century is the fulfilment of the promise, of the fifth and earlier centuries. But from another perspective, it is also an age of tremendous revolution. The previous century had been dedicated to the task of bringing democracy to perfection, of attaining the ideal of self-government extended to all free citizens.60 James’s reading of Jaeger’s Paideia also informed his reading of Plato. James underlined Jaeger’s claim that ‘Plato proposes that education should aim to create the perfectly just state within each of us – after all, that is how actually existing states are created. He had given up the contemporary state as incurable’.61 Though Plato desired to tutor elites to govern, this insight seemed to paradoxically reinforce a libertarian impulse in James, for the perfect state was to come from within, and the existing states previously known had failed. But the nuances continue to be complicated. James is also fond of the rhetoric of Demosthenes. This classical Greek orator is found in Every Cook Can Govern, as well as in Nkrumah and the Ghana Revolution in conversation with African market women.62 Jaeger informed James that, in Against Aristocrates, Demosthenes was astute in recognizing that elite politicians desired to help their country no further than ‘plastering a wall here and repairing a wall there’. Similarly, in On The Crown, Demosthenes argued that appeals to politicians had been useless and that people must be educated to a new mentality—for politicians always said what the public wanted to hear anyhow. James found this interpretation ‘quite’ good and agreed with Jaeger that Demosthenes’s speeches must be understood as not moving toward advocacy of a political party. Rather he was transforming into a ‘popular leader’.63 C.L.R. James is a defender of Pericles against the challenges of direct democracy, which James could be fascinated with, but could also view as excessive when mobilized against a popular leader.64 Pericles ‘ruled Athens as general command for some thirty years’. James saw Pericles as an instance where citizens delegated him to rule repeatedly but could subject him to censure and instant recall. James is fond of Jaeger’s interpretation of what happened to Pericles: Pericles began to be challenged by the spirit of the direct democracy, because his rule, according to Jaeger, appeared to be ‘a concealed tyranny. Yet the logic of history led to the conclusion that, if the democratic state was to maintain itself, it must have the right kind of man as its leader’. James found this assessment by Jaeger ‘quite’ good. Jaeger believed: 60 61 62 63 64 Ibid., 2:1944: 5. Ibid., 3:1945: 200. James (1977: 131). Jaeger (3:1945: 276–77). James (1992: 24–25). 257 MATTHEW QUEST That was in fact the chief . . . problem of democracy, for the democratic principle was bound to develop ad absurdum whenever the democratic state attempted to be more than a strictly regulated system of ratifying the decisions of its representatives, and really become the domination of the masses. From its appearance, therefore, the aim of the educational movement led by the sophists was not to educate the people but to educate the leaders of the people. . . the pupils of [the sophists] were the men who wished to become politicians and eventual leaders of the states.65 The hero, artist, and ordinary person as one? Let us explore James’s affinity for Athenian ideals of citizenship, and its critical discourse, further. When a common substance of citizenship is said to exist that all can partake in, modelled on Athenian ideals, a blurring of workers’ movements and nationalist movements can take place where both are dissatisfied with the limits of representative government. But when it accesses this dynamic this state can kill its direct democratic potential. Through its simplicity and monumentality, James’s Athens was constructed in such a manner that its citizens were said to have a shared past where the ordinary person, the hero, and the artist were one.66 Surely great individuals may approximate this multidimensional character portrait, which James accesses from his Greek archive, but for this to distinguish an entire society would be quite remarkable. He seems to know this privately as he projects these ideals publicly. Nicole Loraux has illustrated that the Funeral Oration, as an Athenian genre, offers a peculiar representation of a direct democracy because it has so many aristocratic implications. It does not really renounce elites and tends to define democracy in non-democratic terms. The drawing of lots to decide who will govern, an aspect central to James’ direct democratic conception, is totally ignored by the genre. In fact, among the abundant literature that has survived from classical Athens, no statement of direct democratic political theory appears to have endured. Loraux asks why the shift towards a more direct democratic way of life was not accompanied by a theoretical justification or a defence against counter-attack by oligarchs?67 James did not speculate on this dilemma in his study. 65 Jaeger (1:1939: 286–87). 66 See Mosse (2001). Mosse’s discussion of the intersection of nationalism and workers movements and their dissatisfaction with representative government from Napoleonic Europe to Nazi Germany, combined with nation-states’ desire to co-opt and disorient, by cultural activities, popular movements striving for direct democracy, is an outstanding model for insurgent cultural studies. He explains presciently how self-governing aesthetic-political ideals, with their origins in classical Athenian culture, have been borrowed throughout time to both enhance and disrupt instincts toward direct democracy. Linking Mosse’s and James’s studies of popular culture is excellent for enhancing critical reflection. I thank Paul Buhle, who knew both Mosse and James, for conversations which amplified this insight. 67 Loraux (2006: 219–20, 223–24, 226, 228–30, 233). 258 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS We must also remember that the Funeral Oration was not the same type of speech that one might make before a popular assembly, instead it has the spectre of war, which was a persistent reality of Greek city states, hanging over it. It was almost as if these self-governing Athenians peculiarly needed to be reminded all the time of their special character. When we observe closely James’s critical discussion of Third World anti-colonial politicians, consistent with The Black Jacobins, we see repeatedly how they ominously remind ordinary people of their urgent tasks while often acting not to allow them to hold the reins of society. They do this often with an awareness of direct democracy, a concern for the spectre of ‘anarchy’, and with the flare of classical rhetoric.68 There is a subtle discourse of the division of labour in the genre of the Funeral Oration where self-government is divided between those who are administrators, those who make decisions, and those who show mere concern. There is an aristocracy of talent in the discourse of the Funeral Oration and the role of the crowd is approval not initiative. In addition, there is a preoccupation with establishing a type of national identity through ‘participation’ in civic affairs rather than implementing a direct democracy.69 James was aware through Jaeger’s Paideia that perhaps Thucydides worked up and invented Pericles’ personality as a whole and of the importance of the Funeral Oration as not merely a brilliant account of soldiers’ prowess but also an idealized rhetorical construction of the whole Athenian state. I believe that James would have welcomed the subsequent scholarly insights of Loraux. Contingency, Greeks and the good life James, clearly animated by Greek ideals of a good life, and not just by Marxist historical materialism, often minimizes contingency (chance and luck) in human affairs and at times relies on false terms of rational self-sufficiency. This has implications for the ability to imagine a direct democracy and reveals moments where he forgets himself. If James can be read as alert to contingency in evaluating statesmen, he rarely acknowledged this in assessing the potential of labour’s self-emancipation. We should be clear this does not mean that James has a utopian conception of the self-governing abilities of workers. James, unlike many, was born with more than adequate personal intellectual and political capacities. All human beings are not endowed with comparable skills in reading, writing, oratory, philosophy, and political strategy. Despite all this, James was often faced with fragile health and the potential of economic hardship—as are many ordinary people. More importantly, his fortunes depended on outside forces: Would friends and family care for him? Would the wider society share his ambitions and projects? Would political institutions (official society and those he created to be 68 James (1963: 206). This is especially so where Toussaint L’Ouverture in the Haitian Revolution lectures the newly freed slaves about ‘anarchy’ and the responsibilities of citizenship that must fall short of direct self-government. 69 Loraux (2006: 239–41). 259 MATTHEW QUEST insurgent), based on human association, be subject to reversals of fortune? Personal achievement, politics, and love were not always under his control. In his meditations on ‘the good life’ of Athenian direct democracy, James did not always consider the fragility of the human condition or his own. This is partially understandable because it is the task of a revolutionary to strive for progress beyond what is ordinarily believed possible. But when theorizing a direct democracy and a self-emancipating society these are not just personal meditations but ethical questions about matters between people. For what happens by luck does not come through individual selfgoverning actions alone. To aspire to make a good life through the power of ‘reason’, safe from chance or risk, can become a tragic and authoritarian project. The contours of Greek philosophy and literature at times overlook these dilemmas while at other junctures ponder these challenges.70 The crafting of James’s Athens: competent authority and discontents James’s study of the classical Athenian city state and its lessons for direct democracy can appear to some as a less than scholarly gloss with the character of propaganda rather than serious education, but diligent research in James’s archive reveals the actual historical sources he used to come to conclusions about Athenian direct democracy. Somewhat overturned by the scholarship of recent generations, ‘the competent authorities’ he leaned on can be surveyed for further critical reflection. In the pages of Correspondence in August of 1956, on the readers’ letters page, can be found concerns by readers from New York City and British Columbia, Canada that James’ Every Cook Can Govern painted ‘an overly rosy picture, although basically it is not too great a strain on the realities’. ‘The . . . account of democracy in Ancient Greece was quite good, although I think there were errors in it. But on the whole, it presented a better picture than we usually get.’ The ‘Editor’s Reply’ was quite extensive. And the reader begins to see James’s engagement with the secondary literature beyond Rostovtzeff and Jaeger. James reveals that Alfred Zimmern’s The Greek Commonwealth (1931) and Gustav Glotz’s The Greek City and Its Institutions (1929) were major influences on his perspective. Both these scholars, while not defending slavery, oppose the view that the Greek Democracy was possible only because of the leisure of a population of slave owners. Zimmern points in a moving paragraph how ‘all this is false, false in its interpretation of the past and in its confident pessimism as to the future, willfully false, above all, in its cynical estimate of human nature.’ Glotz goes further and shows how it was actually the Athenian workers, in continuous struggle against the aristocracy and oligarchs, who produced the democracy and how the workers were the strongest defenders of the democracy. He goes on to show how later the developing capitalist economy, intensified by war, created a slave labor force of a 70 Nussbaum (1986: 1–8, 344–45). 260 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS qualitative different character which threw the free workers out of productive employment, impoverished them and brought about the decline of the democracy.71 In response to critics, James felt the need not only to separate out the direct democratic character of Athens from slavery but also to address the question of a woman’s place in that culture. He also revealed more sources for Every Cook Can Govern. J.P. Mahaffey’s Social Life in Greece: from Homer to Menander (1925), Larue Van Hook, Greek Life and Thought (1923), A.W. Gomme’s Essays in Greek History and Literature (1937), and H.D.F. Kitto’s The Greeks (1951) shaped James’s views on gender.72 (1) The seclusion of Athenian women was not like that of the Oriental harem since they participated in the dramatic and religious festivals which were an organic part of the social and political life of the Greek city-state; (2) the freedom of women of the working classes was much greater than that of women of the aristocracy; (3) the literature of the late 5th century shows that the role and claims of women were becoming a lively issue. However, today the question of women’s place in Athenian society is a very difficult one because our own conception of the family and equality of women is still so confused and to a large extent still governed by the idea that equality means the adoption of women of the habits and manners of men. The understanding of women’s role in modern society from the standpoint of the working class is just beginning and will in time illuminate her role in Athenian society (James’s numeration).73 In the unearthing of these fragments we see James’s concern for how studies of classical Athens should consider woman’s autonomy from the vantage points of a pre-capitalist and modern society. This requires examining woman’s development from the perspective of the spaces where their own political thought may have emerged, in artistic and theological spaces, and in carrying out unwaged work in the home. This reveals the influence of Selma James, C.L.R.’s third wife and comrade, and the analysis found in her pamphlet, A Woman’s Place (1952). Furthermore, recent scholarship in the field by Kostas Vlassopoulos mirrors these earlier interpretations by C.L.R. and Selma.74 Still, writing before the emergence of feminist classical scholarship, C.L.R. James was not aware of how Athenian patriarchal creation myths, like that of Pandora and the story of the Amazon war, created a type of sexual social contract where women were considered ‘the passive half’ of the polis. Women were artificially ‘created out of earth’ and thus were said to belong to an 71 Editors’ Reply (1956: 4), See Zimmern (1956 [orig.1911]) and Glotz (1965 [orig.1929]). See Cohen (2000) for a more contemporary study of how the Athenian slave economy was distinguished by a significant number of wealthy slaves who were powerful entrepreneurs and civil servants and who maintained independent households. 72 See Mahaffey (2014 [orig. 1925]), Van Hook (1977 [orig. 1923]), Gomme (1962 [orig. 1931]), and Kitto (1991 [orig. 1951]). 73 Editors’ Reply (1956: 4). 74 S. James (2012: 13–31) and Vlassopoulos (2007: 33–52). 261 MATTHEW QUEST inferior race apart. Where they strove to be warriors like ‘men’ they found themselves defeated and subordinated as ‘damsels in distress’.75 Steve Johnstone reminds us that scholars of classical Athens have often conflated the character of popular assemblies and popular courts. According to Johnstone, it was out of the popular courts, rather than the assemblies, that what we know of a potential direct democratic Athenian identity emerged.76 James’s Every Cook Can Govern can be accused of blurring the lines of the character of Athenian popular courts and assemblies to assert a society where no experts over-lorded government. He argued that the Athenians were great believers in law, ‘both written and unwritten’.77 What did this mean for James? Bolshevism and Athens James saw in the Athenian popular courts judges or magistrates who became a ‘mere clerk of the court’. Juries did not decide only on the facts and look to judges for information on the law. ‘They decided on the law as well as on the facts.’78 Litigants argued for their own cause, though they could hire someone (logographoi) experienced in the law to write their speech, and then read it for themselves. James placed Athenian popular courts in conversation with Bolshevik experimentation with ‘people’s courts’79 in the Russian Revolution during ‘its heroic period’. James may have the heroic period of the Russian Revolution mistaken despite having written the first anti-Stalinist history of the Communist International. While it is inspiring to conceive of ordinary people in Athens crafting the law, not just interpreting the facts of specific cases under the direction of professionals, James was mystified that Lenin had convinced labour to police itself for his authoritarian state instead of challenging it, as represented by the people’s courts of that historical moment in Russia.80 Perhaps Nicholas Jones’s The Associations of Classical Athens contributes most to helping to reassess James’s Athenian direct democracy, and his affinity for Rousseau, who also relied on the Athenian archive for experimental political thought, and the thread which has James ultimately meditating on Soviets, and the workers’ councils of Russia, in relation to Lenin. Jones’s Athens was a place, counter-intuitive in many ways, where the integrated humanism of the ordinary citizen doesn’t seem to be present. Furthermore, there is a need to account for what was in reality a low level of 75 76 77 78 79 80 Loraux (2000: 7–8, 33). See also Pomeroy (1995). Johnstone (1999: 128–33). James (1992: 10). Ibid., p. 10. Ibid., pp. 10–11. Ibid., pp. 10–11. See also James (1993) and Quest (2012). James’s Leninism and advocacy of direct democracy could become intertwined in an ambiguous discourse; James implausibly concluded that Lenin was both a patron of direct democracy and that he smashed the autonomy of the soviets (workers councils) in the Russian Revolution. 262 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS participation among citizens. The city-state, as central government, was trying to cultivate the popular will. It was trying to incorporate all legitimate participation while insisting all must participate. Animated by Solon’s law, the city-state validates and regulates associational life, which Jones makes clear, was overwhelmingly outside the government. In this manner the state often responded to associational life, which could be a haven for aristocrats, but also at times the marginal, as subversive. The city-state governed under the premise of egalitarianism. But the way in which it framed direct democracy, made participation, by those who were recognized as citizens, actually involuntary.81 This can be an authoritarian dilemma even if all humans were included under the category of citizenship. It is difficult to fathom this if we assume simply that all must be included without a colour, class, or gender bar. Instead, we should begin to re-imagine what the Grenada Revolution may have learned from James’s Athenian outlook as it wished to have a one party state facilitate assemblies or zonal councils for the people. In Grenada there were political prisoners with dissenting viewpoints where they could not be transparently brought to trial.82 ‘The questions are still disputed:’ James’s need for the Athenian City-state We might close this section reflecting on James’s Athens by considering his concise treatment in the lectures in Modern Politics. James began his lectures, aware that ‘the questions are still disputed’, about how the Athenians ‘rejected representative government and followed a pattern of direct democracy’. ‘I am going to make this as vivid as possible’. I doubt if you could take thirty or forty people today from anywhere and put them into some government, however small it might be and ask them to run it. It is not because government is so difficult. The idea that a little municipality, as we have them all over the world today, would have more difficulty and complex problems than the city of Athens is quite absurd. It is that they have lost the habit of looking at government and one another in that way.83 (James’s italics) James knew that ‘there were great gaps in our knowledge of many aspects of Greek life’, and that the facts that scholars of classical Athens had gathered were ‘variously interpreted’. Yet James insisted that ‘history is a living thing’ and was not merely a body of facts. The direct democratic position James originally took in Every Cook Can Govern explicitly built on and transcended the latest scholarship of his time. It was based on something more: ‘our own belief in the creative power of freedom and the capacity of the ordinary man to govern. Unless you share that belief [about] the ancient Greeks, you cannot understand the civilization they built’.84 81 82 83 84 Jones (1999: 288–92, 299–300, 306). See Joseph (2010: 4–31), Quest (2007: 213–215). James (1973: 2–4). James (1992: 24). 263 MATTHEW QUEST While the intentions and conflicting tendencies of classical Athens are still in dispute, reflection and scrutiny as to how direct the Athenian democracy was still has currency—providing we expect that democracy entails that the majority should actually govern. The truth is that even most progressive people, even those who speak occasionally of popular democracy, are substantially content with a mere republic based on electoral politics. James was seeking to go beyond the one party state and the electoral politics of the welfare state. However, the perennial sustainability of James’s Every Cook Can Govern, as a concise study of the Athenian city state and its meanings, cannot ultimately rise and fall on the verdict of the exclusions of that society. Neither can it be discarded because of an awareness that Athens in many ways embodies a truth that had been ‘baked for generations and hardened from an initial error’ as Jennifer Tolbert Roberts has remarked in Athens on Trial. ‘Athens’ should not be held in special contempt simply because in many ways it is an allegory which fuses democracy with state power and is surrounded by discourses that fear and undermines popular democracy from many sectors even through its populism. It is a social dynamic that those who resist and wish to topple hierarchy and domination must learn if it possibly can be overcome. Roberts also notes that Alfred Zimmern, who influenced James, was one of many of his time, who insisted Greece was the greatest civilization and example of social organization the world had ever seen.85 How much further can a city-state or nation-state push itself as a minority rule regime through periodic elections and subordinate participation? What is popular about assemblies and committees subordinate to state power? Can we throw away Athens for all it represents uniquely as an anti-democratic tradition in Western thought as if these contradictions cannot be found elsewhere including in the modern world? This is what James’s push for direct democracy through the trope of classical Athens was trying to get at. James’s comrade Marty Glaberman, who as publisher based in Detroit kept Every Cook Can Govern from languishing in obscurity, suggested at a conference on James’s intellectual legacies that slavery could be found all over the ancient world, as could the subordination of women and feudal relations. In similar and in different more modern forms, there are still relations of exclusion and domination on a global scale. Humanity was not and is not what it should be—even in the postcivil rights, post-colonial era. Yet James reminds us that it is out of such fragmented historical environments that experiments in framing social revolutions and designing a free society happen, and it is out of that incomplete heritage that future battles will be inspired to sweep aside institutionalized oppression and obstacles that we place in our own path.86 85 Roberts (1994: xi, 3, 12). 86 Glaberman (2001). 264 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS References D. Abdullah, Conversation with Author. Summer 2005. Aristotle, The Constitution of Athens, H. Rackman (ed.), (London: Heinemann, 1930). W. H. Auden (ed.), ‘Editor’s Introduction’, in Portable Greek Reader (New York: Penguin, 1977 [orig. 1948]). M. Bernal, Black Athena, Vol. 1 (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1987). G. L. Boggs, Living For Change (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1999). J. Boggs, Pages from A Black Radical’s Notebook: A James Boggs Reader, S.M. Ward (ed.) (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2011). ——, ‘Workers Report,’ Unpublished Manuscript, (Undated 1956), CLR James Collection, Schomburg Research Library, New York City, NY. J. Bracey, ‘Nello’, in P. Le Blanc and S. McLemee (eds.), C.L.R. James and Revolutionary Marxism: Selected Writings, 1939-1949 (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1994), pp. 53–5. M. Bradley (ed.), Classics and Imperialism in the British Empire (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010). P. Buhle, ‘C.L.R. James: the Paradoxical Pan-Africanist’, in R.D.G. Kelley and S.J. Lemelle (eds.), Imagining Home (New York: Verso, 1994), pp.158–66. S. Casson, Ancient Greece: A Study (London: Oxford University Press, 1922). J. H. Clarke and Y. Ben-Jochanan, New Dimensions in African History (Trenton, NJ: Africa World Press, 1991). E. E. Cohen, Athenian Nation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000). C. Crawford, ‘The Multiple Dimensions of Nubian/Egyptian Rhetoric and Its Implications for Contemporary Classroom Instruction’, in E.B. Richardson and R.L. Jackson III (eds.), Contemporary African American Rhetoric(s): Interdisciplinary Perspectives (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University, 2004), pp. 111–35. S. R. Cudjoe, Beyond Boundaries (Amherst, MA: Calaloux, 2003). F. Dhondy, C.L.R. James: A Life (London: Wiedenfeld & Nicholson, 2001). M. Dibb, ‘Beyond a Boundary’ (BBC, 1976). R. Dunayevskaya, Marxism & Freedom, 4th edn (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988 [orig 1958]).) T. L. Dynneson, City-State Civism in Ancient Athens (New York: Peter Lang, 2008). Editor’s Reply. Correspondence, August 1956, pp. 4. J. Edwards, Workers Self-Management in the Caribbean (Atlanta: OOOA, 2014). M. Glaberman, Comment In Response to Anthony Bogues, Recording, CLR James at 100 Conference, Trinidad and Tobago, (September 2001). ——, Punching Out & Other Writings, S. Lynd (ed.) (Chicago: Charles H Kerr, 2002) G. Glotz, The Greek City and Its Institutions (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1965 [orig 1929]). B. Goff (ed.), Classics and Colonialism (London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2005). B. Goff and M. Simpson (eds.), Crossroads in the Black Aegean: Odysseus, Antigone, and the Dramas of the African Diaspora (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008). A. W. Gomme, Essays in Greek History and Literature (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1962 [orig. 1931]). E. Greenwood, Afro-Greeks: Dialogues between Anglophone Caribbean Literature and Classics in the Twentieth Century (London: Oxford University Press, 2010). L. Hardwick, Reception Studies (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003). ——, ‘Against the ’Democratic Turn:’ Counter-texts; Counter Contexts; Counter Arguments’, in L. Hardwick and S. Harrison (eds.), Classics in the Modern World: A Democratic Turn? (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 15–32. L. Hardwick and C. Gillespie (eds.), Classics in Post-colonial Worlds (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007). L. Hardwick and S. Harrison (eds.), Classics in the Modern World: A Democratic Turn? (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013). G. W. F. Hegel, The Philosophy of Fine Art (London: G. Bell and Sons, 1920). P. Henry, Caliban’s Reason: Introduction to Afro-Caribbean Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 2000). C. Høgsbjerg, C.L.R. James in Imperial Britain (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2014). W. Jaeger, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture, 3 Vols. (Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, 1939–1945). C. L. R. James, American Civilization, A. Grimshaw and K. Hart (eds.), (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1993). ——, Beyond a Boundary (London: Serpent’s Tail, 1992 [orig. 1963]). 265 MATTHEW QUEST ——, The Black Jacobins, 2nd edn., (New York: Vintage, 1963 [orig. 1938]). ——, ‘Continuation of Democracy in Greece’, Bulletin: Vol. I., Unpublished Manuscript (26 July 1955). CLR James Collection. Schomburg Research Library, New York City, NY. ——, Every Cook Can Govern (Detroit: Bewick, 1992 [orig. 1956]). ——, Minty Alley (Jackson, MS: University of Mississippi Press, 1997 [orig. 1936]). ——, (A.A.B.), ‘Mr. Lerner: Ideas Are Weapons, But How To Use Them?’, Labor Action (14 June 1943), pp. 4. ——, Modern Politics (Detroit: Bewick, 1973 [orig. 1960]). ——, Nkrumah and the Ghana Revolution (Westport, CT: Lawrence Hill, 1977). ——, Notes on Dialectics (Detroit: Friends of Facing Reality, 1971). ——, Special Delivery: The Letters of C.L.R. James to Constance Webb, 1939-1948, A. Grimshaw (ed.), (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1996). ——, ‘Tomorrow and Today: A Vision’, New World (1966), Guyana Independence Issue. ——, World Revolution, 1917–1936 (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1993 [orig. 1937]). C. L. R. James, G. L. Boggs and C. Castoriadis, Facing Reality (Detroit: Bewick, 1974 [orig. 1958]). G. G. M. James, Stolen Legacy (San Francisco, CA: Julian Richardson Associates, 1988 [orig. 1954]). S. James, Sex, Race, and Class: The Perspective of Winning (Oakland: PM Press, 2012). S. Johnstone, Disputes and Democracy: The Consequences of Litigation in Ancient Athens, (Austin, TX: University of Texas, 1999). N. E. Jones, The Associations of Classical Athens (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999). T. S. D. Joseph, ‘C.L.R. James’s Theoretical Concerns and the Grenada Revolution: Lessons for the Future’, Journal of Eastern Caribbean Studies 35, no. 3 (September 2010), pp. 4–31. M. Kadalie, ‘From One Generation to the Next: The Enduring Legacies of Kimathi Mohammed’, Introduction to Organization & Spontaneity, By Kimathi Mohammed, Updated Edition (Atlanta: OOOA, 2013), pp. 25–6. P. J. Kain, ‘Marx, Hegel, and the Greek Aesthetic Ideal’, in D. Depew (ed.), Greeks and the Good Life (Fullerton, CA: California State University, 1980), pp. 236–253. ——, Schiller, Hegel, and Marx: State, Society and the Aesthetic Ideal of Ancient Greece (Montreal: McGill- Queens University Press, 1982). H. D. F. Kitto, The Greeks (London: Penguin, 1991 [orig. 1951]). E. Kwayana, The Bauxite Strike and the Old Politics, Updated Edition (Atlanta: OOOA, 2012 [orig. 1972]). ——, ‘But A Visionary, Returning Exile, and Guest Activist Ready to Join in the Work of Nation Building: C.L.R. James’s Influence on Guyana and Caribbean Politics’, The CLR James Journal 19, no. 1&2 (2013), pp. 199–227. K. Lawrence, ‘C.L.R. James and W.E.B. Du Bois: Contributions to the Past, Present, and Future of Unorthodox Marxism’, The CLR James Journal 19, no. 1&2 (2013), pp. 138–76. N. Loraux, Born of the Earth: Myth & Politics in Athens (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2000 [orig. 1996]). ——, The Invention of Athens (New York: Zone Books, 2006). J. P. Mahaffey, Social Life in Greece: from Homer to Menander (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2014 [orig. 1925]). J. McClendon, C.L.R. James’s Notes on Dialectics (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2005). W. J. Moses, Afrotopia (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998). G. L. Mosse, The Nationalization of the Masses (New York: H. Fertig, 2001). M. C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986). J. Ober, Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989). ——, Democracy and Knowledge: Innovation and Learning in Classical Athens (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008). D. Orrells, Gurminder, K. Bhambra, and T. Roynon (eds.), African Athena: New Agendas (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011). O. Patterson, Freedom in the Making of Western Culture (New York: Basic Books 1991). K. Plys, ‘Workers’ Self-Management in the Third World, 1952-1979’, International Journal of Comparative Sociology 57, no. 1 (2016), pp. 1–27. 266 CONTEMPORARY MEANINGS OF C.L.R. JAMES’S CLASSICAL ATHENS S. Pomeroy, Goddesses, Whores, Wives, and Slaves: Women in Classical Antiquity (New York: Shocken Books, 1995 [orig. 1975]). K. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1, 4th rev edn. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963). M. Quest, ‘Afterword: C.L.R. James and Kimathi Mohammed’s Circle of Black Power Activists in Michigan’. in Organization & Spontaneity, By Kimathi Mohammed, Updated Edition, (Atlanta: OOOA, 2013c), pp. 105–32. ——, ‘C.L.R. James, Direct Democracy, and National Liberation Struggles’, PhD diss, American Civilization, Brown University (2008). ——, ‘‘‘Every Cook Can Govern:’’ Direct Democracy, Workers’ Self-Management, and the Creative Foundations of C.L.R. James’s Political Thought’, The CLR James Journal 19, no. 1 & 2 (Fall 2013a), pp. 374–91. ——, ‘Legislating the Caribbean General Will: The Later Political Thought of Tim Hector, 19792002’, The C.L.R. James Journal 13, no. 1 (2007), pp. 211–32. ——, ‘The ’Not So Bright’ Protégées and the Comrades that ‘Never Quarreled’:’ C.L.R. James’s Disputes on Labor’s Self-Emancipation and the Political Economy of Colonial Freedom’, Insurgent Notes 9, (October 2013b), http://insurgentnotes.com/2013/10/the-not-so-bright-proteges/ [Accessed 19 January 2016]. ——, ‘Observing Properly Changing Forms of Spontaneity and Organization: Creative Conflicts in C.L.R. James’s Hegelian Dialectics and Political Philosophy’, Science & Society 80, no. 1 (2016), pp. 105–31. ——, ‘Silences on the Suppression of Workers Self-Emancipation: Historical Problems with C.L.R. James’s Interpretation of V.I. Lenin’, Insurgent Notes 7, (2012), http://insurgentnotes.com/ ?s=Lenin&submit=Go [accessed 19 January 2016]. ——, ‘Wisdom is Plentiful Among Ordinary People to Govern: A View of Antigua’s Tim Hector and Guyana’s Eusi Kwayana’, Antigua & Barbuda Review of Books 8, no. 1 (2015), pp. 132–62. P. D. Rankine, ‘Black Apollo? Martin Bernal’s Black Athena: the Afro-Asiatic Roots of Classical Civilization vol iii, and Why Race Still Matters’, in D. Orrells, G.K. Bhambra, and T. Roynon (eds.), African Athena: New Agendas (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 40–56. B. Rennie, ‘The Manifesto of the New Beginning Movement: Strategy for Working Class Power’, Unpublished, 1980. J. T. Roberts, Athens on Trial: The Antidemocratic Tradition in Western Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994). W. Rodney, Groundings with my Brothers (Chicago: Frontline, 1996 [orig. 1969]). ——, ‘African History in the Service of Black Liberation’, Small Axe 5, no. 2 (2001), pp. 66–80. M. V. Ronnick (ed.), ‘Editor’s Introduction’, in The Works of William Sanders Scarborough (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006). F. Rosengarten, Urbane Revolutionary: C.L.R. James and the Struggle for a New Society (Jackson, MS: University Press of Mississippi, 2008). M. Rostovtzeff, A History of the Ancient World, (The Orient and Greece) Vol. 1, 2nd edn. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1945 [orig. 1926]). G. E. M. de Ste, Croix, The Class Struggle in the Ancient Greek World (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1998 [orig. 1981]). D. Scott, ‘The Paradox of Freedom: An Interview with Orlando Patterson’, Small Axe 17, no. 1 (2013), pp. 96–242. S. Stephens and P. Vasunia (eds.), Classics and National Cultures (New York: Oxford, 2010). Thucydides. History of the Peloponessian War, B. Jowett (ed.), (New York: Random House, 1942 [orig 1881]). L. Van Hook, Greek Life and Thought (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977 [orig. 1923]. K. Vlassopoulos, ‘Free Spaces: Identity, Experience and Democracy in Classical Athens’, Classical Quarterly 57, no. 1 (2007), pp. 33–52. M.L. West (ed.), Iambi et Elegi Graeci ante Alexandrum Cantati, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989 and 1992). K. Worcester, ‘The Question of the Canon’, in P. Buhle and P. Henry (eds.), C.L.R. James’s Caribbean (Durham: Duke University Press, 1992), pp. 215–16. A. E. Zimmern, The Greek Commonwealth: Politics and Economics in Fifth Century Athens, 5th edn. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1931 [orig. 1911]). 267
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz