Thomas Halper Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective E pluribus unum—Out of Many, One—was the ofÞcial maxim of America’s constitutional convention, and it encapsulates the centrality of regionalism that the Framers felt compelled to address. How to put the maxim into practice? In an abstract sense, the puzzle seems insoluble, for literally to derive one from many is to obliterate plurality. But the Framers were problem solvers not put off by such considerations, and the core of their response is contained in a term that permeates the Constitution, though it explicitly appears nowhere in it. That term is “federalism,” and in Philadelphia in 1787 the Framers created a system composed of central and regional levels, each deriving its authority from the people and possessing the authority to govern them directly. The Early Years Like most creations, federalism grew partly from both a memory of failure and a dream of success. The failure was the Articles of Confederation that loosely tied the states together in their war for independence, a government that began weak and rapidly grew weaker. Under the Articles, state governments derived their authority from the people and could govern them directly. But the central government, a fragile and untidy organization of the thirteen states, derived its authority from the states, and generally could govern only indirectly through them. As a consequence, the central government emerged as wholly dependent upon the states for enforcement of its orders and collection of its taxes. It did not take long for states to conclude that there was no reason to enforce a national directive not in their interest or to collect all the taxes due the central government, which as a consequence could not pay its debts. The central government, in short, was reduced to a mere pleading supplicant that states could ignore at their convenience. To the extent that this affected what economists know as indivisible public goods, it created a classic free rider problem: if a beneÞt accrues to everyone, it will seem rational to let others pay for it, but if too many opt for the free ride, there will be insufÞcient resources to supply the good. Individual rationality can thus subvert group rationality. With national security, the most prominent public good, the free rider temptation proved so potent after the war with Britain was won that the 103 Thomas Halper Articles could neither induce the states to outÞt a navy nor to pay its 700 soldiers. And because national action required unanimity among the states, contentious issues, like inßation or trade policy, were not addressed. It was not simply that it was difÞcult to get all the states to agree; it was also that if unanimity was in sight, the remaining few states would hold out, making their agreement conditional on extortionate demands, which not only blocked action but also generated mistrust and ill will. With what Madison called a “want of concert in matters where common interest requires it” (Madison, Writings 69), the nation was plainly too divided and impotent to achieve much stature abroad or to bring order and prosperity to the economy at home. Moreover, since it did not get its authority from the people or govern them directly, the central government inevitably appeared ineffective, and therefore illegitimate, for as Madison observed, the people “cannot long respect a government which is too feeble to protect their interests” (Madison to James Monroe, August 7, 1785, Papers, 8:336). Even when the Articles were successful, as in adopting the Northwest Ordinance as a scheme of territorial governance or concluding a peace treaty with Britain, it rarely received due credit. The weakness of the Articles necessarily elevated the role of the states. But what Jefferson termed their “endless quibbles, chicaneries, perversions, vexations, and delays,” (qtd. in Ketcham 162) plus their pandering to debtors, struck many Framers as alarming. “The vile State governments are sources of pollution which will contaminate the American name for ages,” declared Henry Knox, later President Washington’s secretary of war. “Smite them, smite them in the name of God and the people” (qtd. in Drake 96). The centrifugal force of excessive regionalism threatened to tear the republic apart. If the Articles represented failure, the success the Framers envisioned was of a central government strong enough to avoid the Articles’ inÞrmities, and yet not so strong as to devitalize the role of the states. It was a bold and difÞcult dream to attempt to realize, and as the Þfty-Þve men gathered for the constitutional convention, it was by no means self-evident to them that federalism was the answer. It was also a dream full of uncertainty because it was unclear to which level of government the public would believe had Þrst call on their allegiance. The issue was contested by two opposing groups. The Federalists saw the nation as potentially a major commercial republic, and they believed its large size required a powerful central government. Madison called America an “extended republic” and, against nearly all prior thinkers, understood size as an advantage. A large republic, he explained, would necessarily contain a multitude of factions, which, competing against each other, would make it very unlikely that any single group (particularly, a majority) would establish a lawful tyranny. Heterogeneity was thus counted as desirable. Size was also a plus in that it would necessitate a representative and not a direct democracy, for representation would tend to 104 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective Þlter out uninformed or extreme opinions, while encouraging moderation and compromise. Though the Anti-Federalists conceded that “the present confederation is inadequate to the objects of the union” (Samuel Bryan, qtd. in Bach and Stone 601), they also believed that to establish a republic over a huge territory would be like trying “to rule Hell by Prayer” (Thomas B. Wait to George Thatcher, November 22, 1787, in “Thatcher Papers” 268). They thought a republic was possible only with civic minded citizens, who could put the public interest over their own private concerns. This could arise only in genuine communities, but they believed the pursuit of wealth would undermine the sense of community, and an extended republic in any case was plainly too big to constitute a community. Anti-Federalists accordingly favored power exercised at the local level by homogeneous communities comprised of people of roughly equal wealth and not preoccupied with acquiring property. These communities could be found only in smaller units, which here meant the states. The Anti-Federalists were joined by other delegates from smaller states, who feared that a strong central government would be dominated by large states that would be insensitive to their interests. Such a government, they feared, would be poorly suited to rule a nation of diverse people tied to regional economies and separated by long distances. Unmoved by the Federalists, they saw a strong central government as threatening. In the end, though, the Federalists were forced to make some important concessions—Congress was denied the power to veto state legislation, for example, and Senate representation was based on states— and it was their vision that the Constitution embraced. Thus, the new Constitution endowed the national government with important powers not granted under the Articles, including the power to tax, to levy tariffs, to raise armies, to regulate the national economy, and to establish a national court system. Like the Articles, the Constitution also contained a supremacy clause asserting the supremacy of the Constitution over state constitutions and statutes. The dissatisfaction with the Articles that convinced the Framers that they were beyond repair also persuaded them that a much stronger central government was essential. Practical considerations, not notions of abstract rights or duties, directed the decisions. The states survived and retained much of their vitality, but the forces of regionalism were broadly subdued, with major long term consequences. The clear-cut triumph of the Federalists is reßected in the long list of powers delegated to Congress in Article I, section 8. At the end of this list appears a beguilingly vague clause granting Congress the power “to make all laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying into execution the foregoing powers.” This cryptic clause was to prove of immense importance. In 1816 Congress established a second national bank. The Þrst bank had proved so unpopular that 105 Thomas Halper Congress had permitted its charter to expire, and the second bank, ineptly managed, soon became even more unpopular, provoking states to take actions against it. Maryland imposed a tax on the branch of the bank operating within its borders; the bank refused to pay the tax; and the battle was joined. The Supreme Court ruled on the matter in McCulloch v. Maryland (1819), in what is almost certainly its single most signiÞcant case. The opinion was written by chief justice John Marshall, who believed that if the nation were to fulÞll its potential, it would require a powerful central government, secure property rights, and a Supreme Court willing and able to enforce them. It was these views, shaped by experience and not by recondite speculation, that drove his ruling. “Has Congress power to incorporate a bank?” Marshall asked. Maryland had argued that the Constitution nowhere expressly gave Congress that authority, and that it was plainly not necessary that the nation have such a bank. Marshall replied that the Constitution grants Congress the power to lay and collect taxes, to borrow money, to regulate commerce among the states and with foreign nations, and to make all laws necessary and proper to carry out these powers. How, then, shall “necessary and proper” be construed? Marshall’s answer was founded on his conviction that his task was to interpret “a constitution designed to endure for ages to come,” and that this meant that its key provisions had to be interpreted broadly to permit them the ßexibility needed to adjust to changing times. To interpret “necessary and proper” as “absolutely necessary,” therefore, would be at war with the Constitution’s central purpose: to provide a workable scheme of government. Construing “necessary and proper” broadly, Marshall concluded that Congress’ power to incorporate a bank could be implied from its delegated powers over economic matters. This notion of implied powers has come to provide the chief legal justiÞcation of what is known as the living Constitution, the most common rationale offered for the growth of the national government. After establishing that Congress could create a bank, Marshall then had to ask whether Maryland could tax it. “The Constitution and the laws made in pursuance thereof,” he answered are supreme.” If Maryland could regulate instruments of the national government for its own convenience, the Constitution and national laws would soon lose their signiÞcance. A part of the nation cannot prevail over acts taken by the whole nation. States, Marshall announced, “have no power, by taxation or otherwise, to retard, impede, hinder or in any manner control the operation of the national government.” Thus was the principle of national supremacy irrevocably established: when otherwise valid national and state laws conßict, the state laws must give way. Implicit in this decision, too, was the principle that the Supreme Court shall act as umpire in disputes between the national and state governments. Has Congress exceeded its authority? Is a uniform national rule required? Does 106 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective Congress intend to pre-empt the whole Þeld of legislation? Since 1937 and Franklin Roosevelt’s battle to pack the Court, it has almost invariably sided with the national government. Yet regionalism was not slain by McCulloch, but has remained a sonorous minor theme. Years earlier, Jefferson, whose writings suggest that he imagined the pursuit of happiness to end at a family farm, made clear that he preferred government close to the people as more responsive to their needs, fears, and desires. (In this, he was not always consistent, opposing Washington and Hamilton’s national bank, but while in the White House he aggressively expanded presidential authority by purchasing the vast Louisiana Territory.) His Kentucky Resolutions, written to protest the Alien and Sedition Acts (1798) that he believed abridged civil liberties, stand as a classic justiÞcation of states’ rights. Echoing the failed Articles, he reasserted the vision of the Constitution as compact, denying that the national government was “the exclusive or Þnal judge of the extent of the powers delegated to itself, since that would have made its discretion, and not the Constitution, the measure of its powers” (Jefferson 17:379). Instead, he argued each state, as a party to the compact that created the nation, could decide whether the agreement had been violated, and if so, what action could be taken. Kentucky determined that the Alien and Sedition Acts violated the Constitution, and announced that it would refuse to enforce them. A decade later, when Jefferson had Congress pass the Embargo Act directed against British depredations on the high seas, his foes in New England condemned him with his own Kentucky Resolutions’ words. The most prominent nineteenth-century regionalist was undoubtedly John C. Calhoun, secretary of war, vice president, senator from South Carolina, and the South’s most renowned antebellum Þgure. Calhoun Þrst drew attention as a vigorous advocate of national power, speaking in favor of protective tariffs, a national bank, and congressionally funded infrastructure; however, once South Carolina developed a cotton-based, export-import driven economy and the competitive North grew in population and prosperity, he opposed tariffs and formulated militant defenses of states’ rights. When Congress adopted what he called the Tariff of Abominations (1828), Calhoun protested that the Constitution gave states, acting through popularly elected conventions, the right to nullify national laws within their borders, even referring to secession. In South Carolina’s Ordinance of NulliÞcation, he complained that the tariff forced the South “to sell low and . . . to buy high . . . . Our ruin must follow.” Hence, an attempt to enforce the tariff in South Carolina would be “inconsistent with the larger continuance in the Union” (Calhoun, Works 5:21). (The Ordinance went nowhere, as President Andrew Jackson had Congress pass a Force Bill, giving him military authority to carry out the law; later, he had Congress lower the tariffs, and in return South Carolina repealed the Ordinance.) 107 Thomas Halper In A Disquisition on Government (1850), which appeared shortly after his death, Calhoun elaborated on his argument for nulliÞcation. The democratic right to vote, if unchecked, would degenerate into a tyranny of the majority over dissenting groups and interests, he claimed. Madison’s answer had been factions checking and balancing each other in society, a key supplement to the checks and balances in government. But Calhoun thought this inadequate, fearing that it would instead make it “easy for one portion of the community to pervert its power to oppress and plunder the other” (Calhoun, Disquisition 4). Thus, he proposed that the numerical majority be countered by a concurrent majority representing all interests concerned. As he conceived interests essentially in regional terms, he would locate the concurrent majority mostly at the state level. The Constitution, in his view, was created by the pre-existing states as a compact among them, with each entitled to protect its core interests from the whole. If a state believed these interests to be threatened, it should be able to call a popularly elected convention to consider nulliÞcation. The federal government could then reverse the nulliÞcation through a constitutional amendment, and if the amendment were adopted, a state could choose either to accept defeat or to secede. Because this process would be both lengthy and damaging to all sides, Calhoun thought it would “cause the different interests . . . to desist from attempting to adopt any measure calculated to promote the prosperity of one, or more, by sacriÞcing that of others, and thus to force them to unite [to] promote the prosperity of all”(Calhoun, Disquisition 28). Instead, many feared that Calhoun’s concurrent majorities plan would encourage intransigence by drawing out negotiations and emboldening hold outs. What was undisputed was that his plan would make it much harder for the national government to act, but inasmuch as events in one state may have consequences for another, this national weakness could generate all sorts of problems. Consider industrial pollution carried by winds across state boundaries; businesses in the originating states would want to avoid paying for the harm they caused. Absent an overarching national government, how could the businesses be held responsible? Or consider designing a national highway system; how could the government coordinate roads within states so as to form a coherent whole, when each state has its own agenda and the last few hold out states would likely leverage their position? Intransigence, however, was Calhoun’s true goal—intransigence in defense of slavery. The plan never stood a chance of adoption. It is bizarre to contemplate that Calhoun, the preeminent defender of slavery, was also a prominent foe of majority tyranny. (Perhaps the proximity to slaves made liberty taste sweeter; or perhaps liberty for him simply included the liberty to own slaves.) But in any case, the Civil War irreversibly settled the questions of nulliÞcation and secession, and the 13th, 14th, and 15th Amendments that followed stripped the states of much of their former power. No longer could they permit 108 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective slavery, determine citizenship, deny persons equal protection of the law, and deprive persons of life, liberty, and property without due process of law. (In time, this due process clause served as a device to apply most of the Bill of Rights to the states.) But if Calhoun today is mostly of antiquarian interest, regionalists’ states’ rights arguments have continued to be asserted to advance or impede a wide variety of policies. As the nation industrialized in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, business worked to ensure that regulation came from the state level, where it could more easily be manipulated to suit their purposes. The Supreme Court usually agreed, holding insurance (Paul v. Virginia), mining (Carter v. Carter Coal Co.), whisky distilling (Kidd v. Pearson), lumbering (Coe v. Errol), sugar reÞning (United States v. E.C. Knight Co.), and Þshing (Ex parte Fritz) all immune from national regulation. In rulings at war with the principle of national supremacy, the powers reserved to the states in the 10th Amendment were said to limit the powers delegated to Congress in Article I. Similarly, during this period, the South successfully took the position that race relations were entirely the states’ affairs. As African Americans were effectively excluded from the political process and subjected to rigid and elaborate segregation, the result was to shield systematic cruelty and oppression from any remedy. Even anti-lynching bills were impotent in the face of states’ rights claims. More recently, though, some progressives have found some merit in states’ rights, noting that decentralization may empower groups who would otherwise lose out at the national level. Federalism thus allows these groups to translate their rights—to vote, to speak, to organize, to hold ofÞce—into tangible power. That regionalism continues to enjoy robust support was well illustrated in a 2012 Pew Research Center poll. In the decade 2002-2012, the poll found that favorable ratings of the national government dropped almost by half from sixty-four to thirtythree percent. At the same time, ratings for state governments declined only from sixty-four to Þfty-two percent, and local governments only from sixty-seven to sixtyone percent. By substantial margins, respondents gave states higher marks than the national government for honesty, meeting people’s needs, efÞciency, being able to put partisanship aside and work together, and being careful with the people’s money. Centralization Historically, there can be little question that federalism has been characterized by growing centralization. Direct spending by the national government—to the aged on Social Security and Medicare, to veterans receiving beneÞts, to students getting loans or grants, to corporations awarded defense or other contracts, to scientists working in nationally supported health institutions or laboratories—is enormous, 109 Thomas Halper and its trajectory steadily rises. Too, funds offered by Washington to the states may provide overwhelming leverage. Policy areas once dominated by states may now have a large national presence. In education, to take one of the states’ chief functions, states are no longer free to require racial segregation, and with George W. Bush’s No Child Left Behind and Barack Obama’s Race to the Top, Washington expressed its dissatisfaction with the states’ approaches and became involved in shaping the classroom experience. In President Obama’s controversial Affordable Care Act (2010), the national government also increased its inßuence over health care. Insistent voices have bemoaned (and exaggerated) this centralization. Can anything be done to counter it? Since the late 1970s, there has been considerable talk of devolution, which entails dispatching decisions to the state level or to private actors (privatization). Periodic paroxysms of populism or ßirtations with the free market may provide the impetus, and information technology may have provided an attractive example of decentralization in action. Thus, Congress, for example, in its 1996 welfare reform act gave states much more power over eligibility criteria, beneÞts, and administration than they possessed under the old system; in transportation and communications policy Congress has eliminated a great deal of the pre-existing mass of regulations, thereby setting businesses free. The contending movements toward centralization and devolution and away from regionalism point to an important fact about federalism: it is a dynamic system always in ßux. Elaborate justiÞcations supporting or opposing change are frequently wrapped in philosophical or historical references, but the driving forces are almost always practical considerations of policy or partisan self-interest driven by mundane or crisis level concerns. The Persistence of Regionalism Though the long term trend is toward centralization, regionalism remains robust, and there are powerful functional and structural factors that have contributed to its persistence. The Constitution created a rough division of functions, delegating to the national government control over activities like defense, foreign relations, and interstate commerce, which seem to concern the whole republic or which require the nation to speak with one voice. Here the national government must be the master of its own affairs and not dependent upon the states, which might pull it in different directions or prevent it from acting altogether. Many of the national government’s powers reinforce each other. Its power to regulate commerce, for example, is heightened by its power to coin money, tax, operate a postal service, and regulate bankruptcies, patents, and copyrights. Typically, the national government’s powers appear in the Constitution in very imprecise terms, although they were not intended to be unlimited. 110 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective Powers not delegated to the national government or forbidden to the states are reserved either to the states or the people by the 10th Amendment. These reserve powers (which are not spelled out) encompass functions like health, education, sanitation, and public safety, the basic tasks that affect ordinary citizens nearly every day. The Framers thought it best to leave these functions to the various states and localities to determine according to their differing needs and desires, though the national government has since become a major player here. Federalism is so practical a concept that even this rough division of functions may suggest sharper distinctions than actually exist. Thus, though federalism is often spoken of as a layer cake, it should more usefully be conceived as a marble cake, where the swirl of colors suggests the mix of functions (Grodzins 265). Nor is this a recent development. As early as 1785—two years before the constitutional convention—the central government, weak as it was, was involved in the local function of education. Many intergovernmental enterprises have been driven by central government grants-in-aid to the states. Until World War I, these grants consisted chießy of land, and were designed principally to promote education and agriculture. From World War I to the Great Depression, grants were largely money for highway construction. Since the Depression, the emphasis has changed to public welfare, unemployment assistance, and Social Security. It has never been hard to understand state and local enthusiasm for the grant idea. By permitting state and local ofÞcials the ecstasy of spending without the agony of taxing, federal aid has seemed to many politicians a bountiful gift from heaven, and they have organized to lobby Congress to preserve Washington as a magniÞcent money machine. Though they love to receive grants, states frequently complain about how difÞcult it is to apply for money and how many conditions are imposed on its expenditure. The root cause, they claim, is the arrogance of a Washington convinced that it always knows best. Washington ofÞcials reply that as the grants consist of money raised from the nation as a whole and are intended to fulÞll national objectives, they must be spent as Congress intended. They maintain that the charge that Washington unilaterally imposes arbitrary regulations on states and localities is very far from the mark. State and local ofÞcials invariably are given opportunities to shape federal legislation and regulations, and bargaining with an eye toward adjusting differences through compromise is far more common than take-it-or-leave-it commands. Still, if states Þnd the central government’s conditions that onerous, they always retain the option of not asking for the money. Congress has supplemented the grant system with unfunded mandates, in which the national government instructs states to carry out certain tasks, but provides them with little or no money with which to do them. This reverses the usual pattern 111 Thomas Halper of states feeding off the national government. In response to criticism, Congress passed the Unfunded Mandates Reform Act in 1995, but the states continue to complain about education, environmental, and other programs, where they contend the practice continues. What emerges from the whole picture is a grant system heavily marbled with intergovernmental conßict and cooperation. Yet the broad goals remain: to establish national standards for particular services through the imposition of nationwide guidelines; to induce states and localities to adopt policies that the central government has no constitutional authority to require on its own; and to redistribute resources from richer and more densely populated regions to poorer and more sparsely populated regions. As a consequence, grants have become important as weapons of policy and politics. Innovation, however, is by no means monopolized by Washington. States have often served, in Brandeis’s words, as the “laboratories of democracy,” developing primary elections, referenda, anti-discrimination policies, and welfare reforms, some of which the national government subsequently made its own. Federal courts, particularly the Supreme Court, have also been important in blurring the distinction between national and state functions. Education, for example, has always been considered one of the premier functions of the states, and yet the Supreme Court insisted that they were not free legally to require schools to be racially segregated (Brown v. Board of Education); similarly, the Court instructed state and local police to inform suspects of their rights (Miranda v. Arizona) and state and local legislative bodies to apportion themselves on a one-person-onevote principle (Reynolds v. Sims). Reinforcing the national/regional division of functions is a system of independent, though similar, structures. The national and state governments are elected separately and govern separately (though the Constitution gives states a role as states in the Senate and the Electoral College). Both the national and state levels, however, are organized into legislative, executive, and judicial branches. (Nebraska’s legislature has only one chamber.) This parallel structure is not mandated by the Constitution, which requires only that states follow the republican form of government. Beyond the separation of powers, however, immense diversity and further decentralization is apparent, as each state is subdivided into counties, school districts, and special purpose districts. No single national scheme is followed. Counties may be headed by legislatures, elected commissions, or executives; they may be charged with important tasks (Maryland’s counties are responsible for schools) or be conÞned largely to ceremonies (like the Þve counties that comprise New York City). School districts generally feature elected boards, and are funded almost entirely from local property taxes and state aid; they have radically decreased in number, as rural districts have been consolidated in the name of 112 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective improving education. Special purpose districts target speciÞc issues, like mass transit, sewage, water, or soil conservation. They have proliferated and become more important because they can tackle issues that cross political boundaries, because they are willing to address problems that frighten elected ofÞcials, and because their technocratic focus and low public visibility allows them to get things done with relative efÞciency An example is New York City’s Metropolitan Transit Authority, which operates subways and buses in the city, as well as commuter trains to the suburbs. Complicating matters still further, some states and localities have decided to save money by outsourcing certain tasks (like operating prisons) or have even sold infrastructure (like highways) to private companies. One consequence is that regional politics has remained vigorous and independent of national control. This, in turn, has helped to root parties at the state and local level, rendering them far more decentralized than most of their European counterparts. It has also offered the opposing party an opportunity to develop attractive candidates and proposals that it can use to challenge the party in power. Four of the past six presidents have been governors, and every one of them had been in the opposition party. In this sense, federalism facilitates the electoral competition that is so vital to democracy. And, of course, the vigor of state and local politics guarantees that states and localities will themselves retain signiÞcance as political players. Another consequence is that the parallel structures act as one of the system’s most prominent checks and balances. National/regional conßict is endemic, as each level seeks to exercise control over the same issue or to tax the same citizens. Cooperation, however, is endemic, too. Often this takes place informally, as national and state ofÞcials discuss mutual problems in an effort to achieve satisfactory solutions in a spirit of responsibility and compromise. But sometimes cooperation is achieved formally in such areas as the regulation of utilities and certain other major industries, environmental and navigation programs, supervision of elections, and the construction of public improvements. In a few areas, the Constitution demands cooperation, but most often it is simply permissive. With checks and balances comes the criticism of insufÞcient coordination, for it is the very essence of compromise that neither side receives all it sought, and so the result will nearly always appear to some as truncated or inadequate. If there were no regional entities and only national ofÞcials issuing orders, policies might be far more comprehensive, uniform, and logically consistent. But, of course, as defenders of federalism like to point out, this would not necessarily be a good thing. Compromises frequently improve policies by forcing consideration of a variety of interests and perspectives. And the prospect of national ofÞcials issuing orders without state interference may seem to hold the promise of a disturbing authoritarianism. 113 Thomas Halper The problem of coordinating national and state entities is exacerbated by competition among the states, chießy for productive citizens and businesses. Those sympathetic to the competition see it as essential in enforcing Þnancial discipline on the states and limiting the reach of their governments. By providing a range of options, it is said to enhance liberty. Critics believe, however, that by forcing states to compete for jobs and taxes, this competition unfairly strengthens the hand of corporations, who can leverage offers from one state to extort beneÞts from another. Hence, talk of a race to the bottom. The Constitution recognizes only states as regional governing bodies. Cities, towns, counties, and other local government units are simply not mentioned. Rather, they are considered creatures of the state, created by a state for its convenience and thus vulnerable to a state’s decision either to alter the arrangement or even to abolish the unit. According to the Dillon Rule (announced by an Iowa judge, John F. Dillon, in an inßuential treatise on municipal corporations) all municipal powers should be construed narrowly, and “any fair, reasonable, substantial doubt” be resolved against the municipality (1:448). How is it that a people celebrating self government have denied independence to the level of government most responsive to their desires? This apparent anomaly is not always borne out in fact. Most state constitutions grant large cities at least partial home rule, and localities are both represented in legislatures and able to defend their interests. Still, limitations on local governance are undeniable. Small cities and towns are denied home rule. Cities frequently need state approval to impose taxes, and issues of city-suburb relations that bubble-up in questions of commuter taxes and public transportation ordinarily are decided not by the contestants but by the state. Local governments are also restrained in their authority to borrow money, and key special purpose districts are created by the state and beyond the control of the localities within which they operate. A New Regionalism? With the post-World War II era, the urban-rural dichotomy began to be trumped by the exponential growth of suburbs. At Þrst derided as bedroom communities dependent on adjacent cities for employment and culture, they have long since become much more self sufÞcient and self contained. Indeed, it has become a cliché for residents to claim for suburbia the best of both city and country, with its shopping and entertainment choices plus its low crime and single-family homes with lawns. Suburbs have generally used their boundaries to protect themselves from what they see as the problems of the cities (crime, poverty, inferior public services). Racial and economic segregation, though rarely openly acknowledged, has also sometimes been a chief concern. Cities often speak of the advantages of annexing 114 Does Region Really Matter? A Constitutional Perspective suburbs into metropolitan governing units or adopting tax-base sharing that connect the localities economically, but these proposals are rarely implemented due to suburban opposition. At the same time, formal jurisdictional borders have lost much of their salience, as the lines between city and suburb or between suburb and suburb have become so indistinct as almost to disappear. Increasingly, Americans identify places in terms of highways (the PaciÞc Coast Highway or the Long Island Expressway) or the names of shopping malls (Woodbury Commons or the Mall of America), ignoring the town identiÞcation entirely. Many suburbs (unlike typical small towns) are too new to have much in the way of historical identity or traditions. (Gated communities, generally high priced, function almost as small, private governments.) The proliferation of suburbs has also undercut the stereotype of the wealthy enclave, for over half the poor in large metropolitan areas live in suburbs, which often have not developed the appropriate institutions (social service agencies, clinics, etc.), while sizable numbers of the well-to-do have moved to cities. Quality of life and Þnancial complaints (trafÞc congestion, taxes, high energy costs) that once damned cities are now often heard plaguing suburbs. And though well paying jobs remain disproportionately in suburbs, sizable numbers of the prosperous and young professionals have chosen to live in cities, giving rise to the controversial phenomenon of gentriÞcation. With suburbs, region has taken on meanings that Jefferson and Calhoun could scarcely have imagined. Conclusions The Constitution, with its federal structure, has helped to ensure both the dominance of the national government and the vitality of regional governments. Other factors—history, ideology, geography, technology, and so on—also have been in play. A consequence has been that in an era generally considered hospitable to centralization, regionalism remains healthy and vigorous. With the Constitution focusing so heavily on the national government, state and local governance has essentially been left to the ordinary political process. The outcome, in a nation as large and diverse as the United States, has been a rather stunning variety of institutions, approaches, and policies. Some of the resulting rhetoric has embraced politics; some has disdained politics; none of the players has avoided politics. The talk is generally of “good government” or “what works,” but self interest rarely abdicates its position of dominance. This preoccupation with the practical is exactly what the preeminently practical Framers had in mind and why, today as in 1787, region matters. 115 Thomas Halper Works Cited Bach, John M., and Frederick D. Stone. Pennsylvania and the Federal Constitution, 1787-1788. Philadelphia: Historical Society of Pennsylvania, 1888. Brown v. Board of Education. 347 U.S. 483 (1954). Calhoun, John C. Works. New York: D. Appleton, 1855. _____.A Disquisition on Government and a Discourse on the Constitution and Government, Richard K. Cralle ,ed.. Columbia: General Assembly of South Carolina, 1851. Carson River Lumbering Co. v. Patterson. 33 Cal. 334 (1867). Carter v. Carter Coal Co. 298 U.S. 238 (1936). Coe v. Errol. 116 U.S.57 (1886). Dillon, John F. Commentaries on the Law of Municipal Corporations. Boston: Little, Brown, 1911. Drake, Francis S. The Life and Correspondence of Henry Knox, Major-General in the American Revolutionary Army. Boston: S.G. Drake, 1873. Ex parte Fritz. 86 Miss. 210 (1905). Grodzins, Morton. “The Federal System,” in Goals for Americans. New York: American Assembly, 1960. 265-82. Jefferson, Thomas. Writings, Albert Ellery Bergh, ed. Washington: Thomas Jefferson Memorial Association, 1907. Ketcham, Ralph. James Madison. New York: Macmillan, 1971. Kidd v. Pearson. 128 U.S. 1 (1888). Madison, James. Papers, ed. William T. Hutchinson et al. Chicago and Charlottesville: University of Chicago Press and University of Virginia Press, 1962. _____. Writings, ed. Jack N. Rakove. New York: Library of America, 1999. McCulloch v. Maryland. 17 U.S. 316 (1819). Miranda v. Arizona. 384 U.S. 436 (1966). Paul v. Virginia. 75 U.S. 168 (1869). Pew Research Center. “Growing Gap in Favorable Views of Federal, State Governments.” April 26, 2012. Reynolds v. Sims. 377 U.S. 533 (1964). “Thatcher Papers.” History Magazine, November, 1869. United States v. E.C.Knight. 156 U.S. 1 (1896). 116
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz