Donald Winch Free Trade, Cosmopolitanism and the Political Economy of National Identity An open lecture given at Kyoto University, Thursday, May 7, 1992. I am pleased to have been invited to spend the next six weeks with the Faculty of Economics at Kyoto University under British Council auspices. I am also grateful to Professors Sechiyama and Yagi for their efforts in organising this visit. This is my third trip to Kyoto during the last five years, and I hope it will help to establish closer relations with my own university. As some of you will realise, however, I am not perhaps the best person to forge closer relations between economists here and in Sussex. Although I was originally trained as an economist at the London School of Economics and later at Princeton University, and although I have served as an editor of the Economic Journal and continue to serve as the Publications Secretary of the Royal Economic Society, my research and teaching is now concentrated entirely on intellectual history, with a strong tendency to move sidewards from the history of economics into the history of social and political ideas. It is certainly a long time since I have done any research that relates to current economic issues. Moreover, my interpretation of how intellectual history should be written prevents me from claiming that it is highly relevant to modern economics. There have been periods when theoretical debate in economics has been conducted on the territory cultivated by historians of economics, the best examples being: Adam Smith's quarrel with his mercantile and physiocratic predecessors; Marx's work on theories of surplus value; the arguments by the early marginalist as to whether they were engaged in a revolutionary or evolutionary process of intellectual change; Keynes's attempt to express his own position in terms of a rejection of 'classical economics'; and the debates over capital and growth theory in the nineteen-sixties which turned on the relative merits of classical and Marxian approaches to value and distribution compared with neo-classical models. But these examples, in my opinion, also demonstrate how, while you can often derive challenging historical hypotheses 1 from such disputes, good history rarely comes from its use as a weapon in methodological and ideological controversies. Good history of economics, like any other form of intellectual history, comes from consistent efforts over a long period to pose intelligent historical questions about past writers and their texts. It also entails detailed detective work of a biographical or bibliographical kind that, like all empirical work, can only be of interest to those who already want to know the answers. In formulating interpretations of historical texts it is often more important to examine the contemporary context than it is to focus on supposed similarities or dissimilarities between the past and the present. Since I hold these rather old-fashioned views of history you will appreciate why I cannot proselytize for the history of economics as an essential element in the education of economists. If economists are interested in past economists and their texts, so much the better; but I do not feel able or willing to argue that they ought to be interested. Nor, incidentally, have I ever thought of what I do as a purely antiquarian pursuit, as though I was engaged in rearranging and dusting the specimens in some kind of museum of quaint and outmoded economic models. The authors I have studied, and the kinds of questions that have moved them to write as they did, seem alive to me, and it is my duty as an historian to make them come alive to readers. But that presumes the readers have an interest in the first place, which is something one cannot assume among economists today. To use another metaphor, if I were a military historian I would not assume that today's soldiers are necessarily going to be interested in learning how past battles were won or lost. Soldiers who are fighting today's battles may wish to spend more time on improving their weapons and tactics in other ways. To judge solely from the number of historians of economics I have met in Japan, the field is in a much healthier condition than it is in Britain. I understand some of the reasons for this state of affairs, and I hope to learn more during my visit. By inviting me to spend this period at Kyodai you have done me the honour of expressing an interest in my research, but I shall not abuse your hospitality and tolerance too much by speaking about it on this occasion. 2 Instead, I have chosen a speculative topic which may be of more interest to economists, even though it largely consists of historical reflections and raises more questions than it answers. *** I have used 'political economy' in the title of this lecture because I wish to combine politics and economics in order to speak about something I have called, rather vaguely, "national identity". But there is an immediate tension or paradox involved in trying to do this which I can best express by raising two questions. The first flows from a well-known distinction. Whereas science, by definition, is a cosmopolitan enterprise, many other fields of study are characteristically local or national in their sympathies and interests. The distinction is best expressed in the language of the nation where the underlying issues were first formulated clearly, namely German, where a dividing line was drawn betweenNaturwissenchaftenand Geisteswissenchaften. Thus if we speak about Japanese or British biology or physics, it is only to describe a non-essential feature of these natural sciences -- the nationality of those doing it and the national institutions within which they are organised to do so. There may also be divergent cultural patterns of interest for which an historical explanation may be required, but on any matter of common concern there ought not to be any essential differences in what counts as knowledge. My first question then becomes: does economics conform with this scientific model, and if so, has it always done so? Alternatively, is economics more like other cultural branches of study -- literature, for example -- where we expect there to be greater national, religious and ethnic differences, and where nationality and historical tradition matters as much, if not more than the cosmopolitanism I have associated with the natural sciences. My second question is more directly about economics: while a politics of national identity makes perfectly good sense, an economics of national identity is more difficult to conceive -- far more so than,say, an economics of national survival or even an economics of national sovereignty. Is this a comment on economists and the kind of discipline that economics has become, or does it say something about the nature of the world in which we live? 3 Both of these questions are too large one for anyone to answer in a single talk, and I am fully aware of my own lack of qualifications as a mere historian of economics for providing answers. Many years ago, when I was a pupil first of James Meade and secondly of Jacob Viner, I was better qualified to tackle the question -- or so I thought. At that time, in the nineteen-fifties and sixties, international economics was coming to grips with the economics of customs unions, free trade areas, and full economic unions involving the harmonization of monetary and fiscal policies. Before the European Economic Community made these matters a practical reality, international economics was trying to work out how to analyse the various categories of gain or loss resulting from regional or partial movements towards the goal of multilateral free trade, and how to measure those gains and losses.1 Multilateral free trade represented the bench-mark against which we felt that it was relevant to judge the effects of regional economic union on the welfare of individual members or on the world at large. We were aware of the various arguments that had been advanced for protection -- the valid and invalid ones, judged from an economic point of view -- but we remained confident that multilateral free trade was the essential bench-mark, despite the fact that it existed only as an ideal state. What this reflects, of course, is the overwhelmingly liberal character of the tradition of economics in which I was educated -- a tradition which was particularly strong in the Anglo-American world, though not as firmly rooted in some other European countries, where it had been challenged by alternatives deriving from the German historical tradition and by Marxism. Regional movements towards free trade were merely second-best, which is why the name given to this branch of applied welfare economics was the theory of the second best, and why we thought it was the duty of an economist to speak up for a truly cosmopolitan perspective. My teachers, Meade and Viner, though not agreed on all matters connected with the economics of customs unions, were prime representatives of this liberal cosmopolitanism in economics. The economic nationalism of the interwar period in which 1 As an illustration of work that was then central see J. Viner, The Customs Union Issue, New York, 1950; J. E. Meade, The Theory of Customs Union, Amsterdam, 1955, an expansion of his Problems of Economic Union, Chicago, 1952 and part of his larger work on The Theory of Economic Policy, Oxford, 1951-5; and T. Scitovsky, Economic Theory and Western European Integration, London, 1958. 4 they reached manhood provided their original battleground; and they were both active during and after the Second World War in trying to create a world order that would minimize the scope for economic nationalism. The monuments to this world order were, of course, the International Monetary Fund, the World Bank, and the General Agreement on Trade and Tariffs. I can now see that I was educated as an international economist at a peak period in liberal economic optimism. The only dark clouds on the horizon were those associated with the economics of underdevelopment in the Third World, and even here we felt that wisdom would eventually prevail if the post-war institutions of the IMF, IBRD, and GATT were allowed to function as intended. I do not know how Japanese economists of my generation were being educated in the nineteen-fifties. That is something else I hope to learn about during my stay in Kyoto. I suspect that many of them were being educated in a different way, with a stronger emphasis on the power disparities at work in international economic relations, possibly deriving from Marxist sources. The view of the world from Britain's position on the edge of the Atlantic rim was also probably different from the view of the world from Japan's position on the edge of the Pacific rim -- at a time when Japan was about to launch itself on its meteoric career as a world economic power. Perhaps you will tell me during the question period what these differences were and are. I mention my own educational formation as an economist only because it could help you to understand what I now want to say as an historian. *** What I have called the liberal cosmopolitanism of the economics I learned was built into the fabric of the discipline in Britain at its outset. That is something I have come to appreciate more as a result of becoming a historian. International trade theory was very much the creation of such figures as Adam Smith, David Ricardo and John Stuart Mill; it was an extension to world trade of what Smith called the 'system of natural liberty'. Free competition, free movements of goods, and free movement of labour and capital, both within and between nations, were the central clues to economic growth and prosperity. The fact that Smith chose a plural title for his work,An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, 5 was a sign of his acceptance of the Enlightenment belief that criteria could be formulated to establish comparative national performance on a universal or cosmopolitan scale. It was never quite as simple as this sounds because in the course of articulating the case for free trade, the economists I have mentioned encountered many of the difficulties that have become familiar ever since. There were arguments within the political economy camp about exceptions to free trade on grounds of national security, with Malthus, for example, tentatively going further by trying to formulate the case for protection of Britain's capacity to maintain a higher degree of self-sufficiency in subsistence goods than free trade would allow. The British classical economists also had to deal with the problems of trade between large and small nations, rich and poor nations, and the complex issues connected with the British empire and colonisation. 2 There was even a debate provoked by Robert Torrens on the wisdom of establishing an imperial zollverein or customs union. They were also alert to the welfare problems of gauging the impact of free trade on different groups of producers within Britain. There would be gainers and losers, though the fact that Smith had identified economics with the study of long-term economic growth and had made consumers' interests rather than producers'interests the test of wise and just policy helped his classical followers to give confident answers on the distributional questions. Free trade became the normative goal according to which policies should be judged, and the fact that other nations in Europe and North America, even Britain's ex-colonies in Australia and Canada, did not accept free trade in the same thorough-going way as Britain was taken as a sign of their misfortune, probably due to defects in the kinds of political systems they had. Thus when Australia was colonized in the 1830s it was seriously suggested that alongside immigrants from all the other trades and professions there should be "at least one good Political Economist at each settlement to prevent us from devising an Australasian tariff."3 If Britain was isolated in being the only major economic power to accept the scientific logic of free trade after she had removed the last vestiges of protection by repealing the Corn 2 The last of these topics was the subject of my doctoral dissertation, written, as I then thought, as a kind of holiday from international economics; see Classical Political Economy and Colonies, London, 1965 and translated into Japanese in 1975 3 Edward Gibbon Wakefield, A Letter from Sydney(1829), Everyman edition, London, 1929, p.85. 6 Laws in 1846, so much the worse for the rest of the world. I can illustrate the dominant mood by citing two highly confident, even arrogant, statements made by John Eliot Cairnes and Walter Bagehot respectively in the 1870s. "Great Britain, if not the birthplace of Political Economy, has at least been its early home, as well as the scene of the most signal triumphs of its manhood. Every great step in the progress of economic science... has been won by English thinkers; and while we have led the van in economic speculation, we have also been the first to apply with boldness our theories to practice. Our foreign trade, our colonial policy, our fiscal system, each has in turn been reconstructed from the foundation upwards under the inspiration of economic ideas; and the population and the commerce of the country, responding to the impulse given by the new principles operating through these changes, have within a century multiplied themselves manifold.4 Bagehot was no less enthusiastic a few years later when celebrating British achievements in the hundred years since the Wealth of Nations appeared. "In that time [political economy] has had a wonderful effect. The life of almost every one in England -- perhaps of every one -- is different and better in consequence of it. The whole commercial policy of the country is not so much founded upon it as instinct with it. Ideas which are paradoxes everywhere else in the world are accepted axioms here as results of it. No other form of political philosophy has every had one thousandth part of the influence on us; its teachings have settled down in to the common sense of the nation, and have become irreversible.5 As I have already hinted, the victory being celebrated here was not achieved without some challenge from other positions. In addition to the spokesmen for various agricultural and industrial interests who stood to lose from free trade, there were others who from the very beginning of the history of economics as a discipline mistrusted its conclusions precisely because they were internationalist or cosmopolitan. The best English illustration of this can 4 "Political Economy and Laissez-Faire", reprinted in Essays on Political Economy: Theoretical and Applied, London, 1873, p.232. 5 Economic Studies, London, 1908, p.1. 7 be found in a statement by the romantic poet and conservative political theorist, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, who frequently complained in the early decades of the nineteenth century about what he called the "denationalising" tendencies of political economy, explaining what he meant by going on to say that it had made "love of our country a foolish superstition". Coleridge's romantic friends believed that "nationality" was bound up with self-sufficiency: "The nation that cannot exist without the commodity of another nation, is in effect the slave of that other nation."6 (I feel sure that you could supply me with Japanese statements of a similar kind.) Coleridge's protest against political economy will indicate why I said just now that it was easier to conceive of a politics of national identity than an economics of national identity: he was correctly diagnosing what was to become a dominant feature of British economic thinking among those who were dedicated to the development of the science. British economists were behaving as though they were leading members of an international scientific community, where the rules of scientific inquiry guaranteed that the truths of political economy were truly cosmopolitan. They were also acting and speaking as though nationality was of little account and as though economists, unlike politicians, had a duty to speak for common humanity, with no presumption that the welfare of individuals of other nationalities was any less weighty than those of one's own nation. It was Friederich List, building on the ideas of the American founding father, Alexander Hamilton, who articulated the largest challenge to the conclusions of the English science. He also provided a useful word to describe its individualistic tendencies and failure, as he saw it, to recognise the importance of national entities, namely "cosmopolitical economy". The object of List's book on The National System of Political Economy (1841) was to unmask what he saw as the bogus origins and influence of this English way of thinking. List was arguing, in effect, that Britain had achieved her national identity by means that denied it to others -- the latecomers in the race to acquire the power that went with manufacturing capacity. As one might expect, neither List nor any of the other spokesmen for protectionism, such as Henry Carey, had much influence on British thinking, though John Stuart Mill gave 6 Table Talk, edited by H. N. Coleridge, London, 1838, pp.288-9. 8 cautious recognition to the "infant-industry" argument for tariffs. Apart from this, Carey's and List's arguments were simply regarded as a reversion to mercantile and pre-scientific fallacies. The climax of the British mood of confidence in free trade came in the writings of those who founded what became known as the Manchester School in the eighteen-fifties and sixties. Thus Richard Cobden and John Bright held that Britain had an almost Christian mission to use its unilateral acceptance of free trade as an example that would convert the rest of the world in the interests of international peace and harmony. By then, however, the free trade movement had ceased to be closely associated with original work in the science of political economy; it had become a political or quasi-religious movement engaged in propaganda. The challenge to the free trade position in the late nineteenth century Britain came from an ex-Liberal politician, Joseph Chamberlain, who led the Tariff Reform campaign -- a campaign that took sustenance from fears that Britain was rapidly losing its industrial hegemony to Germany and America. Economists were recruited on both sides of a dispute that culminated in the defeat of Chamberlain's proposals in the 1903 election, but it is doubtful if any new economic arguments for or against tariffs came from them. They rehearsed the old arguments against a different background. When economists declared in favour of upholding the policy of free trade, or of departing from it, they were either disagreeing about the empirical evidence or giving largely political reasons for their final choice. The single most durable contribution by an economist to the tariff reform debate was Alfred Marshall's Memorandum on Fiscal Policy of International Trade(1903). It was an undogmatic attempt to show that as far as Britain was concerned the change in her competitive position did not warrant a change in her policy on free trade. Her older industries needed the stimulus that came from cheaper and better imports, and the relevant elasticities of demand for her products made it unlikely that she would be able to use tariffs to shift the burden of taxation to foreigners. The older British economists may have been overdogmatic, but the only error of which they were guilty, in Marshall's view, was in not 9 recognising the force of the "infant-industry" case for tariffs in other countries who were industrializing after Britain. The earlier free trade case, Marshall said, "ignored the fact that protection to immature industries is a very great national good; and that, though that good may be bought at too great a cost, it would have been foolish for nations with immature industries to adopt England's system pureand simple."7 But it was also Marshall's conclusion, based on a special empirical study which he made of the effects of American and German protectionism, that any net benefit these countries had derived from this policy had been greatly outweighed by the corruption introduced into their political systems in the course of making tariff policy. Similarly with regard to imperial unity and the other political benefits held out by Chamberlain's case for tariffs and preference to imperial suppliers, Marshall was unconvinced that the benefits should be purchased at the likely cost to British consumers, especially those in lower-income groups. I mention this because I would not like to convey the impression that British economists were guilty of the kind of political naivety one finds in the writings of Cobden and Bright. From the very beginning, in the work of Smith, one finds him taking a non-utopian view of his task of advising policy-makers. Given the power of established producers' interest groups, he was not hopeful that free trade would ever be accepted in Britain. He endorsed the idea that "opulence" would have to be sacrificed for national security; and he also addressed himself to the important second-best questions raised by free trade. Thus he did not think it would be prudent for a small nation to make a unilateral move in this direction: "The very bad policy of one country may thus render it in some measure dangerous and imprudent to establish what would otherwise be the best policy in another." He considered the short-term disturbances of removing trade restrictions as well as such realistic issues as the use of tariffs as a retaliatory device to force reductions by other countries; he also dealt with the case of countervailing duties on imported goods to offset the effects of domestic taxes on importcompeting products.8 Smith was not legislating for some idealised world. 7 8 Official Papers by Alfred Marshall, London, 1926, p. 392 On this see my "Science and the Legislator: Adam Smith and After', Economic Journal, 93, 1983, especially pp.505-11. 10 *** Nevertheless, it is still possible to argue that British economists did not fully confront the political economy of national identity and sovereignty again until they were faced with conflicts between national and international economic policy objectives in the interwar period. Keynes was the first economist to pose these issues in dramatic form during the nineteen-twenties: why should Britain, suffering from high unemployment concentrated in the export industries, subject its currency and interest rates to the international discipline being set up for them by bankers under the gold standard, regardless of the political and shortterm economic costs of this policy? Notice that this was not a question directly raised by free trade, but by the international constraints imposed on national governments by the world monetary system -- a system in which Britain was once the dominant banker, but where her capacity to act in this fashion was under threat as a result of the rise of the United States as a financial power and the weakening of the British economy before and after the First World War. The problems to which Marshall had given a relatively optimistic answer had reappeared in more pessimistic monetary guise. Britain's difficulties in the interwar period were to lead, first, to the forced abandonment of the gold standard in 1931, and subsequently to the abandonment of free trade in 1933. Keynes did not agree with the tariff response, but it was undoubtedly a significant sign that economic recovery was to be sought by more nationalistic methods in the country that had previously shown the greatest commitment to internationalism. At this time Keynes came under fire from more orthodox members of the economics profession for appearing to support economic nationalism, though later in his life, of course, Keynes returned to the full liberal internationalism of his upbringing when he played a major part in designing the post-1945 international institutional order. In recent decades Keynes and Keynesians have been heavily criticised by monetarists, public choice theorists, and those who march under J.M.Buchanan's banner of "constitutional economics". The criticism has centred on the charge that Keynes politicized economics,thereby undoing the greatest achievement of classical economics in the late 11 eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.9 It is certainly true that Keynes, in arguing for selfconscious management in monetary affairs, was undermining a position that was strongly entrenched among central bankers, Treasury officials, and many orthodox economists. This position was summarized by one of them as follows: the great virtue of the gold standard was its "knave-proof" qualities, meaning that inflation, deflation, interest rates and exchange rates were best treated as technical issues involving "automatic" mechanisms and rules of the game that were non-discretionary. (It is similar to one of Marshall's arguments against tariffs, namely that the political case for free trade was simply that "it is not a device, but the absence of a device."10) The position also entailed a sceptical view of the capacity of democratic governments to act responsibly on these vital economic matters: how could you allow the international value of a currency to be determined as part of the promises and counter-promises of a contest for support between political parties? A public choice version of this would ask why you should expect any bureaucratic organisation to be interested in achieving any goal defined as the public interest? It is true that Keynes did not have a high opinion of central bankers and the rules of the gold standard game; he welcomed the relaxation that came with the downfall of the gold standard; and he also supported active fiscal policies by governments during the depression. But it would be a mistake to think that this led him to believe that complex issues of economic management were best left to the political processes at work in democratic governments. The following statement is fairly typical of his attitude: "I believe that the right solution will involve intellectual and scientific elements which must be above the heads of the mass of more or less illiterate voters."11 He was advancing the claims of another form of technocracy, one that wasassociated with the new economics he was working out at the time, and through which he hoped to convert, first his fellow-economists, and secondly politicians and the civil service. But there is some truth in the charge that Keynes politicised economics, even if 9 For a brief statement of the position see Buchanan's article on "constitutional economics" in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 10 Official Papers, p. 394. 11 The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, VIII, p. 295. For more evidence on this see my "Economic Knowledge and Government in Britain" in M. Furner and B. Supple (eds), The State and Economic Knowledge; The American and British Experience, Cambridge, 1990, pp. 40-70. 12 he did not wish to politicise economic policy-making. Keynes spent a good deal of time showing that supposedly "knave-proof" mechanisms were not automatic; that they involved discretion, and that discretion opened up possibilities of choosing between alternative policy goals, between inflation and deflation, between unemployment and exchange rate stability, and so on. I mention this historical episode because it has returned to haunt members of the European Economic Community as they move towards ever closer economic union, with the prospect of a single currency in sight and the removal this year of all remaining restrictions on the movement of goods, services, and factors of production across EC internal frontiers. In principle at least, the economics of these developments is fairly straightforward; they turn on the case for regional movements towards free trade, and they only become difficult if one thinks that the trade-diverting effects are more serious to the world at large than the tradecreating and trade-expansion effects of regional economic union. If these problems are not thought to be serious, an economic union represents the ultimate goal of the cosmopolitan political economy I have been describing, which has always found it more congenial to treat nations as though they were aberrant regions. After all, the origin of that branch of the subject called international economics, can be found in the following questions: why does a theory of value that works in the case of interregional trade not apply to trade between nations? Why do the competitive forces that work within nations to determine where production should best be located from the consumers' point of view not work between nations? The answer lies, of course, in the half-realistic assumption of early nineteenth-century Europe that whereas both goods and factors are mobile within nations only goods are mobile between nations. If we apply this to Europe after 1992, and after whatever form of monetary union emerges, we arrive at a Europe of economic regions rather than nations. Interregional economics takes over from international economics. The politics of the situation, however, are a good deal more complex. For various reasons connected as much with history and culture as economics, Britain has had more difficulty than other members of the EC in accepting the pace and scale of the movement towards 13 closer economic and political union. It may be significant, however, that Mrs Thatcher's antiEuropean stance played a major part in her downfall within the Conservative party, and that the issue has hardly featured in the recent British election campaign. Outright opposition to what is described as the loss of national sovereignty in economic affairs is confined to the far right and far left of the British political spectrum. Indeed, if Keynes were alive today he would be struck by the irony of a situation in which it is the anti-Keynesian monetarists who are closest to the "nationalist" position he adopted for a time during the interwar period. The monetarists are bitterly opposed to Britain's entry into the European monetary system because it curbs her freedom of action over interest rates and monetary policy. On the far left the fears are mostly focussed on the loss of autonomy by a socialist government to engage in the kind of national planning and protection to vulnerable groups that their kind of anti-market socialism makes preeminent. They are, if you like, in a comparable position to East German communists who can now point to the disastrous effects of union with an economically more powerful economic neighbour at an exchange rate that took no account of the enormous disparities between the two parts of Germany. It has brought massive unemployment at a time when the old political apparatus of East Germany has been dismantled. Leaving these extreme conditions and positions to one side, however, there are still large political problems for those in the centre. For different reasons perhaps, the Conservative, Liberal Democratic and Labour parties in Britain have all accepted membership of the European exchange system, with the two largest parties reserving their position on a single currency and other features of closer union. They accept the loss of freedom to devalue or pursue a divergent monetary policy in the belief that the system involves closer control over inflation. Although Labour supporters have traditionally been most suspicious of central bankers -- whom they do not regard as being famous for their responsiveness to the needs of the unemployed, the under-educated, and the sick and the poor -- they have now placed their trust in what is called the Social Fund and the Social Chapter of the EC, where the fund is to compensate regions harmed by free trade and the chapter regulates working conditions throughout Europe. They see this as a European way of obtaining the kinds of welfare 14 commitments that Conservative governments have attempted to dismantle in Britain. For this very reason, the Conservative party is largely opposed to the Social Chapter. But there are still major unresolved political issues here. Does membership of the Exchange Rate Mechanism entail being tied to the policies of the German Bundesbank? Or will it open the door to a genuinely European-wide monetary authority? Has there ever been an international economic order that has not required, if only implicitly, a dominant single country capable and willing of exercising leadership, whether it has been London, New York, Bonn or Tokyo? If so, can one really imagine a collaborative and consensual method of managing currencies? Can monetary management by a central European bank be divorced from control over other aspects of public finance such as government deficits and borrowing requirements? To whom would the members of this authority be accountable? How far would their powers extend? As these questions indicate, the largest problems are still those centring on bureaucracy and political accountability in a Europe that has still not developed strong parliamentary institutions that command any respect or legitimacy. It is one thing to accept the disciplines implied in membership of an exchange rate system, and even British national pride in the pound sterling is unlikely to remain a barrier to acceptance of a single currency if there is a danger of Londonlosing its present position as a banking centre. But the loss of political control by a British Parliament is far more sensitive, especially when Britain has no tradition of written constitutions and bills of rights interpreted by judicial authorities. What authority will emerge that is capable of dealing with the social and economic disparities that exist today and could -- in what may be a long adjustment period -- be widened by the effect of closer union? The difficulties of achieving German reunion gives us some idea of how difficult these disparities are to deal with, even when there is a clear national governing body, a common language, and the memories of previous nationhood. Since I do not have answers to any of these questions, I will conclude this lecture in historical vein. In the light of some British fears about joining any monetary union dominated by Germany, I cannot resist the temptation to cite List's prediction in 1837 of the likely effects of a British-dominated free trade world. 15 "All England would ...be developed into one immense manufacturing city. Asia, Africa, and Australia would be civilised by England, and covered with new states modelled after the English fashion. In time a world of English states would be formed, under the presidency of the mother state, in which the European Continental nations would be lost as unimportant, unproductive races. By this arrangement it would fall to the lot of France, together with Spain and Portugal, to supply this English world with the choicest wines, and to drink the bad ones herself; at most France might retain the manufacture of a little millinery. Germany would scarcely have more to supply this English world with than childrens' toys, wooden clocks, and philological writings...It would not require many centuries before people in this English world would think and speak of the Germans and the French in the same tone as we speak at present of the Asiatic nations." I leave you to consider whether you would give this high or low marks for its predictive qualities. In my opinion it was roughly true for only the first third of the period that has elapsed since 1837. What has happened since is common knowledge: the English-speaking world, first in Britain and more recently in North America, has lost much of its earlier dominance, and Germany, despite its present difficulties with reunion, has become the major economic power in Europe. One of the Asiatic nations referred to so dismissively by List, Japan, now leads the way, bringing other Asiatic nations in its train. Does economics have the power as a science to analyse, let alone predict, what will happen in the next century? What will be the balance between national identity and cosmopolitanism in the next wave of developments? It would be fitting if it was a Japanese economist who showed us how to deal with these questions. 16
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz