A CRITIQUE OF WESTERN CONFLICT RESOLUTION FROM A NONWESTERN PERSPECITVE PAUL E.SALEM THE FOLLOWING ARE reflections on the premises and assumptions of Western conflict resolution as viewed from another cultural perspective, in this case, Arab. They derive from exposure to conflict writings and simulations in a Western milieu and the experience of teaching conflict resolution in a non-Western context, namely in Beirut. The essay aims to present a tentative critique of some hidden assumptions in the Western approach to conflict resolution, and to provide some insights into the macro-cultural framework to which Western conflict resolution approaches must adapt if they are to be used in the Arab world-and perhaps also in other areas of the non-Western world. One must make clear from the beginning that any attempt to make broad generalizations about two diverse and loosely defined cultural and social groupings as "the West" and" the Arab world" is fraught with dangers of reductionism, essentialism, and simplification, to say nothing of Orientalism (Said 1978). The effort of finding general cultural patterns and tendencies, however, is, I think, well worth the risk and the effort; and the generalizations presented are only intended as food for thought and signposts for further research rather than as definitive conclusions. Also, it should not be understood from the text that Arab society does not have effective conflict resolution methods of its own. Indeed, such methods are widespread and considerably effective. This paper, however, is more narrowly concerned with developing a sober view of Western approaches to conflict resolution than with exploring indigenous Arab methods of conflict resolution. Peace and Empire The Western community of conflict resolution theorists and practitioners operate within a macro-political context that they may overlook, but which colors their attitudes and values. This seems remarkably striking from an outsider's point of view and is largely related to the West's dominant position in the world. All successful "empires" develop an inherent interest in peace. The ideology of peace reinforces a status quo that is favorable to the dominant power. The Romans, for example, preached a Pax Romana, the British favored a Pax Britannica, and the Americans today pursue - consciously or not - a Pax Americana. Conflict and bellicosity is useful - indeed essential - in building empires, but an ideology of peace and conflict resolution is clearly more appropriate for its maintenance. Indeed, for many outsiders, it is quite common to view Western international conflict resolution policies, whether in the Arab-Israeli peace process, the UN Security Council, or elsewhere, as merely stratagems for defusing opposition to and rejection of the status quo. To the dominated members of a "pseudo-imperial" world system, peace may be something that they might indeed seek to avoid, and conflict may be an objective that they might seek to invigorate in order to destabilize the world system and precipitate its crisis or collapse. They may prefer to bum the temple down, rather than succumb to the worship of a foreign god. The debatable virtues of peace and the underestimated virtues of battle Other than the interest a triumphant West naturally has in peace, the concept of peace itself has a particular and positive cultural valuation there. The centrality of the idea that peace is, in any conditions, "good" and war is necessarily and in all circumstances" bad" is to some degree peculiar to the Christian worldview. This is not to say that other religions do not value peace or that the Church in history did not succeed in devising intricate theological arguments for a theory of the Just or Good War; in its central precepts, however, the Christian religion does specifically exalt the categories, such as socio-political justice or obedience to a strict moral code. This exaltation - or over - valuation - of peace and blanket denigration of war and the traditional military virtues, to a considerable degree, characteristic of the Christian worldview; but it is not a central part of the ancient Greek, Babylonian, Roman, Jewish or Islamic worldviews. In addition, early Christianity adopted outward doctrines of peace partially to insinuate itself throughout the Roman Empire; Islam, however, although it places peace as an exalted virtue, openly declared a sacred political program, and set out unapologetically from the beginning to back up its proselytism with force. The Prophet himself and all the Rightly Guided Caliphs were proud warriors. In this context, war in itself is not shameful, nor is peace necessarily and always good. With regard to conflict resolution, the Western blanket assumption that working for peace is always, regardless of circumstance and conditions, a good thing might be questionable in other cultural contexts. Conflict without struggle and the end of history The Western world of the post-World War II era has largely abandoned the ideal of struggle which characterized its earlier history. Pre-World War II Western history, on the other hand, is largely marked by intense and often violent struggles to establish national unity, national independence, socioeconomic equality, and/or popular government. The more successful among western nations also prospered by conquering other nations and struggling for world supply and consumer markets. The ideal of struggle was especially exalted in the nineteenth century philosophies of Hegel, Marx, and Nietzsche; it was lent a pseudo-scientific basis by Darwin and bastardized by the national supremacy of German and Italian fascism. Moreover, among the decisive events that shaped modem Western political history-the revolutions of 1776, 1789, 1848 and 1917; the wars of Napoleon; and World Wars I and II was the ideal of struggle that was held in highest regard. As Francis Fukuyama (1992) describes, however, many in the West today enjoy an indeterminate satisfaction that they have somehow reached "the end of history." This may not be completely illusory: in politics the "West" has achieved stability, orderly transitions of power, widespread freedoms, protection of basic rights, and participation in government; in economics it has achieved high levels of wealth and reasonable patterns of wealth distribution; class conflict has been more or less resolved in favor of a large middle class; in other social matters, education and literacy are widespread, health care is adequate, and popular culture through various media offers amusement and enjoyment of leisure time to a majority of the population. The West, in other words, may see nothing major that it still needs to struggle intensely in order to secure. It has reached a situation of relative self satisfaction. From the West's perspective, what is, in a broad sense, is good, and should be preserved. Outside the context of struggle, however, conflict is an overwhelmingly negative phenomenon, notable only for its harmful side effects of violence, suffering, and general discomfiture. If the macro picture is indeed positive, as described above with regard to the West, then conflicts are, in a sense, troublesome brush fires that need to be put out rather than incipient struggles that need to be fanned. Obviously, from the outside - for example, Arab perspective, wherein major and, perhaps, revolutionary change seems, to many, necessary at the level of political, economic, and social affairs, the side - effects of conflict are not nearly as significant as the value of the struggle itself if it succeeds. Indeed, in the major ideological currents that have defined political thinking in the modem Arab world - nationalism, Marxism, and Islamic fundamentalism struggle has been held in high regard. In the thought of Arab nationalism (and indeed various regional nationalisms such as Syrian nationalism and Egyptian nationalism) the struggle - often violent - against external colonial powers and internal collaborationist forces was at the center of the nationalist worldview (see Aflaq 1959 and Saadeh 1959,79). In the Marxist and leftist currents that swept the Arab world, especially during the 1950s and 1960s, an irreducible struggle between the working class on the one hand and the local and international capitalist classes on the other was central. In Islamic fundamentalism of the radical type such as that challenging power in Algeria, Egypt, Jordan, SYfia, Lebanon, and other Arab countries, a central struggle is posited between the minority of true believers and the majority of the population that is Muslim in name only. (A Qur'anic verse which is cited frequently by the main ideologue of modem Islamic fundamentalism, Sayyid Qutb, is "[F]ight them until persecution is no more, and religion is all for God." [Qur'an 2:93, quoted in Qutb 1964, 152.]) In each of these cases, struggle, and the conflict that comes with it, is central to the group's political view and is regarded, in some cases, as a progressive, invigoration, and purifying process. Utilitarianism and the comfort culture of the twentieth century Western conflict resolution relies heavily on the assumption that pain is bad and pleasure, or comfort is good. It is accepted as obvious that the suffering, physical or otherwise, associated with conflict is one of the main inconveniences that conflict resolution practitioners try to eliminate. First, this assumption in itself that suffering is bad and comfort is good required a significant philosophical revolution in the West to become accepted. It was the task of nineteenth century utilitarian philosophers, like Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, to make this principle a fairly widely accepted premise of modem Western culture. It flew - and still flies today among other cultures - against the more original principle that "good is good and bad is bad," where the first usages of good and bad in this phrase are defined in general moral or religious terms having nothing to do with pleasure or pain. The focus of Western conflict resolution theorists on the suffering generated by conflict rather than on the justice or morality of the cause may not strike resonant philosophical cords in other cultures. On the contrary, suffering itself in many cultures, including pre-modem Western culture, enjoys a fairly high valuation as a means for moral or spiritual purification or a necessary divinelyordained component of life. Second, the belief that discomfort is an isolatable evil and one that can be eradicated seems a characteristic of twentieth century postwar Western culture. With advances in health care, economic standards of living, and home appliances, and a vigorous media culture of consumerism and immediate-needs-satisfaction, the modem Western urbanite or suburbanite lives in a world where comfort is achievable and discomfort is limited if not eliminated. In this context, suffering associated with conflict stands out. In order societies, however, where levels of socio-economic development in virtually all spheres are still considerably behind those of the West, comfort itself is the aberration, and discomfort and suffering are more familiar companions of life. In that context, the suffering or discomfort associated with conflict does not stand out; it blends in with a fabric of discomfort and suffering that embraces most aspects of life. The Western conflict resolution emphasis on the necessity of resolving conflict because of the salient discomfort that it brings with it may not be relevant in a social setting in which discomfort is widespread. People there may give less importance to the discomfort generated by the conflict and more importance to the justice or outcome of the dispute. Third, there seems to be a hidden assumption among the Western conflict resolution community that physical suffering - to be precise, physical violence-is in a category of unacceptable suffering all its own. This assumes a valid and clearcut distinction between physical and non-physIcal suffering along the continuum of suffering. The confusion here stems partly, I think, from the pleasure-pain utilitarian philosophy and the acculturation to physical comfort, both described above. Is physical pain indeed more painful than non-physical pain? Is a serious flesh wound worse than a serious injustice? If we gave a person a choice between getting punched in the face or having their home taken away from them, which would they choose? If we gave them a choice between losing their life, or losing their country? Injustice, economic need, political need (struggles for liberty or freedom from oppression) are all, in many cases experienced as acute non-physical suffering. The definition of suffering itself, therefore, needs considerable clarification and specification. It may not mean the same thing from one culture to the next. In the Arab world as well, suffering is not something necessarily to be shunned, nor is physical pain or sacrifice particularly worse than non-physical losses like loss of honor, loss of patrimony, loss of face, etc. Prometheus and Sisyphus The West is riding at the crest of a wave of success at many levels. It is enjoying the later stages of a period of astoundingly rapid advances that began with the Italian Renaissance and expanded with the Industrial Revolution. With a record of Promethean achievement in technological, economic, political, social, and intellectual spheres, and with a modem history of continuous development, the West enjoys a basic optimism that things can be changed and that change can be for the better. World War I, World War II, the German holocaust, and the development of nuclear weapons have dampened but not extinguished this optimism. This Arab and Islamic world, by contrast, is in the trough of a wave of decline and defeat. The heyday of Arab-Islamic culture, politics, economics, and technology began to fade in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries; the history of the past seven centuries has largely been one of stagnation and decline from that apogee. The legacy of this period is partially a pessimism that things cannot easily be changed, that change may often be for the worse, and that the forces that determine change are beyond one's control. For conflict resolution, the optimism of Westerners who approach conflicts with the confidence that they can be managed and resolved, contrasts sharply with the pessimism of others who may regard conflicts as inherently unresolvable or unmanageable, and for whom the whole project of conflict resolution may smack of naive over-optimistic enthusiasm. could be "right," even if their positions are contradictory to one another never mind Aristotle's logical premise on which most Western thought was subsequently built, that a thing must be either "A" or "Not A"; from the Postmodern standpoint it could be "A" here, and "Not A" somewhere else. This is a great boon to modem approaches to conflict resolution, in which it is essential for parties t a conflict to be open to the possibility that while they may be right, so may the other parties. Postmodernism's mood of relativism allows an easy acceptance that the interplay of right and wrong is not necessarily a zero - sum game. In other more traditional cultures, that could best be described as pre-modem or modernizing, rather than postmodern, there are stricter codes of right and wrong and more rigid accounts of truth. From their perspective, the interplay of right and wrong is more likely to be a zero - sum game: "I am either right or wrong; and to the degree that I am right, my opponent must be wrong, and vice versa." This mode of thinking makes several aspects of modem conflict resolution techniques (such as, for example, formulating a problem in a way that satisfies all parties (Moore 1986, 18)) difficult to carry through. "Flower Power" and the new negotiation The credo of individual openness that was part of the cultural revolution of the 1960s and 1970s in the West has found its way into Western conflict resolution techniques. Most Western conflict resolution manuals start with several exercises in which opponents are supposed to "open up," talk about their "personal experiences," "feelings" or "deep interests," and develop "relationships" with their opponents "as individuals." This segue into the negotiation proper may seem natural and comfortable to Westerners, but it may go against the grain of members of many other cultures. "Opening up," rather than maintaining and reinforcing formal roles, may be a highly distressing and counter-productive process that may alienate the participant from the negotiation process and from his negotiation partners and opponents. In many non- Western negotiation situations, it might be wiser to increase the level of formality and social role-playing in order to get the negotiations goin, rather than to increase the level of personalization and individual self-revelation or to engage in game-playing to supposedly bring out the Jungian "inner child." The role of the good citizen The West has already undergone the processes of centralization, bureaucratization, atomization, rule-formation and rule-acceptance that was described by Weber as characteristic of modernization. One of the results of this process is the production of the "good" citizen/subject who generally accepts authority and rules (even if fairly anonymous), pays his taxes, stops at red lights Conflict resolution and the "Scientific" Worldview Western culture has internalized the natural mechanistic universalism of Thales and the atomism of Democritus, both of which provided a large part of the philosophical foundations on which the West's scientific and technological advances were built. Both allow a view of conflict resolution in which conflict is seen as the result of a clash of natural forces among discrete and independent units. The forces can be understood and resolved, and the atoms can be independently identified and dealt with. This is a particular worldview, and is profoundly different from others, such as a truly religious worldview in which conflict is the result of a struggle between divine, devilish or profane forces; a moralistic worldview, in which conflict is the result of a natural struggle between right and wrong; or a superstitious worldview, in which conflict is the result of magic, unknowable forces. A neutral, "objective" approach to conflict assumes a certain neutral and "objective" view of the world. The collapse of the religious and moralistic worldview was a painful process that the West took centuries to pass through; it cannot be assumed that other cultures are at the same stage of advanced a-religiosity and a-morality. The descent into psychology In the nineteenth century, Nietzsche made it no longer possible to easily float religious, moralistic, or even historicist explanations of events. His grand nihilism reduced the world to the individual and his individual will. Furthermore, his attack on the idea that reason and morality are the fundamental guiding lights of the individual led to a revived interest in psychology. Freud's "discovery of the unconscious," followed by Skinner's behaviorism and other explanations of human motivation and action provided the intellectual tools for an entirely human explanation of human attitudes and behavior, downgrading religious, ideological, moralistic, and other explanations. With regard to conflict resolution, this intellectual legacy of the modem West encourages it to perceive conflict as the result of the thoughts and impulses of the individual, the causes of which are largely within that individual. In other cultures that have not yet gone through this process of nihilism and psychologization it may be far more difficult to interpret conflict by reducing it to a set of perceptions, attitudes, and behavior patterns exhibited by autonomous individuals. The convenience of Postmodernism The Postmodern perspective that took hold of Western intellectual life after World War II downgrades systematic philosophies in favor of an attitude of vague relativism. Being right - indeed rights themselves - is a matter of perspective and may differ from culture or from individual to individual. Within their `own contexts, more than one person or culture (even at midnight on a deserted crossroads), etc. In the Western conflict resolution context, this usually means a relatively easy acceptance of the role of the anonymous moderator, facilitator, mediator, or other such central figures in the negotiation process; also it may facilitate an easy acceptance of freshlydevised rules to guide the negotiation process. In other contexts, the attempt of an anonymous (i.e. non-traditional) moderator/facilitator to establish leadership and authority over a negotiation process may cause resentment and may become part of the problem in the form of a struggle for power between the moderator/facilitator and the various participants. The same may be true of new, non-legitimized negotiation rules and guidelines; the imposition of rules may in itself be resented and resisted as an imposition of inappropriate authority. It is in this context that the importance of a traditional authority figure as moderator/facilitator and traditionally accepted rules of conflict resolution become apparent. Militarization, industrialization and the team player The grand factories brought on by industrialization and the mass citizen armies inaugurated by Napoleon eventually brought the majority of the population in the West into large group enterprises. This continued in the twentieth century with the growth of bureaucracies and large corporations that employ the bulk of the new middle class. Through these formative experiences, many Westerners have internalized the benefits of team work and the costs of uncooperativeness or prisoner's-dilemma profiteering. In more fragmented societies organized around the family, the clan, or the small enterprise, the world appears far more competitive and large-scale team work has very few exemplars. Large-scale group work there may often be perceived as a formula for getting duped, and prisoner's-dilemma profiteering is often regarded as rewarding and rarely punished. As a result the seemingly natural appeal to "work together" (e.g. Moore 1986, 19) toward reaching an agreement does not resonate as positively elsewhere as it does in the West. Working together, as opposed to working separately, in other context may cause apprehension as control is cede to a group in whom the individual has little inherent trust. Hobbes and the problem enforcing agreements In the seventeenth century, Hobbes identified the difficulty of negotiating a social contract, or building trust, without a coercive power to enforce it; he argued that for parties to participate in negotiating an agreement without the guarantee that there will be a power to protect and enforce it would be irrational (Ebenstein 1969, 377). He also pointed out how dangerous it would be for parties to participate in such an agreement if the guarantee was not provide; it might even be worse than the state of nature in which you at least had a measure of freedom and equality as protection. In the West, most people have had the guarantee of strong government and the rule of law for a number of centuries now. In the Western conflict resolution literature, the final phases of negotiation, those of "working toward agreement," have a breezy relieved air to them, as if the most difficult and threatening part were over, and the parties would soon have an "agreement" on which they both could rely. In a political environment in which governmental authority is unstable and in which the rule of law is not necessarily paramount, moving toward "agreement," which is, after all, a situation of interdependence not only involving your adversary but also some external guarantor of the agreement, may be in itself disquieting. It implies a giving up of control and autonomy and a limiting of one's freedom of action on the shaky gounds that the adversary can be trusted to fulfill his part of the bargain and that the "system" will help protect his contract. But in the absence of an enforcer, it may be preferable to maintain a conflictual but known and predictable situation, than to try to construct a less conflictual but more interdependent and unpredictable one. Locke and negotiating with have-nots Another point to consider is that in developing societies, people are mostly concerned with getting things they do not presently have rather than protecting what they do have, John Locke’s social contract, on which of Western liberalism is founded, was based on protecting what one has: life, liberty, and private property. It is a negotiation among haves for the protection and preservation of what they have. Western conflict resolution is not too far from this perspective, based as it is on some assumption that all parties to the conflict have something to lose, something to preserve, and something to gain. Negotiating with real have-nots who have nothing to lose nothing to preserve, and everything to gain, might be quite different. Negotiating and bargaining assumes that each party has some number of "chips" that they can trade and shuffle around with other to create a satisfactory resolution to some conflict; but what of the party who has no chips at all, and whose only option in an uneven negotiation situation is to seize the other party's (or parties') "chips"? Indeed, with some veiling sophistication, this is what Marxist revolutionism proposes. Thus, Western conflict resolution through negotiation in a society of haves and have-nots may prove problematic and, at times, impossible. In closing I hope that in the paragraphs above I have raised some worthwhile question about the philosophical, moral, psychological, and cultural framework from within which Western conflict resolution departs. It should be kept in mind that I am not suggesting any judgments on Western or Arab cultures, but merely trying to underline the serious diversity that exist at the deepest levels of different cultural and social formations. Value judgments only make sense from within one culture framework or another. Moreover, I have attempted to present a tentative critique of some hidden premises of Western conflict resolution and to point out a number of areas within Arab political culture in which modem Western assumptions relating to the theory and practice of conflict resolution do not fully apply. I have tried to indicate that some of the bases on which Western conflict resolution rest are not to be found, in exact mirror image, in the Arab world, nor perhaps in other cultures. The conclusion to be drawn from this is not that the Arab world, for example, is more conflict-prone or less conflict resolution-oriented than the West but that in transporting Western conflict resolution theories and techniques to the Arab world or elsewhere, they must undergo considerable cultural adaptation.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz