Chapter 3 3.1 Exercises 1. “February 2, 2009, was a Monday” is a declarative sentence that is true and, therefore, is considered a statement. 2. “The ZIP code for Oscar, LA, is 70762” is a declarative sentence that is true and, therefore, is considered a statement. 3. “Listen my children and you shall hear of the midnight ride of Paul Revere” is not a declarative sentence and does not have the property of being true or false. Hence, it is not considered a statement. 4. “Did you yield to oncoming traffic?” is a question, not a declarative sentence and therefore, it is not a statement. 5. “5 + 9 14 and 4 1 = 12” is a declarative sentence that is false and, therefore, is considered a statement. 6. “5 + 9 12 or 4 2 = 5” is a declarative sentence that is true and, hence is considered a statement. 7. “Some numbers are positive” is a declarative sentence that is true and, therefore, is a statement. 8. “Grover Cleveland was president of the United States in 1885 and 1897” is a declarative sentence that is true and is, therefore, a statement. 9. “Accidents are the main cause of deaths of children under the age of 7” is a declarative sentence that has the property of being true or false and, therefore, is considered to be a statement. 10. “It is projected that in the United States between 2010 and 2020, there will be over 500,000 job openings per year for elementary school teachers, with median annual salaries of about $51,000” is a declarative sentence that has the property of being either true or false and, therefore, is considered to be a statement. 12. “Behave yourself and sit down” is a command, not a declarative sentence and, therefore, is not considered a statement. 13. “Kevin ‘Catfish’ McCarthy once took a prolonged continuous shower for 340 hours, 40 minutes” is a declarative sentence that has the property of being either true or false and, therefore, is considered to be a statement. 14. One gallon of milk weighs more than 3 pounds” is a declarative sentence that has the property of being true and, therefore, is considered to be a statement. 15. “I read the Detroit Free Press, and I read the Sacramento Bee” is a compound statement because it consists of two simple statements combined by the connective “and.” 16. “My brother got married in Copenhagen” is not a compound statement because only one assertion is being made. 17. “Tomorrow is Saturday” is a simple statement because only one assertion is being made. 18. “Jing is younger than 18 years of age, and so is her friend Shu-fen” is a compound statement because it consists of two simple statements combined by the connective “and.” 19. “Jay’s wife loves Ben and Jerry’s ice cream” is not compound because only one assertion is being made. 20. “The sign on the back of the car read ‘Canada or bust!’” is not compound because only one assertion is being made. 21. “If Lorri sells her quota, then Michelle will be happy” is a compound statement because it consists of two simple statements combined by the connective “if...then.” 22. “If Bobby is a politician, then Mitch is a crook” is a compound statement because it consists of two simple statements combined by the connective “if...then.” 11. “Where are you going tomorrow?” is a question, not a declarative sentence and, therefore, is not considered a statement. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.1: STATEMENTS AND QUANTIFIERS 49 23. The negation of “Her aunt’s name is Hermione” is “Her aunt’s name is not Hermione.” 24. A negation of “No rain fell in southern California today” is “Some rain fell in southern California today.” 25. A negation of “Some books are longer than this book” is “No book is longer than this book.” 26. A negation of “All students present will get another chance” is “At least one student present will not get another chance.” 27. A negation of “No computer repairman can play blackjack” is “At least one computer repairman can play blackjack.” 28. A negation of “Some people have all the luck” is “No people have all the luck.” 29. A negation of “Everybody loves somebody sometime” is “Someone does not love somebody sometime.” 39. A translation for “~p” is “She does not have green eyes.” 40. A translation for “~q” is “He is not 60 years old.” 41. A translation for “p q” is “She has green eyes and he is 60 years old.” 42. A translation for “p q” is “She has green eyes or he is 60 years old. 43. A translation for “~p q” is “She does not have green eyes or he is 60 years old.” 44. A translation for “p ~ q” is “She has green eyes and he is not 60 years old.” 45. A translation for “~p ~q” is “She does not have green eyes or he is not 60 years old.” 46. A translation for “~p ~q” is “She does not have green eyes and he is not 60 years old.” 30. A negation of “Everyone needs a friend” is “Someone does not need a friend.” 47. A translation for “~(~p q)” is “It is not the case that she does not have green eyes and he is 60 years old.” 31. A negation of "The trash needs to be collected" is "The trash does not need to be collected." 48. A translation for “~(p ~q)” is “It is not the case that she has green eyes or he is not 60 years old.” 32. A negation of "Every architect who wants a job can find one" is "Not every architect who wants a job can find one." 49. “Tyler collects DVDs and Josh is not an art major” may be symbolized as p ~q. 33. A negation of “x > 12” (without using a slash sign) would be “x 12.” 50. “Tyler does not collect DVDs or Josh is not an art major” may be symbolized as ~p ~q. 34. A negation for “x < 6” (without using a slash sign) would be “x 6.” 51. “Tyler does not collect DVDs or Josh is an art major” may be symbolized as ~p q. 35. A negation for “x 5” would be “x < 5.” 52. “Josh is an art major and Tyler does not collect DVDs” may be symbolized as q ~p. 36. A negation for “x 19” would be “x > 19.” 37. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 38. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Let p represent the statement “She has green eyes,” and let q represent “He is 60 years old.” Translate each symbolic compound statement into words. 53. “Neither Tyler collects DVDs nor Josh is an art major” may be symbolized as ~(p q) or equivalently, ~p ~q. 54. “Either Josh is an art major or Tyler collects DVDs, and it is not the case that both Josh is an art major and Tyler collects DVDs” may be symbolized as (q p) [~(q p)]. 55. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 50 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 56. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Refer to the sketches labeled A, B, and C in the text, and identify the sketch (or sketches) that is (are) satisfied by the given statement involving a quantifier. 57. The condition that “all pictures have frames” is satisfied by group C. 58. The condition that “No picture has a frame” is satisfied by group B. 59. The condition that “At least one picture does not have a frame” is met by groups A and B. 60. The condition that “Not every picture has a frame” is satisfied by groups A and B. Observe that this statement is equivalent to “At least one picture does not have a frame.” 69. Since rational numbers are real numbers, the statement “All rational numbers are real numbers” is true. 70. Since irrational numbers are real numbers, the statement “All irrational numbers are real numbers” is true. 1 is a rational number but not an 2 integer, the statement “Some rational numbers are not integers” is true. 71. Since 72. Since whole numbers are rational, the statement “Some whole numbers are not rational numbers” is false. 73. The number 0 is a whole number but not positive. Thus, the statement “Each whole number is a positive number” is false. 1 is a rational number. Thus, 2 the statement “Each rational number is a positive number” is false. 61. The condition that “At least one picture has a frame” is satisfied by groups A and C. 74. The number 62. The condition that “No picture does not have a frame” is satisfied by group C. Observe that this statement is equivalent to “All pictures have a frame.” 75. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 63. The condition that “all pictures do not have frames” is satisfied by group B. Observe that this statement is equivalent to “No pictures have a frame.” 64. The condition that “Not every picture does not have a frame” is satisfied by groups A and C. Observe that this statement is equivalent to “At least one picture does have a frame.” 65. Since all whole numbers are integers, the statement “Every whole number is an integer” is true. 66. Since not every integer is a whole number, the statement “Every integer is a whole number” is false. 67. Since all natural numbers are integers, the statement “There exists a natural number that is not an integer” is false. 68. Since 3 is an integer but not a natural number, the statement “There exists an integer that is not a natural number” is true. 76. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 77. We might write the statement “There is no one here who has not made mistakes before” using the word “every” as “Every person here has made mistakes before.” 78. A. The statement “For some real number x, x 0” is true. Let x = 10, for example. This real number satisfies the statement. B. The statement “For all real numbers x, x3 0 ” is false. For example, let x = 2. Observe that ( 2)3 8 ò 0. C. The statement “For all real numbers x less than 0, x 2 is also less than 0” is false. Let x = 4, which is less than 0, but x 2 ( 4) 2 16, which is not less than 0. D. The statement “For some real number x, x 2 0 ” is false. If you square any real number (negative, positive, or 0), the result will be 0. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.2: TRUTH TABLES AND EQUIVALENT STATEMENTS 51 79. The statement “Some cats have fleas” is symbolized c f , and its negation “No cat has fleas” could be stated “Every cat does not have fleas.” This negation is expressed symbolically as c ~ f . 80. In part (b) of Example 5, the statement “Some cats do not have fleas can be expressed symbolically as c ~ f . The negation is c f . In part (c) of Example 5, the statement “No cats have fleas” can be expressed symbolically as c ~ f , and its negation is expressed as c f . 3.2 Exercises 1. If q is false, then (p ~q) q must be false, since both conjuncts (parts of the conjunction) must be true for the compound statement to be true. 2. If q is true, then q (q ~p) is true, since only one disjunct (parts of the disjunctive statement) need be true for the compound statement to be true. 3. If p q is true, and p is true, then q must also be true in order for the conjunctive statement to be true. Observe that both conjuncts must be true for a conjunctive statement to be true. 4. If p q is false, and p is false, then q must also be false. Observe that both disjuncts must be false for a disjunctive statement to be false. 5. In order for p q ~ q to be true, either p must be true, or q ~ q must be true. But q ~ q cannot be true, so p must be true. 6. The statement p ~ q r is a conjunction. In order for a conjunction to be true, both component statements must be true. Therefore, p must be true, and q r must be false. But a disjunction is false only if both components are false, so both q and r are false. In conclusion, p must be true, and q and r must both be false. 7. If ~ p q is true, both components (disjuncts) must be false. Thus, the disjunction itself is false making its negation true. 8. If ~ p q is false, then both p and q must be true. This will assure that the conjunction itself is true making its negation false. In exercises 920, p represents a false statement and q represents a true statement. 9. Since p = F, ~p = ~F = T. That is, replace p by F and determine the truth of ~F. 10. Since q = T, ~q = ~T = F. Thus, ~q is false. 11. Since p is false and q is true, we may consider the “or” statement as F T T, by logical definition of an “or” statement. That is p q is true. 12. Since p is false and q is true, we may consider the “and” statement as F T F, by the logical definition of an “and” statement. That is, p q is false. 13. With the given truth values for p and q, we may consider p ~q as F ~T F F F, by the logical definition of “ .” 14. With the given truth values for p and q, we may consider ~p q as ~F T T T T, by the logical definition of “ .” Thus, the compound statement is true. 15. With the given truth values for p and q, we may consider ~p ~q as ~F ~T T F T. Thus, the compound statement is true. 16. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have F ~T F F F. Thus, the compound statement p ~q is false. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 52 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 17. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have ~(F ~T) ~(F F) ~F T. Thus, the compound statement ~(p ~q) is true. 24. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have (F ~F) T (F T) T T T T. Thus, the compound statement (q ~r) p is true. 18. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have ~(~F ~T) ~(T F) ~(T) F. Thus, the compound statement ~(~p ~q) is false. 25. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have T (F F) T F F. Thus, the compound statement p (q r) is false. 19. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have ~[~F (~T F)] ~[T (F F)] ~[T F] ~F T. Thus, the compound statement ~[~p (~q p)] is true. 26. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have (~T F) ~F (F F) T F T T. Thus, the compound statement (~p q) ~r is true. 20. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have ~[(~F ~T) ~T] ~[(T F) F] ~[F F] ~F T. Thus, the compound statement ~[(~p ~q) ~q] is true. 21. The statement 6 2 is a disjunction since it means “6 > 2” or “6 = 2.” 22. The statement “8 3” is true because 8 > 3 and only one disjunct need be true. The statement “5 5” is true because 5 = 5 and only one disjunct need be true. In exercises 2332, p represents a true statement, and q and r represent false statements. 23. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have (T F) ~F F T T. Thus, the compound statement (p r) ~q is true. 27. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have ~(T F) (F ~F) ~F (F T) T T T. Thus, the compound statement ~(p q) (r ~q) is true. 28. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have (~F ~F) (~F F) (T T) (T F) T F T. Thus, the compound statement (~r ~q) (~r q) is true. 29. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have ~[(~T F) F] ~[(F F) F] ~[F F] ~F T. Thus, the compound statement ~[(~p q) r] is true. 30. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have ~[F (~F ~T)] Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.2: TRUTH TABLES AND EQUIVALENT STATEMENTS 53 ~[F (T F)] ~[F F] ~F T. Thus, the compound statement ~[r (~q ~p)] is true. 31. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have ~[~F (F ~T)] ~[T F] ~T F. Thus, the compound statement ~[~q (r ~p)] is false. 32. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have ~ (T F) ~ (T F) ~T ~F FT F. Thus, the compound statement ~ (p q) ~ (p q) is false. Let p represent the statement “16 < 8,” which is false, let q represent “5 4,” which is false and let r represent “17 17,” which is true. [E.g. p = F, q = F and r = T.] 33. Replacing p and r with the given truth values, we have F T F. The compound statement p r is false. 34. Replacing p and q with the observed truth values, we have F ~F F T T. The compound statement p ~q is true. 35. Replacing q and r with the observed truth values, we have ~F ~T T F T. The compound statement ~q ~r is true. 36. Replacing p and r with the observed truth values, we have ~F ~T T F F. The compound statement ~p ~r is false. (F F) T F T T. The compound statement (p q) r is true. 38. Replacing p, q and r with the observed truth values, we have ~F (~T ~F) T (F T) T T T. The compound statement ~p (~r ~q) is true. 39. Replacing p, q and r with the observed truth values, we have (~T F) ~F (F F) T F T T. The compound statement (~r q) ~p is true. 40. Replacing p, q and r with the observed truth values, we have ~(F ~F) ~T ~(F T) F ~T F F F F. The compound statement ~(p ~q) ~r is false. 41. Since there are two simple statements (p and r), we have 22 4 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. 42. Since there are three simple statements (p, r, and s), we have 23 8 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. 43. Since there are four simple statements (p, q, r, and s), we have 24 16 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. 44. Since there are five simple statements (p, q, r, s, and t), we have 25 32 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. 37. Replacing p, q and r with the observed truth values, we have Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 54 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 45. Since there are seven simple statements (p, 52. p ~q 7 q, r, s, t, u, and v), we have 2 128 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. 46. Since there are eight simple statements (p, q, r, s, m, n, u, and v), we have 47. If the truth table for a certain compound statement has 64 rows, then there must be six distinct component statements (26 64). 48. It is not possible for a truth table of a compound statement to have exactly 54 rows, because 54 is not a natural-number power of 2. 49. ~p q p q ~p p ~q T F T F T T F T F F F F T T q T T 8 2 256 combinations of truth values, or rows in the truth table, to examine. ~q p 53. (q ~p) ~q p q ~p ~q (q ~p) (q ~p) ~q T T F F T T T F F T F T F T T F T T F F T T T T 54. (p ~q) p p ~q ~q (p ~q) p p q ~p q T T F F F F T T T T T F F T T F F F F T F F F F T T T F F T F F F F T F 55. (p ~q) (p q) 50. ~p ~q p q (p ~q) (p q) p q ~p ~q ~p ~q T T T T F T T T T T T F F F T F T T T F T F F T F F T T F T F F F F F F T F T T F T F F F T T F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 F F T T T 56. (~p ~q) (~p q) 51. ~(p q) p q p q ~(p q) p q (~p T T T F T T F F F ~q) (~p q) F F T F T T F T F F F F T F F T T F T F T F T T F F T T T T F F F T F F T T T T T T F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.2: TRUTH TABLES AND EQUIVALENT STATEMENTS 55 57. (~p q) r 59. (~p ~q) (~r ~p) q) r p q r F T F T T T T F F T F F T T F F F F F T T F T F F F F F F T F F T T T T T T F T T F T T T F F F F F T T F F F T F F F T F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 p q r T T T F T T F F T F T F T F F F T F (~p 58. r (p ~q) ~q) ~p) F F F F F F F F T T T F F T F F F F F F T T T T F T T F F T F T T T F T F F T T T T F F T T F F F T T T T F T T T T T T T T 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 (~p (~r 60. (~r ~p) (~p ~q) p q r r (p ~q) p q r (~r ~p) (~p ~q) T T T T T T F F T T T F F F F F F F T T F F F T F F T T F T T F F F F F T F T T T T T T T F T F F F F F T T T F F F T T T T T F F T T F T F T T F T T T T F F F F T T F T T T T T F F T F F F F F F F T F T T T T T T F F F T T T F F T F F T F T T T T T T F F F F F F F T F F F T T T T T T T 1 3 1 2 1 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 56 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 61. ~(~p ~q) (~r ~s) ~q) (~r F F T F F F F F T F T T F F T T T F F F F T T T T T F F T T F F F T F F T T F T T F T T T T F F T T T T T F F T F F F T F F T F T T T T F F T T T F T T F F T T T T T F F F F T T F T T T T T T F T T T T T T 2 1 4 2 3 2 ~ p q r s (~p T T T T T F T T T F T F T T F T T F T T F F T T F T T T F T F T F F T T F T F F F T F F T T T T T F T T F T F T F T F T F F F F T T F T T F F T F F T T F F F T F T T F F F F F T 3 1 ~s) 62. (~r s) (~p q) p q r s (~r s) (~p q) T T T T F T T F F F T T T T F F F F F F F T T T F T T T T F F F T T T F F T T F F F F T T F T T F T T F F F F T F T F F F F F F F F T F F T T T T F F F F T F F F T T F F F F F F T T T F T T T T T T F T T F F F F F T T T F T F T T T T T T T T F T F F T T F T T T T F F T T F T T F T F F F F T F F F F F T F F F F F T T T T F T F F F F F F T T F F T F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.2: TRUTH TABLES AND EQUIVALENT STATEMENTS 57 63. “You can pay me now or you can pay me later” has the symbolic form (p q). The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by one of De Morgan’s laws, to (~p ~q). The corresponding word statement is “You can’t pay me now and you can’t pay me later.” 64. “I am not going or she is going” has the symbolic form ~p q. Its negation, ~(~p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to p ~q. The word translation for the negation is “I am going and she is not going.” 65. “It is summer and there is no snow” has the symbolic form p ~q. The negation, ~(p ~q), is equivalent by De Morgan’s to ~p q. The word translation for the negation is “It is not summer or there is snow.” 1 is a positive number and 9 is less than 2 zero” is of the form p q. The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s to ~p ~q. The word translation for the 1 negation is “ is not a positive number or 2 9 zero.” (Note that the inequality “” is equivalent to “not less than.”) 66. “ 67. “I said yes but she said no” is of the form p q. The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p ~q. The word translation for the negation is “I did not say yes or she did not say no.” (Note: The connective “but” is equivalent to that of “and.”) 68. “Dan tried to sell the software, but he was unable to do so” is of the form p q. The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p ~q. The word translation for the negation is Dan did not try to sell the software, or he was able to do so.” 69. “6 1 = 5 and 9 + 13 7” is of the form p ~q. The negation, ~(p ~q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p q. The translation for the negation is “6 1 5 or 9 + 13 = 7.” negation is “8 10 and 5 = 2.” (Note that the inequality “” is equivalent to “ ”). 71. “Prancer or Vixen will lead Santa’s sleigh next Christmas” is of the form p q. The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p ~q. A translation for the negation is “Neither Prancer nor Vixen will lead Santa’s sleigh next Christmas.” 72. “The lawyer and the client appeared in court” is of the form p q. The negation, ~(p q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p ~q. The word translation for the negation is “The lawyer did not appear in court or the client did not appear in court.” 73. “For every real number x, x < 14 or x > 6” is true since for any real number at least one of the component statements is true. 74. “For every real number x, x > 9 or x < 9” is false since for the real number x = 9, both component statements are false. 75. “There exists an integer n such that n > 0 and n < 0” is false since any integer that makes one of the component statements true will make the other false. 76. “For some integer n, n 3 and n 3” is true since both component statements are true for the integer n = 3. 77. p q p q p q T T F T F T F T T F F F Observe that it is only the first line in the truth table that changes for “exclusive disjunction” since the component statements cannot both be true at the same time. 78. The phrase “and/or” represents inclusive disjunction since both or either component statement(s) may be true. 70. “8 < 10 or 5 2” is of the form p ~q. The negation, ~(p ~q), is equivalent, by De Morgan’s, to ~p q, A translation for the Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 58 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 79. “3 + 1 = 4 2 + 5 = 7” is false since both component statements are true. equivalent, and it can be said that “OR distributes over AND.” 80. “3 + 1 = 4 2 + 5 = 10” is true since the first component statement is true and the second is false. (b) p q r p (q r) T T T T T T T T 81. “3 + 1 = 6 2 + 5 = 7” is true since the first component statement is false and the second is true. T T F T T T T F T F T T T F T T T F F T F F F F 82. “3 + 1 = 12 2 + 5 = 9” is false since both component statements are false. F T T F F T T T F T F F F T T F 83. The lady is behind Door 2. Reasoning: Suppose that the sign on Door 1 is true. Then the sign on Door 2 would also be true, but this is impossible. So the sign on door 2 must be true, and the sign on door 1 must be false. Because the sign on Door 1 says the lady is in Room 1 and this is false, the lady must be behind Door 2. F F T F F F T T F F F F F F F F 1 3 1 2 1 84. (a) p (q r) T T T T T T F T T T F F F T T T F F T T F F T T F F F F T T F T T T T F T F F F T F F F F T F F F F T F F F F F F F F 1 3 1 2 1 p q r T T T T T p q r (p q) (p r) T T T T T T T T T T T T F T T T T T F F T F T T F F T T T T T F F T F F F T F F F T T F F T F F F T F T F F F T F F F F F F T F F F F F F T F F F F F F F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Since the final column (step 3) of the truth tables are identical, the statements are equivalent, and it can be said that “AND distributes over OR.” (c) Writing exercise; answers will vary. p q r (p q) (p r) T T T T T T T T T T T T F T T T T T T F T F T T T F T T T T T F F T T F T T T F F T T F T T T F T T F T F F T T F F F F F F T F F F F F T T F F F F F F F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Since the final column (step 3) of the truth tables are identical, the statements are 85. The statement ~ p q ~ p ~ q can be expressed verbally as “The negation of a conjunction is equivalent to the disjunction of the negations. 3.3 Exercises 1. The statement “You can do it if you just believe” becomes “If you just believe, then you can do it.” 2. The statement “It must be bad for you if it’s sweet” becomes “If it’s sweet, then it must be bad for you.” Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.3: THE CONDITIONAL AND CIRCUITS 59 3. The statement “Every even integer divisible by 5 is divisible by 10” becomes “If it is an even integer divisible by 5, then it is divisible by 10.” 4. The statement “No perfect square integers have units digit 2, 3, 7, or 8” becomes “If an integer has units digit 2, 3, 7, or 8, then it’s not a perfect square.” 5. The statement “No grizzly bears live in California” becomes “If it is a grizzly bear, then it doesn’t live in California.” 6. The statement “No guinea pigs get lonely” becomes “If it is a guinea pig, then it doesn’t get lonely.” 7. The statement “Surfers can’t stay away from the beach” becomes “If they are surfers, then they can’t stay away from the beach.” 8. The statement “Running Bear loves Little White Dove” becomes “If he is Running Bear, then he loves Little White Dove.” 9. The statement “If the antecedent of a conditional statement is false, the conditional statement is true” is true, since a false antecedent will always yield a true conditional statement. logically equivalent. To decide if the above is true, examine the corresponding truth tables for each individual statement. p q p q ~p q T T T T T F T T T F T F F F F F F T F T T T T T F F F T F T T F 1 2 1 1 2 1 This statement is true because the truth values (columns 2) for each compound statement are the same, showing that the statements are equivalent. 15. “Given that ~p is true and q is false, the conditional p q is true” is a true statement since the antecedent, p, must be false. 16. “Given that ~p is false and q is false, the conditional p q is true” is a false statement since the antecedent, p, is true and the consequent, q is false. 17. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 18. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 10. The statement “If the consequent of a conditional statement is true, the conditional statement is true” is true, since a true consequent is always associated with a true conditional statement (i.e., it doesn’t matter what the truth value of the antecedent is if the consequent itself is true). 19. “T (7 < 3)” is a false statement, since the antecedent is true and the consequent is false. 11. The statement “If q is true, then p q r q is true” is true, since 21. “F (5 5)” is a true statement, since a false antecedent always yields a true conditional statement. with a true consequent the conditional statement is always true (even though the antecedent may be false). 12. The statement “If p is true, the ~p (q r) is true” is true since the antecedent, ~p, is false. 13. The negation of “If pigs fly, I’ll believe it” is “If pigs don’t fly, I won’t believe it.” This statement is false. The negation is “Pigs fly and I won’t believe it.” 20. “F (4 8)” is a true statement, since a false antecedent always yields a conditional statement which is true. 22. “(8 8) F” is a false statement, since the antecedent is true and the consequent is false. 23. “ (52 25) (8 8 16) ” is a true statement, since a false antecedent always yields a true conditional statement. 24. “(5 = 12 7) (9 > 0)” is true, since the antecedent and the consequent are both true. 14. The statements “If it flies, then it’s a bird” and “It does not fly or it’s a bird” are Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 60 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC Let s represent the statement “She sings for a living,” let p represent the statement “he fixes cars,” and let m represent “they collect classics.” 25. “~m p” expressed in words, becomes “If they do not collect classics, then he fixes cars.” 26. “p ~m” expressed in words, becomes “If he fixes cars, then they do not collect classics.” 27. “s (m p)” expressed in words, becomes “If she sings for a living, then they collect classics and he fixes cars.” 28. “(s p) m” expressed in words, becomes “If she sings for a living and he fixes cars, then they collect classics.” 29. “~p (~m s)” expressed in words, becomes “If he does not fix cars, then they do not collect classics or she sings for a living.” 30. “(~s ~m) ~p” expressed in words, becomes “If she does not sing for a living or they do not collect classics, then he does not fix cars.” Let b represent the statement “I take my ball,” let s represent the statement “it is sunny” and let p represent “the park is open.” 31. The statement “If I take my ball, then the park is open,” can be symbolized as “b p.” 32. The statement “If I do not take my ball, then it is not sunny” can be symbolized as “~b ~s.” 33. The statement “The park is open, and if it is sunny then I do not take my ball” can be symbolized as “p (s ~b).” 34. The statement “I take my ball, or if the park is open, then it is sunny” can be symbolized as “b (p s).” 35. The statement “It is sunny if the park is open” can be symbolized as “p s.” 36. The statement “I’ll take my ball if it is not sunny” can be symbolized as “~s b.” Assume that p and r are false, and q is true. 37. Replacing r and q with the given truth values, we have ~F T TT T. Thus, the compound statement ~r q is true. 38. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have TF F. Thus, the compound statement q p is false. 39. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have FT T. Thus, the compound statement p q is true. 40. Replacing r and p with the given truth values, we have ~F F TF F. Thus, the compound statement ~r p is false. 41. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have ~F (T F) TF F. Thus, the compound statement ~p (q r) is false. 42. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have (~F F) F (T F) F TF F. Thus, the compound statement (~r p) p is false. 43. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have ~T (F F) FF T. Thus, the compound statement ~q (p r) is true. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.3: THE CONDITIONAL AND CIRCUITS 61 51. (~p q) p 44. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have (~F ~T) (F ~F) (T F) (F T) FF T. Thus, the compound statement (~p ~q) (p ~r) is true. 45. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have (F ~T) (~F ~F) (F F) (T T) TT T. Thus, the compound statement (p ~q) (~p ~r) is true. p q (~p q) p T T F T T T T T F F T F T T F T T T T F F F F T F F T F 1 2 1 3 2 52. (p q) (p q) 46. Replacing p, r and q with the given truth values, we have [(F ~T) (F F)] F [(F F) T] F T T F T F F Thus, the compound statement (p ~q) (p r) r is false. (p q) (p q) T T T T T T T T F T F F T T T F F T F F T T F T T F F F F F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 p q T T Since this statement is always true (column 3), it s a tautology. 53. (p q) (q p) p q (p q) (q p) T T T T T T T T T 47. Writing exercise; answers will vary. T F T T F T F T T 48. Answers will vary. One example is p [(~q r) p]. Observe that any “If..., then...” statement with antecedent p, q or r will work, since all that is needed to make the statement true is a false antecedent. F T F T T T T T F F F F F F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 49. ~q p p q ~q p T T F T T T F T T T F T F T F F F T F F 1 2 1 50. (~q ~p) ~q (~q T F T F F F F T F F T T F T F T T F F F F T T T T T 1 2 1 3 2 p q T T ~p) Since this statement is always true (column 3), it is a tautology. 54. (~p ~q) (p q) ~q) (p q) T F T T T T T T F T F F F F T F F T T T T F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 (~p p q T T F T F F F T T F F ~q Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 62 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 55. [(r p) ~q] p p q r [(r p) ~q] p T T T T T T F F T T T T F F T T F F T T T F T T T T T T T T T F F F T T T T T T F T T T T F F F T F F T F F F F F F T F F F T T T F T T F F F F F F F F F T T F 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 56. [(r p) (p q)] p p q r [(r p) (p q)] p T T T T T T T T T T T T F F F T F T T T T F T T T T F F T T T F F F F T F F T T F T T T F F F F T F F T F F F F F F T F F F T T F F F F T F F F F F F F F F T F 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since this statement is always true (column 4), it is a tautology. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.3: THE CONDITIONAL AND CIRCUITS 63 57. (~r s) (p ~q) p q r s (~r s) (p ~q) T T T T F T T T T F F T T T F F T F T T F F T T F T T T T T T F F T T F F T F F F T F F T F T T F T T T T T T T F T F F T F T T T T T F F T T T T T T T T T F F F T F F T T T T F T T T F T T T F T F F T T F F T F T F T F F T F T T T T T F T F F T F F T F F T F T F F F T T F T T T F T T F F T F F T F T F T T F F F T T T T T F T T F F F F T F F T F T T 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 58. (~p ~q) (s r) p q r s (~p ~q) (s r) T T T T F F F T T T T T T T F F F F T F T T T T F T F F F T T F F T T F F F F F T F T F T F T T F F T T T T T T F T F F F T T F T T T F F T F F T T T F F T F F F F F T T F T F F T T T T F F T T T T F T T F T F F T F T T F T F T T F F T T F F F T F F T F F T F T F F F T T T T T T T T T F F T F T T T T F T T F F F T T T T F T F F F F F F T T T T F T F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 64 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 59. The statement is not a tautology if only one F appears in the final column of a truth table, since a tautology requires all T’s in the final column. 60. Consider the negation of the statement. 61. The negation of “If that is an authentic Coach bag, I’ll be surprised” is “That is an authentic Coach bag and I am not surprised.” 62. The negation of “If Muley Jones hits that note, he will shatter glass” is “Muley Jones hits that note and he will not shatter glass.” Florida.” An equivalent statement would be “The person is not a resident of Pensacola or is a resident of Florida.” 72. An equivalent conditional statement to “All women were once girls” is “If you are a woman, then you were once a girl.” An equivalent statement would be “The person is not a woman or was once a girl.” 73. The statements p q and ~p q are equivalent if they have the same truth tables. 63. The negation of “If the bullfighter doesn’t get going, he’s going to get gored” is “The bullfighter doesn’t get going and he doesn’t get gored.” 64. The negation of “If you don’t say ‘I do,’ then you’ll regret it for the rest of your life” is “Don’t say ‘I do’ and you will not regret it for the rest of your life.” 65. The negation of “If you want to be happy for the rest of your life, never make a pretty woman your wife” is “You want to be happy for the rest of your life and you make a pretty woman your wife.” 74. 67. An equivalent statement to “If you give your plants tender, loving care, they will flourish” is “You do not give your plants tender, loving care or they flourish.” 69. An equivalent statement to “If she doesn’t, he will” is “She does or he will.” 70. An equivalent statement to “If I say ‘black’, she says ‘white’” is “I do not say ‘black’ or she says ‘white.’” 71. An equivalent conditional statement to “All residents of Pensacola are residents of Florida” is “If you are a resident of Pensacola, then you are a resident of q T F T T F F F F T T T T T F T F T T F 1 2 1 1 2 1 q T T T F T F F T F F F q T T Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. 66. The negation of “If I had a hammer, I’d hammer in the morning” is “I had a hammer, and I wouldn’t hammer in the morning.” 68. An equivalent statement to “If you scratch my back, I’ll scratch yours” is “You do not scratch my back or I will scratch yours.” ~p p p p q ~ (p q) p ~q T T F T T T T F F T F T T F F T T T F T F F T T F F F F F F F T F F F T 3 1 2 1 1 2 1 Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. 75. p q p q ~q ~p T T T T T F T F T F T F F T F F F T F T T F T T F F F T F T T T 1 2 1 1 2 1 Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.3: THE CONDITIONAL AND CIRCUITS 65 76. p q q p T T T T T T T F T F F F T T F T F T T T F F F F F T F F T F 1 2 1 1 2 1 p q T T Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are not the same, the statements are not equivalent. 77. p q p ~q ~p ~q T T T F F F F F T F T T T F T T F T F T F T T F F F F T T T T T 1 2 1 1 2 1 Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. 78. p q ~p q ~p q T T F F T F T T T F F F F F T F F T T T T T T T F F T F F T F F 1 2 1 1 2 1 Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are not the same, the statements are not equivalent. 79. p q q ~p p ~q T T T F F T F F T F F T F T T T F T T T T F T F F F F T T F T T 1 3 2 1 3 2 Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 66 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC q) r T T T T T T T T T T F T T T F T T T F T T F T F F F T T T F F F T T T T F F F T F F F 3 1 2 1 ~( 80. p q r T T T F T T F F T F T F T F F F T T F T F F F F F p q) r T T T T T T T F T F T T T T F T F T F T T T T T F F T T T F T T F F F T T F F F F F F F 4 1 1 2 1 3 1 (p Since the truth values in the final columns for each statement are the same, the statements are equivalent. 81. In the diagram, two series circuits are shown, which correspond to p q and p ~q. These circuits, in turn, form a parallel circuit. Thus, the logical statement is (p q) (p ~q). One pair of equivalent statements listed in the text includes (p q) (p ~q) p (q ~q). Since (q ~q) is always true, p (q ~q) simplifies to p T p. 82. In the diagram, a parallel circuit is shown, which corresponds to r q. This circuit, in turn, is in series with p. Thus, the logical statement is p (r q). 83. In the diagram, a series circuit is shown, which corresponds to ~q r. This circuit, in turn, forms a parallel circuit with p. Thus, the logical statement is p (~q r). 84. The diagram shows p in series with a parallel circuit consisting of two smaller parallel circuits involving q and ~p, and ~p and ~q, respectively. Thus, the logical statement is p ~ p q ~ p ~ q . This is equivalent to p ~ p q ~ p ~ q , which is equivalent to p T , which equivalent to p. 85. In the diagram, a parallel circuit corresponds to p q. This circuit is parallel to ~p. Thus, the total circuit corresponds to the logical statement ~p (p q). This statement in turn, is equivalent to (~p p) (~p q). Since ~p p is always true, we have T (~p q) T. 86. The diagram shows two parallel circuits, ~p q and ~p ~q which are parallel to each other. Thus, the total circuit can be represented as (~p q) (~p ~q). This circuit can be simplified using the following equivalences: (~p q) (~p ~q) ~p q ~p ~q ~p q ~q ~p (q ~q) ~p T T. 87. The logical statement, p (q ~p), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, p (q ~p), simplifies to p q as follows: Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.3: THE CONDITIONAL AND CIRCUITS 67 p (q ~p) (p q) (p ~p) (p q) F p q. 88. The logical statement, (~p ~q) ~r, can be represented by the following circuit. 89. The logical statement, (p q) (~p ~q), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, (p q ) (~p ~q), simplifies to F as follows: (p q) (~p ~q) [p (~p ~q)] [q (~p ~q)] [p ~p ~q] [q ~q ~p] [F ~q] [F ~p] F F F. 90. The logical statement, (~q ~p) (~p q), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, (~q ~p) (~p q), simplifies to ~p q as follows: (~q ~p) (~p q) [~q (~p q)] [~p (~p q)] [~q ~p q] [~p ~p q] [(~q q) ~p] [(~p ~p) q] (T ~p) (~p q) T (~p q) ~p q. 91. The logical statement, [(p q) r] ~p, can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, [(p q) r] ~p, simplifies to (r ~p) q as follows: [(p q) r] ~p [(p r) (q r)] ~p [(p r) ~p] [(q r) ~p] [p r ~p] [(q r) ~p] [(p ~p) r] [(r ~p) q] (F r) [(r ~p) q] F [(r ~p) q] (r ~p) q or q (r ~p). 92. The logical statement, [(~p ~r) ~q] (~p r), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, [(~p ~r) ~q] (~p r), can simplify to (~p r) ~q in the following manner. Both [(~p ~r) ~q] and (~p r) must be true. But if (~p r) is true, then (~p ~r) is false. If (~p ~r) is false, then ~q must be true for the original disjunction to be true. Thus, [(~p ~r) ~q] (~p r) (F ~q) (~p r) ~q (~p r) (~p r) ~q or ~q (~p r). 93. The logical statement, ~q (~p q), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement, ~q (~p q), simplifies to p q as follows: ~q (~p q) ~q (p q) q (p q) q p q p q q p (q q) p q. 94. The logical statement, ~p (~p ~q), can be represented by the following circuit. The statement ~p (~p ~q), simplifies to T as follows: ~p (~p ~q) p (~p ~q) p ~p ~q (p ~p) ~q T ~q T. 95. Referring to Figures 5 and 6 of Example 6 in the text: Cost per year of the circuit in Figure 5 = number of switches $.06 24 hr 365 days = (4) (.06) 24 365 = $2102.40. Cost per year of the circuit in Figure 6 = number of switches $.06 24 hr 365 days = (3) (.06) 24 365 = $1576.80. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 68 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC Thus, the savings is $2102.40 $1576.80 = $525.60. 96. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 97. The logic circuit shown is equivalent to the statement ~(A A) B, which is in turn equivalent to ~A B, which is equivalent to A B. 3.4 Exercises For each given conditional statement (symbolically as p q), write (a) the converse (q p), (b) the inverse (~p ~q), and (c) the contrapositive (~q ~p) in if...then forms. Wording may vary in the answers to Exercises 110. 1. The conditional statement: If beauty were a minute, then you would be an hour. (a) Converse: If you were an hour, then beauty would be a minute. 4. The conditional statement: If I had a nickel for each time that happened, I would be rich. (a) Converse: If I were rich, then I would have a nickel for each time that happened. (b) Inverse: If I did not have a nickel for each time that happened, then I would not be rich. (c) Contrapositive: If I were not rich, then I would not have a nickel for each time that happened. It is helpful to restate the conditional statement in an “if...then” form for the exercises 58 and 10. 5. The conditional statement: If you walk in front of a moving car, then it is dangerous to your health. (a) Converse: If it is dangerous to your health, then you walk in front of a moving car. (b) Inverse: If beauty were not a minute, then you would not be an hour. (b) Inverse: If you do not walk in front of a moving car, then it is not dangerous to your health. (c) Contrapositive: If you were not an hour, then beauty would not be a minute. (c) Contrapositive: If it is not dangerous to your health, then you do not walk in front of a moving car. 2. The conditional statement: If you lead, then I will follow. (a) Converse: If I follow, then you lead. (b) Inverse: If you do not lead, then I will not follow. (c) Contrapositive: If I do not follow, then you do not lead. 3. The conditional statement: If it ain’t broke, don’t fix it. (a) Converse: If you don’t fix it, then it ain’t broke. (b) Inverse: If it’s broke, then fix it. (c) Contrapositive: If you fix it, then it’s broke. 6. The conditional statement: If it’s milk, then it contains calcium. (a) Converse: If it contains calcium, then it’s milk. (b) Inverse: If it’s not milk, then it does not contain calcium. (c) Contrapositive: If it does not contain calcium, then it’s not milk. 7. The conditional statement: If they are birds of a feather, then they flock together. (a) Converse: If they flock together, then they are birds of a feather. (b) Inverse: If they are not birds of a feather, then they do not flock together. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.4: THE CONDITIONAL AND RELATED STATEMENTS 69 (c) Contrapositive: If they do not flock together, then they are not birds of a feather. 8. The conditional statement: If it is a rolling stone, then it gathers no moss. (a) Converse: If it gathers no moss, then it is a rolling stone. (b) Inverse: If it is not a rolling stone, then it gathers moss. (c) Contrapositive: If it gathers moss, then it is not a rolling stone. 9. The conditional statement: If you build it, then he will come. (a) Converse: If he comes, then you built it. (b) Inverse: If you don’t build it, then he won’t come. (c) Contrapositive: If he doesn’t come, then you didn’t build it. 10. The conditional statement: If there’s smoke, then there’s fire. (a) Converse: If there’s fire, then there’s smoke. (b) Inverse: If there’s no smoke, then there’s no fire. (c) Contrapositive: If there’s no fire, then there’s no smoke. 11. The conditional statement: p ~q. (b) Inverse: p q. (c) Contrapositive: q p. 14. The conditional statement: ~q ~p. (a) Converse: ~p ~q. (b) Inverse: q p. (c) Contrapositive: p q. 15. The conditional statement: p (q r). (a) Converse: (q r) p. (b) Inverse: ~p ~(q r) or ~p (~q ~r). (c) Contrapositive: (~q ~r) ~p. 16. The conditional statement: (r ~q) p. (a) Converse: p (r ~q). (b) Inverse: ~(r ~q) ~p or (~r q) ~p. (c) Contrapositive: ~p ~(r ~q) or ~p (~r q). 17. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 18. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Writing the statements, Exercises 1940, in the form “if p, then q” we arrive at the following results. 19. The statement “If the Kings go to the playoffs, pigs will fly” becomes “If the Kings go to the playoffs, then pigs will fly.” (a) Converse: ~q p (b) Inverse: ~p q. (c) Contrapositive: q ~p. 12. The conditional statement: ~p q. (a) Converse: q ~p. 20. The statement “If I score 90% or higher on my test, I’ll go to a movie” becomes “If I score 90% or higher on my test, then I’ll go to a movie”. 21. The statement “Legs of 3 and 4 imply a hypotenuse of 5” becomes “If it has legs of 3 and 4, then it has a hypotenuse of 5.” (b) Inverse: p ~q. (c) Contrapositive: ~q p. 13. The conditional statement: ~p ~q. 22. The statement “’This is a leap year’ implies that next year is not” becomes “If this is a leap year, then next year is not.” (a) Converse: ~q ~p. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 70 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 23. The statement “All whole numbers are rational numbers” becomes “If a number is a whole number, then it is a rational number.” 24. The statement “No irrational numbers are rational” becomes “If a number is a rational number, then it is not an irrational number.” 25. The statement “Doing logic puzzles is sufficient for driving me crazy” becomes “If I do logic puzzles, then I am driven crazy.” 26. The statement “Being in Kalamazoo is sufficient for being in Michigan” becomes “If you are in Kalamazoo, then you are in Michigan.” 27. The statement “Two coats of paint are necessary to cover the graffiti” becomes “If the graffiti are to be covered, then two coats of paint must be used.” 28. The statement “Being an environmentalist is necessary for being elected” becomes “If one is elected, then one is an environmentalist.” 29. The statement “Employment will improve only if the economy recovers” becomes “If employment improves, then the economy recovers.” 30. The statement “The economy will recover only if employment improves” becomes “IF the economy recovers, then employment improves.” 35. The statement “A rectangle is a parallelogram with perpendicular adjacent sides” becomes “If the figure is a rectangle, then it is a parallelogram with perpendicular adjacent sides.” 36. The statement “A square is a rectangle with two adjacent sides equal” becomes “If the figure is a square, then it is a rectangle with two adjacent sides equal.” 37. The statement “A triangle with two perpendicular sides is a right triangle” becomes “If a triangle has two perpendicular sides, then it is a right triangle.” 38. The statement “A parallelogram is a foursided figure with opposite sides parallel” becomes “If the figure is a parallelogram, then it is a four-sided figure with opposite sides parallel.” 39. The statement “The square of a three-digit number whose units digit is 5 will end in 25” becomes “If a three-digit number whose units digit is 5 is squared, then the square will end in 25.” 40. The statement “An integer whose units digit is 0 or 5 is divisible by 5” becomes “If an integer has a units digit of 0 or 5, then it is divisible by 5.” 41. Option D is the answer since “r is necessary for s” represents the converse, s r, of all of the other statements. 31. The statement “No whole numbers are not integers” becomes “If a number is a whole number, then it is an integer.” 42. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 32. The statement “No integers are irrational numbers” becomes “If a number is an integer, then it is rational.” 44. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 33. The statement “The Phillies will win the pennant when their pitching improves” becomes “If their pitching improves, then the Phillies will win the pennant.” 43. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 45. The statement “6 = 9 3 if and only if 8 + 2 = 10” is true, since this is a biconditional composed of two true statements. 34. The statement “The grass will be greener when we’re on the other side” becomes “If we’re on the other side, then the grass will be greener.” Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.4: THE CONDITIONAL AND RELATED STATEMENTS 71 46. The statement “3 + 1 7 if and only if 8 8” is false since this is a biconditional consisting of a true and a false statement. 47. The statement “8 + 7 15 if and only if 3 5 8” is false, since this is a biconditional consisting of a false and a true statement. 48. The statement “6 2 = 18 if and only if 9 + 7 16” is true, since this is a biconditional consisting of two false statements. 49. The statement “George H.W. Bush was president if and only if George W. Bush was not president” is false, since this is a biconditional consisting of a true and a false statement. 50. McDonald’s sells Whoppers if and only if Apple manufactures iPods” is false, since this is a biconditional consisting of a false and a true statement. 51. The statements “Michael Jackson is alive” and “Michael Jackson is dead” are contrary, since both cannot be true at the same time. 52. The statements “That book is nonfiction” and “That book costs more than $150” are consistent, since both statements can be true. 53. The statements “This number is a whole number” and “This same number is irrational” are contrary, since both cannot be true at the same time. 54. The statements “This number is positive” and “This same number is a natural number” are consistent, since both statements can be true. 55. The statements “This number is an integer” and “This same number is a rational number” are consistent, since both statements can be true. 56. The logic circuit shown is expressed symbolically as ~ ~ A ~ A B ~ B ~ A B A ~ A B B ~ A B by DeMorgan's laws We then build the truth table for this statement. B)) (B ~ (A B) ) T ~ (A F T T T T T T F T T T T F T T F F F F F T T F F F F F T T F T T F F T T F T T F F F T F T T F F F 4 3 1 2 1 5 1 4 3 1 2 1 A B (A T T T T F T F T F F 1 The final column (step 5) shows truth values that match those for the biconditional (true when A and B have the same truth value, false when A and B have different truth values). The truth tables for the biconditional p q and the statement ~ p q are shown side-by-side on the next page. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 72 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC p q p q ~ (p q) T T T T T T T F T T F T F F F T T F F T F F T F F T T F F F T F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 From their truth tables, we see that p q and ~ p q are equivalent. 57. Let p represent “the troll is Truthful Troll” and let q represent “the door to the east leads to freedom.” Then (1) the statement “if the troll is Truthful Troll, then the conditional statement he uttered is true” is symbolized by p p q , and (2) the statement “if the conditional statement he uttered is true, then he is Truthful Troll” is symbolized p q p . 58. The biconditional formed from the statements in Exercise 58 is p p q . (a) The truth table for this statement is shown below. p (p q) T T T T T T F T F T F F F T F F F T T F F F F F T F 1 3 1 2 1 p q T T (b) Since this biconditional must be true, the first row of the truth table corresponds to the situation. Thus, p and q are both true. That is, the troll is Truthful Troll, and the eastern door leads to freedom. 3.5 Exercises 1. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “amusement parks” must be inside the region representing “locations that have thrill rides” so that the first premise is true. Locations that have thrill rides Amusement parks x x represents Universal Orlando Let x represent the amusement park Universal Orlando. By the second premise, x must lie in the “amusement parks” region. Since this forces the conclusion to be true, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.5: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH EULER DIAGRAMS 73 2. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “disc jockeys” must be inside the region representing “those who play music” so that the first premise is true. Those who play music Disc jockeys x x represents Calvin Let x represent Calvin. By premise 2, x must lie in the “disc jockeys” region. Since this forces the conclusion to be true, the argument is valid. 3. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “celebrities” must be inside the region representing “those who have problems” so that the first premise is true. Those who have problems x Celebrities x x represents that man Let x represent “that man.” By the second premise, x must lie in the “those who have problems” region. Thus, he could be inside or outside the inner region. Since this allows for a false conclusion (he doesn’t have to be in the “celebrities” region for both premises to be true), the argument is invalid. 4. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “Southerners” lies inside the region representing “those who speak with an accent.” Let x represent Nick. By the second premise, Nick must lie inside the region of those who speak with an accent and hence may lie inside the inner or the outer region. But, for the conclusion to be true, he must lie only inside the inner region. Thus, the argument is invalid. Those who speak with an accent x Southerners x x represents Nick 5. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “dogs” must be inside the region representing “creatures that love to bury bones” so that the first premise is true. Creatures that love to bury bones Dogs x x represents Puddles Let x represent “Puddles.” By the second premise, x must lie outside the region representing “creatures that love to bury bones.” Since this forces the conclusion to be true, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 74 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 6. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “vice-presidents” must be inside the region representing “those who use cell phones” so that the first premise is true. Let x represent “Bob.” By the second premise, x must lie outside the region representing “those who use cell phones.” Since this forces the conclusion to be true, the argument is valid. 7. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “residents of Colorado” must be inside the region representing “those who know how to breathe thin air” so that the first premise is true. Let x represent “Julie.” By the second premise, x must lie in the “those who know how to breathe thin air” region. Thus, she could be inside or outside the inner region. Since this allows for a false conclusion (she doesn’t have to be in the “residents of Colorado” region for both premises to be true), the argument is invalid. 8. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “people who drive” must be inside the region representing “people who have a photo I.D.” so that the first premise is true. Let x represent “Kay.” By the second premise, x must lie in the “people who have a photo I.D.” region. Thus, she could be inside or outside the inner region. Since this allows for a false conclusion (she doesn’t have to be in the “people who drive” region for both premises to be true), the argument is invalid. 9. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “dinosaurs” intersects the region representing “plant-eaters.” This keeps the first premise true. Let x represent “Danny.” By the second premise, x must lie in the region representing “plant-eaters.” Thus, he could be inside or outside the region “dinosaurs.” Since this allows for a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.5: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH EULER DIAGRAMS 75 10. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “philosophers” intersects the region representing “those who are absent minded.” This keeps the first premise true. Let x represent “Nicole.” By the second premise, x must lie in the region representing “philosophers.” Thus, she could be inside or outside the region representing “people who are absent minded.” Since this allows for a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. 11. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “nurses” intersects the region representing “those who belong to a union.” This keeps the first premise true. Let x represent “Heather.” By the second premise, x must lie in the region representing “nurses.” Thus, she could be inside or outside the region “those who belong to a union.” Since this allows for a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. 12. The following represents one way to diagram the premises so that they are true; however, the argument is invalid since, according to the diagram, no trucks have both sound systems and gun racks making the conclusion false. 13. Interchanging the second premise and the conclusion of Example 3 (in the text) yields the following argument. All magnolia trees have green leaves. That plant is a magnolia tree. That plant has green leaves. Draw an Euler diagram where the region representing “Magnolia trees” must be inside the region representing “Things that have green leaves” so that the first premise is true. Let x represent “That plant.” By the second premise, x must lie inside the region representing “Magnolia trees.” Since this forces the conclusion to be true, the argument is valid, which makes the answer to the question yes. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 76 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 14. The valid argument of Example 4 (in the text) is, All expensive things are desirable. All desirable things make you feel good. All things that make you feel good make you live longer. All expensive things make you live longer. Another possible conclusion, which will keep the argument valid is “All expensive things make you feel good.” The argument remains valid since the premises diagrammed (Figure 13, in the text) force this conclusion to be true also. 15. The following is a valid argument which can be constructed from the given Euler diagram. All people with blue eyes have blond hair. Erin does not have blond hair. Erin does not have blue eyes. 16. The following is a valid argument which can be constructed from the given Euler diagram. RNs can perform all procedures that LVNs can perform. LVNs can give vaccinations. RNs can give vaccinations. 17. The following represents one way to diagram the premises so that they are true; however, the argument is invalid since, according to the diagram, all birds are planes, which is false even though the stated conclusion is true. 18. The following Euler diagram represents true premises. Since the diagram forces the conclusion to be true also, the argument is valid. 19. The following Euler diagram yields true premises. It also forces the conclusion to be true. Thus, the argument is valid. Observe that the diagram is the only way to show true premises. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.5: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH EULER DIAGRAMS 77 20. The following Euler diagram represents true premises. The argument is invalid even though the conclusion is true since the diagram implies that no chickens are birdsa false statement. 21. The following Euler diagram represents true premises. But x can reside inside or outside of the “Cities that are northeast of Deming” diagram. In the one case (x inside) the conclusion is true. In the other case (x outside) the conclusion is false. Since true premises must always give a true conclusion, the argument is invalid. 22. The following Euler diagram yields true premises. It also forces the conclusion to be true. Thus, the argument is valid. Observe that the diagram is the only way to show true premises. 23. The following Euler diagram represents the two premises as being true and we are forced into a true conclusion. Thus, the argument is valid. 24. The following Euler diagram represents true premises. No information, however, is given regarding the relationship between the largest angle and the longest side. The argument is invalid even though the conclusion is true. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 78 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC The premises marked A, B, and C are followed by several possible conclusions (Exercises 2530). Take each conclusion in turn, and check whether the resulting argument is valid or invalid. A. All people who drive contribute to air pollution. B. All people who contribute to air pollution make life a little worse. C. Some people who live in a suburb make life a little worse. Diagram the three premises to be true. 25. We are not forced into the conclusion, “Some people who live in a suburb contribute to air pollution” since option (A) represents true premises and a false conclusion. Thus, the argument is invalid. 26. We are not forced into the conclusion, “Some people who live in a suburb drive” since diagrams (A) and (B) represent true premises where this conclusion is false. Thus, the argument is invalid. 27. We are not forced into the conclusion, “Suburban residents never drive” since diagram (C) represents true premises where this conclusion is false. Thus, the argument is invalid. 28. We are not forced into the conclusion, “Some people who contribute to air pollution live in a suburb” since option (A) represents true premises and a false conclusion. Thus, the argument is invalid. 29. The conclusion, “Some people who make life a little worse live in a suburb” yields a valid argument since all three options (AC) represent true premises and force this conclusion to be true. 30. The conclusion, “All people who drive make life a little worse” yields a valid argument since all three options (AC) represent true premises and force this conclusion to be true. 3.6 Exercises 1. Let p represent “Rascal Flatts comes to town,” q represent “I will go to the concert,” and r represent “I’ll call in sick for work.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq qr p r. This is the valid argument form “reasoning by transitivity.” 2. Let p represent “you use binoculars,” q represent “you get a glimpse of the bald eagle,” and r represent “you will be amazed.” The argument is the represented symbolically by: pq qr p r. This is the valid argument form “reasoning by transitivity.” 3. Let p represent “Marina works hard enough” and q represent “she will get a promotion.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq p q. This is the valid argument form “modus ponens.” 4. Let p represent “Isaiah’s ankle heals on time” and q represent “he will play this season.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq p q. This is the valid argument form “modus ponens.” 5. Let p represent “he doesn’t have to get up at 3:00 A.M.” and q represent “he is ecstatic.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq q p. Since this is the form “fallacy of the converse,” it is invalid and considered a fallacy. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 79 6. Let p represent “you are a mathematician” and q represent “you turn coffee into theorems.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq q p. Since this is the form “fallacy of the converse,” it is invalid and considered a fallacy. 7. Let p represent “Clayton pitches” and q represent “the Dodgers win.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq ~q ~p. This is the valid argument form “modus tollens.” 11. Let p represent “she uses e-commerce” and q represent “she pays by credit card.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: p q (or q p) ~q p. Since this is the form “disjunctive syllogism,” it is a valid argument. 12. Let p represent “Mia kicks” and q represent “Drew passes.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: p q (or q p) ~p p. Since this is the form “disjunctive syllogism,” it is a valid argument. 8. Let p represent “Josh plays” and q represent “the opponent gets shut out.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq ~q ~p. This is the valid argument form “modus tollens.” 9. Let p represent “you’re going through hell” and q represent “keep going.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq ~p ~q. Since this is the form “fallacy of the inverse,” it is invalid and considered a fallacy. 10. Let p represent “you can’t get rid of the skeleton in your closet” and q represent “you’d best teach it to dance.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq ~p ~q. Since this is the form “fallacy of the inverse,” it is invalid and considered a fallacy. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 80 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC To show validity for the arguments in the following exercises, we must show that the conjunction of the premises implies the conclusion. That is, the conditional statement P1 P2 ... Pn C must be a tautology. For exercises 13 and 14 we will use the standard (long format) to develop the corresponding truth tables. For the remainder of the exercises we will use the alternate (short format) to create the truth tables. 13. Form the conditional statement [(p q) p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q p q (p q) p ~q [(p q) p] ~q T T T T F F T F T T T T F T T F F T F F F F T T Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 14. Form the conditional statement [(p ~q) p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q ~q p ~q (p ~q) p [(p ~q) p] ~q T T F F F T T F T T T T F T F F F T F F T F F T Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 15. Form the conditional statement [(~p ~q) q] p from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q [(~p ~q) q] p T T F T F T T T T T F F T T F F T T F T T F F F T T F F F T T T F F T F 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 81 16. Form the conditional statement [(p ~q) p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q [(p ~q) p] ~q T T T T F T T F F T F T T T T T T T F T F F F F F T F F F F T T F F T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 17. Form the conditional statement [(p q) (q p)] (p q) from the argument. Complete a truth table. (q p)] (p q) T T T T F T T F T F F T F T T T F F 1 3 2 4 3 p q [(p q) T T T T F F F T F F Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 18. Form the conditional statement [(~p q) p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q [(~p q) p] ~q T T F T T T T F F T F F T F T T T T F T T T T F F T F F F T F F F F T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. Note: If you are completing the truth table along rows (rather than down columns), you could stop after completing the first row, knowing that with a false conditional, the statement will not be a tautology. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 82 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 19. Form the conditional statement [(p ~q) q] ~p from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q [(p ~q) q] ~p T T T F F F T T F T F T T T F F T F F T F T F T T T T F F F T T F F T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 20. Form the conditional statement [(p ~q) ~p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. ~q) ~p] F F F F T F T T F F T T T F T T F F F T T T T T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 p q [(p T T T T F T F T F F F ~q Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 21. Form the conditional statement ([(p q) (q p)] p) (p q) from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q ([(p q) (q p)] p) (p q) T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T F T F F F F T T F T T T T F F T F T T F T F F F F T F T T F F F T F T F T F F F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 4 3 5 3 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 83 22. Form the conditional statement ([(p q) (p q)] q) p from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q ([(p q) (p q)] q) p T T T T T T T T T T T T T T F T F F T T T F F F T T F T F F T T F T T T T F F F F F F F F F F F F F T F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 4 1 5 1 Since the conditional formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 23. Form the conditional statement [(~p q) (~p q) p] ~q from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q [(~p q) (~p q)] p] ~q T T F T T T F T T T T F F T F F F F F F T F F T T T F T T T T T T T T F F T F F F T T F F T F F F F T T 1 2 1 3 4 3 5 4 2 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. 24. Form the conditional statement ([(r p) (r q)] (q p)) (r p) from the argument. p q r ([(r p) (r q)] (q p)) (r p) T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T T F F F T T F T T T T T T T F T T T F T T T T T T T T F F F T T T T T T F F F F T T F T T F F F T T F T T F T T T F F T T T F F T F F T T T F F T F F F F T F F F F T F F T F F F F F T T F F T T T F F F F F T T T F F F F F F F T F F F F F F F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 4 2 3 2 5 3 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 84 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 25. Form the conditional statement ([(~p r) (p q)] (~r p)) (q r) from the argument. p q r ([(~p r) (p q)] (~r p)) (q r) T T T F F T T T T F T T T T T T F F F F T T T T T T F F T F T F F T T T T F T T T T T F F F F F T T T T T T T T F T T T T T T T T F T F T T F T F T F F T T F T F F T F F F T T T T F F F F T F T T F F F T F F T F F T F F T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 2 3 2 5 4 The F in the final column 5 shows us that the statement is not a tautology and hence, the argument is invalid. 26. Form the conditional statement ([(p ~q) (q ~r)] (p ~r)) (r p) from the argument. Complete a truth table. p q r ([(p ~q) (q ~r)] (p ~r)) (r p) T T T T F F F T F F F T T F T T T T T T F T F F T T T T T T T T T F T T T F T T T T T F T F T T T F T T T T T F F T T T T F T T T T T T T F T T F T T F T F T T F F F F F F T T F F F T F F T F T T T T T F T T T F T F F F T F T T T F T F F F F F T T F F F F F F T T T F T T T F T T T F T F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 6 4 5 4 9 7 8 7 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 27. Every time something squeaks, I use WD-40. Every time I use WD-40, I must go to the hardware store. Every time something squeaks, I go to the hardware store. 28. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 85 29. Let p represent “Joey loves to watch movies,” q represent “Terry likes to jog,” and r represent “Carrie drives a school bus.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: p q ~p ~q r r. Construct the truth table for [p (q ~p) (~q r)] r. p q r [p (q ~p) (~q r)] r T T T T F T F F F F T T T T T T F T F T F F F F T F T F T F T T T F T F T T T T T T T F F T T F T F F T F F T F F T T F F T T T F F T T T T F T F F F T T T F F T F T F F F T F F F T T F T T T T T F F F F F F T T F T F F T F 2 3 1 2 1 4 2 3 2 5 4 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 30. Let p represent “Hurricane Gustave hit that grove of trees,” q represent “trees are devastated,” and r represent “people plant trees when disasters strike.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq r ~ q r ~p. Construct the truth table for [(p q) (r ~q)] (r ~p). (r T F T T F F F F T F F F T T F F T T F F F T F T T F T F F F 1 2 1 3 1 [(p p q r T T T T T T T F T T T F T T F T F F T F T T F F T F F F T F F F q) ~q)] (r F F T T F F F F T F T F T T T T F F F F T T F T F T F F T T T T F F T F T T T T T T T T F T T F T T 2 1 4 2 3 2 ~p) Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 86 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 31. Let p represent “Yoda is my favorite Star Wars character,” q represent “I hate Darth Vader,” and r represent “I hate Luke Skywalker.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq r q ~r ~p. Construct the truth table for [(p q) (r q) (~r)] ~p. (Note: we do not have to complete a column under each simple statement p, q, and r, as we did in exercises above, since it is easy to compare the appropriate index columns to create the truth value for each connective.) p q r [(p q) (r q) (~r)] ~p T T T T T T F F T F T T F T T T T T F F T F T F F T F F T F T F F F F F F T T F F T T T T T F F T T F T F T T T T T T T F F T T T T F F T T F F F T F F F T T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. Note: If you are completing the truth table along rows (rather than down columns), you could stop after completing the second row, knowing that with a false conditional, the statement will not be a tautology. 32. Let p represent “Carrie Underwood sings,” q represent “Joe Jonas is a teen idol,” and r represent “Jennifer Hudson wins a Grammy.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: p ~q ~q ~r r ~p. Construct the truth table for [(p ~q) (~q ~r) r] ~p. p q r [(p ~q) (~q ~r) r] ~p T T T T T F T F T F T T F F T T F T T F T F T T F F T F T F T T T T F T F F F T T F T F F T T T T T T T F F T F F T T F F F F F T F F T T T F T F F F F F F T T F F T T F F T F T T F T F F F T T T F F F F T T T T T T F F T T 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 4 3 5 4 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. Note: If you are completing the truth table along rows (rather than down columns), you could stop after completing the first row, knowing that with a false conditional, the statement will not be a tautology. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 87 33. Let p represent “The Cowboys will make the playoffs,” q represent “Troy comes back to play,” and r represent “Jerry coaches the Cowboys.” The argument is then represented symbolically by pq ~r q r ~p. Construct the truth table for [(p q) (r q) (~r)] ~p. p q r [(p q) (~r q) r] ~p T T T T T T T T F F T T F T T T F F T F T F T F F F F T T F T F F F F T F F T F F T T F F T F T T T F T F F F T F F T T F F T T T F T T T T F F F T T T F F T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 3 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. (Note: If you are completing the truth table along rows, rather than down columns, you could stop after completing the first row, knowing that with a false conditional, the statement will not be a tautology. 34. Let p represent “I’ve got you under my skin,” q represent “you are deep in the heart of me,” and r represent “you are really a part of me.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq q ~r qr p r. Construct the truth table for [(p q) (q ~r) (q r)] (p r). p [(p q) (q (q r)] (p r) F T T T T T F F F T T T T F F T F F F F T T T T T T T T T T F T T T T T T F F T T 1 4 3 5 4 ~r) q r T T T T F T F F T T F T T T T T T F T F F F T F T F F F F F T F T T T F T F T F T T T F F T T T F F F F T T F 2 3 1 2 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. (Note: If you are completing the truth table along rows, rather than down columns, you could stop after completing the second row, knowing that with a false conditional, the statement will not be a tautology.) Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 88 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 35. Let p represent “Dr. Hardy is a department chairman,” q represent “he lives in Atlanta,” and r represent “his first name is Larry.” The argument is then represented symbolically by pq qr ~r ~p. Construct the truth table for [(p q) (q r)] (~r ~p). p q r [(p q) (q r)] (~r ~p) T T T T T T T F T F T T F T F F T T F F T F T F F F T F T F T F F F F F T T F F F T T T T T T F T T F T F T F F T T T T F F T T F F T F T T F F F T F F T T T T 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 36. Let p represent “I am your women,” q represent “you are my man,” and r represent “I stop loving you.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: (p q) ~r r ~p ~q. Construct the truth table for {[(p q) ~r] r} (~p ~q). p q r ([(p q) ~r} r) (~p ~q) T T T T F F F T T F F F T T F T T T F F T F F F T F T F T F T T T F T T T F F F T T F F T F T T F T T F T F T T T T T F F T F F T T F F T T T F F F T F T F T T T T T T F F F F T T F F T T T T 1 2 1 3 2 4 2 3 2 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 89 The following exercises involve Quantified arguments and can be analyzed, as such, by Euler diagrams. However, the quantified statements can be represented as conditional statements as well. This allows us to use a truth tableor recognize a valid argument formto analyze the validity of the argument. 42. The statement “none of your sons can do logic” becomes “if he is your son, then he can’t do logic.” 37. Let p represent “you are a man,” q represent “you are created equal,” and r represent “you are a woman.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq qr p r. This is a “reasoning by Transitivity” argument form and, hence, is valid. 44. The statement “no teetotalers are pawnbrokers” becomes “if the person is a teetotaler, then the person is not a pawnbroker.” 38. Let p represent “you are a man,” q represent “you are mortal,” and r represent “you are Socrates.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq rp r q. By interchanging the first premise with the second premise the argument becomes a “reasoning by transitivity” form and, hence, is valid. 39. (a) We apply reasoning by repeated transitivity to the seven premises. A conclusion from this reasoning, which makes the argument valid, is reached by linking the first antecedent to the last consequent. This conclusion is “When the cable company keeps you on hold, your dad gets punched over a can of soup.” (b) If the premise “Your dad does not get punched over a can of soup” is added, then we can apply reasoning by transitivity to the contrapositives of the original premises to draw the conclusion that “The cable company does not keep you on hold.” 40. Writing exercise; answers will vary. Answers in Exercises 4148 may be replaced by their contrapositives. 41. The statement “all my poultry are ducks” becomes “if it is my poultry, then it is a duck.” 43. The statement “guinea pigs are hopelessly ignorant of music” becomes “if it is a guinea pig, then it is hopelessly ignorant of music.” 45. The statement “no teachable kitten has green eyes” becomes “if it is a teachable kitten, then it does not have green eyes.” 46. The statement “opium-eaters have no selfcommand” becomes “if it is an opium-eater, then it has no self-command.” 47. The statement “I have not filed any of them that I can read” becomes “if I can read it, then I have not filed it.” 48. The statement “all of them written on blue paper are filed” becomes “if it is written on blue paper, then it is filed.” 49. (a) “No ducks are willing to waltz” becomes “if it is a duck, then it is not willing to waltz” or p ~s. (b) “No officers ever decline to waltz” becomes “if one is an officer, then one is willing to waltz” or r s. (c) “All my poultry are ducks” becomes “if it is my poultry, then it is a duck” or q p. (d) The three symbolic premises are p ~s rs q p. Begin with q, which only appears once. Replacing r s with its contrapositive, ~s ~r, rearrange the three premises. qp p ~s ~s ~r By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion which provides a valid argument is q ~r. In words, “if it is my poultry, then it is not an officer,” or “none of my poultry are officers.” Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 90 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 50. (a) “Everyone who is sane can do logic” becomes “if one is sane, then one is able to do logic” or r p. (b) “No lunatics are fit to serve on a jury” becomes “if one is a lunatic (or not same), then one is not fit to serve on a jury” or ~r ~q. (c) “None of your sons can do logic” becomes “if he is your son, then he cannot do logic” or s ~p. (d) The three symbolic premises are rp ~r ~q s ~p. Replacing r p with its contrapositive, ~p ~r, rearrange the three premises. s ~p ~p ~r ~r ~q By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion which provides a valid argument is s ~q. In words, “if he is your son, then he is not fit to serve on a jury,” or “your sons are not fit to serve on a jury.” 51. (a) “Promise-breakers are untrustworthy” becomes “if one is a promise-breaker, then one is not trustworthy” or r ~s. (b) “Wine-drinkers are very communicative” becomes “if one is a wine-drinker, then one is very communicative” or u t. (c) “A person who keeps a promise is honest” becomes “if one is not a promise-breaker, then one is honest” or ~r p. (d) “No teetotalers are pawnbrokers” becomes “if one is not a wine-drinker, then one is not a pawnbroker” or ~u ~q. (e) “One can always trust a very communicative person” becomes “if one is very communicative, then one is trustworthy” or t s. (f) The symbolic premise statements are r ~s ut ~r p ~u ~q t s. Begin with q, which only appears once. Using the contrapositive of ~u ~q, (q u), and r ~s, (s ~r), rearrange the five premises as follows: qu ut ts s ~r ~r p. By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion which provides a valid argument is q p. In words, this conclusion can be stated as “if one is a pawnbroker, then one is honest,” or “all pawnbrokers are honest.” 52. Let p be “it is a guinea pig,” q be “it is hopelessly ignorant of music,” r be “it keeps silent while the Moonlight Sonata is being played,” and s be “it appreciates Beethoven.” (a) “Nobody who really appreciates Beethoven fails to keep silent while the Moonlight Sonata is being played” becomes “if one appreciates Beethoven, then one keeps silent while the Moonlight Sonata is being played” or s r. (b) “Guinea pigs are hopelessly ignorant of music” becomes “if you are a guinea pig, then you are hopelessly ignorant of music” or p q. (c) “No one who is hopelessly ignorant of music ever keeps silent while the Moonlight Sonata is being played,” becomes “if one is hopelessly ignorant of music, then one fails to keep silent while the Moonlight Sonata is being played” or q ~r. (d) In symbols, the statements are (a) s r (b) p q (c) q ~r. Using the contrapositive of the premise s r, (~r ~s), rearrange the premises as follows: Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 3.6: ANALYZING ARGUMENTS WITH TRUTH TABLES 91 pq q ~r ~r ~s. By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion which provides a valid argument is p ~s. In words, this conclusion can be stated as “if you are a guinea pig, then you do not appreciate Beethoven,” or equivalently, “guinea pigs don’t appreciate Beethoven.” 53. Begin by changing each quantified premise to a conditional statement. (a) The statement “all the dated letters in this room are written on blue paper” becomes “if it is dated, then it is on blue paper” or r w. (b) The statement “none of them are in black ink, except those that are written in the third person” becomes “if it is not in the third person, then it is not in black ink” or ~u ~t. (c) The statement “I have not filed any of them that I can read” becomes “if I can read it, then it is not filed” or v ~s. (d) The statement “none of them that are written on one sheet are undated” becomes “if it is on one sheet, then it is dated” or x r. (e) The statement “all of them that are not crossed are in black ink” becomes “if it is not crossed, then it is in black ink” or ~q t. (f) The statement “all of them written by Brown begin with ‘Dear Sir’” becomes “if it is written by Brown, then it begins with ‘Dear Sir’” or y p. (g) The statement “all of them written on blue paper are filed” becomes “if it is on blue paper, then it is filed” or w s. (h) The statement “none of them written on more than one sheet are crossed” becomes “if it is not on more than one sheet, then it is not crossed” or ~x ~q. (i) The statement “none of them that begin with ‘Dear Sir’ are written in the third person” becomes “if it begins with ‘Dear Sir,’ then it is not written in the third person” or p ~u. (j) The symbolic premise statements are (a) r w (b) ~u ~t (c) v ~s (d) x r (e) ~q t (f) y p (g) w s (h) ~x ~q (i) p ~u. Begin with y, which appears only once. Using contrapositives of v ~s (s ~v), ~q t (~t q), and ~x ~q (q x), rearrange the nine statements. yp p ~u ~u ~t ~t q qx xr rw ws s ~v. By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion that makes the argument valid is y ~v. In words, the conclusion can be stated as “if it is written by Brown, then I can’t read it,” or equivalently “I can’t read any of Brown’s letters.” 54. (a) “No one who is going to a party ever fails to brush his hair” becomes “if one is going to a party, then he brushes his hair” or p q. (b) “No one looks fascinating if he is untidy” becomes “if one is untidy, then he does not look fascinating” or ~u ~s. (c) “Opium-eaters have no self-command” becomes “if one is an opium-eater; then he has no self command” or t ~r. (d) “Everyone who has brushed his hair looks fascinating” becomes “if one has brushed his hair, then he looks fascinating” or q s. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 92 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC (e) “No one wears white kid gloves unless he is going to a party” becomes “if he wears white kid gloves, then he is going to the party” or v p. (f) “A man is always untidy if he has no self-command” becomes “if a man has no self-command, then a man is not tidy” or ~r ~u. (g) The symbolic premise statements are (a) p q (b) ~u ~s (c) t ~r (d) q s (e) v p (f) ~r ~u Begin with t, which only occurs once. Using the contrapositives of q s, (~s ~q), p q, (~q ~p), and v p, (~p ~v), rearrange the five premises as follows: t ~r ~r ~u ~u ~s ~s ~q ~q ~p ~p ~v. By repeated use of reasoning by transitivity, the conclusion which provides a valid argument is t ~v. In words, this conclusion can be stated as “if he is an opium-eater then he doesn’t wear white kid gloves” or equivalently, “opium-eaters do not wear white kid gloves.” Chapter 3 Test 1. The negation of “6 3 = 3” is “6 3 3.” 2. The negation of “all men are created equal” is “some men are not created equal.” 3. The negation of “some members of the class went on the field trip” is “no members of the class went on the field trip.” An equivalent answer would be “all members of the class did not go on the field trip.” 4. The negation of “If I fall in love, it will be forever” is “I fall in love and it will not be forever.” Remember that ~(p q) (p ~q). 5. The negation of “she applied and did not get a student loan” is “she did not apply or she got a student loan.” Remember that ~(p q) (~p ~q). Let p represent “you will love me” and let q represent “I will love you.” 6. The symbolic form of “If you won’t love me, then I will love you” is “~p q.” 7. The symbolic form of “I will love you if you will love me.” is “p q.” 8. The symbolic form of “I won’t love you if and only if you won’t love me” is “~q ~p.” 9. Writing the symbolic form “~p q” in words, we get “you won’t love me and I will love you.” 10. Writing the symbolic form “~(p ~q)” in words, we get “it is not the case that you will love me or I won’t love you” (or equivalently, by De Morgan’s, “you won’t love me and I will love you”). Assume that p is true and that q and r are false for Exercises 1114. 11. Replacing q and r with the given truth values, we have ~F ~F T T T. The compound statement ~q ~r is true. 12. Replacing p, q and r with the given truth values, we have F (T ~F) F (T T) F T T. The compound statement r (p ~q) is true. 13. Replacing r with the given truth value (s not known), we have F (s F) F not known T. The compound statement r (s r) is true. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. CHAPTER 3 TEST 93 The wording may vary in the answer in Exercises 2124. 14. Replacing p and q with the given truth values, we have T (T F) T (F) F. The compound statement p (p q) is false. 21. “All integers are rational numbers” can be stated as “if the number is an integer, then it is a rational number.” 22. “Being a rhombus is sufficient for a polygon to be a quadrilateral” can be stated as “if a polygon is a rhombus, then it is a quadrilateral.” 15. Writing exercise; answers will vary. 16. The necessary condition for 23. “Being divisible by 2 is necessary for a number to be divisible by 4” can be stated as “if a number is divisible by 4, then it is divisible by 2.” Remember that the “necessary” part of the statement becomes the consequent. (a) a conditional statement to be false is that the antecedent must be true and the consequent must be false. (b) a conjunction to be true is that both component statements true. 24. “She digs dinosaur bones only if she is a paleontologist” can be stated as “if she digs dinosaur bones, then she is a paleontologist.” Remember that the “only if” part of the statement becomes the consequent. (c) a disjunction to be false is that both component statements must be false. (d) a biconditional to be true is that both component statements have the same truth value. 17. 18. p (~p q) T T T F T T F T F F F F F T F F T T T F F F F T T F 2 3 1 2 1 p q T T 25. The conditional statement: If a picture paints a thousand words, then the graph will help me understand it. (a) Converse: If the graph will help me understand it, then a picture paints a thousand words. p q ~ (p q) (~p ~q) T T F T T F F F T F T F T F T T F T T F T T T F F F T F T T T T 2 1 3 1 2 1 Since the last completed column (3) is all true, the conditional is a tautology. 19. The statement “some negative integers are whole numbers” is false, since all whole numbers are non-negative. (b) Inverse: If a picture doesn’t paint a thousand words, then the graph won’t help me understand it. (c) Contrapositive: If the graph doesn’t help me understand it, then a picture doesn’t paint a thousand words. 26. The conditional statement: ~p (q r). (a) Converse: (q r) ~p. (b) Inverse: p ~(q r), or p (~q ~r). (c) Contrapositive: ~(q r) p, or (~q ~r) p. 20. The statement “all irrational numbers are real numbers” is true, because the real numbers are made up of both the rational and irrational numbers. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. 94 CHAPTER 3 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 27. Complete an Euler diagram as: Since, when the premises are diagrammed as being true, and we are forced into a true conclusion, the argument is valid. 28. (a) Let p represent “he eats liver” and q represent “he will eat anything.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq p q. This is the valid argument form “modus ponens,” hence the answer is A. (b) Let p represent “you use your seat belt” and q represent “you will be safer.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq ~p ~q. The answer is F, a fallacy of the inverse. (c) Let p represent “I hear Mr. Bojangles,” q represent “I think of her,” and r represent “I smile.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq qr p r. This is the valid argument form “reasoning by transitivity,” hence the answer is C. (d) Let p represent “she sings” and q represent “she dances.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: p q ~p q. This is the valid argument form “disjunctive syllogism,” hence the answer is D. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc. CHAPTER 3 TEST 95 29. Let p represent “I write a check,” q represent “it will bounce,” and r represent “the bank guarantees it.” The argument is then represented symbolically by: pq r ~q r ~p. Construct the truth table for ([(p q) (r ~q)] r) (~p). (r ~q)] r) (~p) T F T T T F F F T T F F T F F F T F F F T T T F T T F F F F F T T F F T F T T T F T F F F T T T F T F T T F T F F F T T F F T T T T T T T T T T F F F T T F T T F F T T 2 3 1 2 1 4 3 5 4 p q r T T T T T F T F T T F F ([(p q) Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is a tautology, the argument is valid. 30. Construct the truth table for [(~p ~q) (q p)] (p q). p q [(~p ~q) (q p)] (p q) T T F T F T T T T T T T T T F F T T T F T T T T T F F T T F F F T F F T F T T F F T T T T F T F F F F F 1 2 1 3 1 2 1 4 2 3 2 Since the conditional, formed by the conjunction of premises implying the conclusion, is not a tautology, the argument is invalid. Copyright © 2016 Pearson Education, Inc.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz