Rastko Močnik 316.75:141.7 Two Types of Ideological Interpellation Abstract: The paper presents a contribution to the theory of ideology based on Althusser’s idea of ideological interpellation. Ideological interpellation is conceptualised along a simplified re-elaboration of Oswald Ducrot’s treatment of Bakhtinian polyphony. The text distinguishes between interpellation by identification (reproductive) and interpellation by subjectivation (disruptive and eventually innovative, with reference to Rancière). Finally, the text attempts to describe the articulation between political and theoretical practices on the historical case of Lenin’s polemics against the “otzovism”. Keywords: Theory of ideology, ideological interpellation, polyphony, identification, subjectivation, political effects of theoretical practices. I n the present paper I shall attempt a contribution to the theory of ideology. How theories of ideology matter can easily be shown if we consider the political consequences of a particular theory. In Lukács’s History and Class Consciousness, for example, the only true classes are the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, the line of their confrontation is historically objectively determined, and the outcome of their struggle depends upon how successful each particular class will be at its class composition which, in turn, depends on their “achieving” or “realising” their class consciousness.1 In practical political terms, this boils down to the doctrine of the Bolshevik type party, committed to the Leninist “introduction of consciousness into the proletariat”.2 If, to the contrary, we develop a theory of ideology around “[…] when the final economic crisis of capitalism develops, the fate of the revolution (and with it the fate of mankind) will depend on the ideological maturity of the proletariat, i.e. on its class consciousness.” G. Lukács, History and Class Consciousness. 2“Social-Democracy leads the struggle of the working class […]. Social- 1 Rastko Močnik | 35 a certain interpretation of the Gramscian concept of hegemony, we may get Berlinguer’s doctrine of “historical compromise”.3 In the two doctrines that, in a sense, mark the range of the 20th century communist politics, we can discern an undervaluation of the role that ideological pluralism performs in the reproduction of bourgeois society. Lukács reserves the possibility of ideological interpellation to the marginal classes like the peasantry or the petty bourgeoisie, whose consciousness, he writes, “is always borrowed from elsewhere”, and does not investigate the conditions of the possibility of such “borrowing”. Such an investigation might have prompted him to reflect upon the relevance of ideological interpellation for the proletarian individuals, and might have consequently reduced his historical optimism. On the other side, Berlinguer seems not to have considered that parliamentary democracy is the material existence of bourgeois ideological pluralism, and is thus a mechanism that reproduces bourgeois domination. These theoretical insufficiencies had enormous political consequences. The two paradigmatic political failures of traditional communism, Stalinist politics and the Euro-communist way, actually shared the two theoretical insufficiencies of traditional Marxism, the absence of a theory of ideological interpellation and that of a theory of the material existence of ideology. The Bolshevik educational stance not only overlooked every individual’s vulnerability to ideological interpellation coming from discourses other than those presum- 3 Democracy represents the working class […]. We must take up actively the political education of the working class and the development of its political consciousness. […] Class political consciousness can be brought to the workers only from without, that is, only from outside the economic struggle, from outside the sphere of relations between workers and employers.” V. I. Lenin, What is to be done? “L’esperienza compiuta ci ha portato alla conclusione che la democrazia è oggi non soltanto il terreno su cui l’avversario di classe è costretto a retrocedere, ma anche il valore storicamente universale sul quale fondare una società socialista”. Enrico Berlinguer, discourse in Moscow, 1970. “La gravità dei problemi del paese, le minacce sempre incombenti di avventure reazionarie e la necessità di aprire finalmente alla nazione una sicura via di sviluppo economico, di rinnovamento sociale e di progresso democratico rendono sempre più urgente e maturo che si giunga a quello che può essere definito il nuovo grande ‘compromesso storico’ tra le forze che raccolgono e rappresentano la grande maggioranza del popolo italiano.” (Enrico Berlinguer, Riflessioni sull’Italia dopo i fatti del Cile. Alleanze sociali e schieramenti politici, Rinascita, 12 October 1973). 36 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 ably belonging to her or his “own” imputed class consciousness, it was also blind to the material existence of ideology as instantiated in the Bolshevik party itself. Euro-communist democratism not only ignored the concrete historical character of multi-party parliamentarism as the material existence of bourgeois ideological pluralism and hence a mechanism of bourgeois class domination, it also neglected the crucial importance of ideological interpellations operating outside the political apparatus, and thus abandoned the constitutive tenets of Gramsci’s theory of hegemony. Such considerations underline the theoretico-political outreach of Althusser’s concepts of ideological interpellation and of the material existence of ideology. The present paper situates itself within the field delineated by these two Althusserian concepts. Orientation towards another discourse and double inscription of discursive sequences Within the above sketched theoretical horizon, we shall approach the problem of ideological interpellation by first examining discursive phenomena like the one we can observe in Shakespeare’s verse If snow be white, why then her breasts are dun Sonnet 130, v. 3 It would be a simplistic reduction to contend that a reader not familiar with the cliché “breasts white like snow” would not be able to understand this verse. It would be more productive, and probably also more realistic (for how often do we really encounter this kind of clichés nowadays?) to argue that a reader educated in the present scholarly canon would be able to understand the verse regardless of the biographical contingency of having ever come across the concetto or not.4 4 The same phenomenon occurs when we interpret utterances like: “I believe in God”; “I believe in friendship”; “I believe in democracy”; etc. These utterances offer no indication as to what is to be believed regarding God, friendship, democracy etc., and still we have no trouble to understand them as saying “I believe … that God exists; … that friends are loyal to each other; … that democracy has beneficent effects generally ascribed to it; …” etc. Rastko Močnik | 37 We will try to show that this self-supporting enlightenment on the part of the interpreter results from ideological interpellation in the Althusserian sense. If we deploy the process condensed in Shakespeare’s verse we may get an initial idea about the components of interpellation:5 If snow be white, then breasts should be like snow. If breasts should be like snow, why then her breasts are dun. Two features should retain our attention: 1. the utterance alludes to a sequence that, although not enunciated, contributes to its meaning (the sequence in italics); 2. a component of the sequence is reduplicated and appears in two positions of the reasoning, first as a conclusion and next as a premise. In Shakespeare’s verse, the two mechanisms are condensed in the same string. The following less artistic utterance will help us to further elaborate our conceptual framework: If you got trouble, get a lawyer. Then you got more trouble, but at least you got a lawyer.6 We can present this string as an argumentation in three phases: 1. The first argumentation consists of an argument and a conclusion. The argument runs: “If you got trouble, you need a trouble-shooter.” The conclusion drawn from this argument states: “Therefore the best thing to do is to get a lawyer.” 5 6 As a sonnet is an artistic, not an ideological formation, it may seem abusive to probe it for ideological mechanisms. However, as we conceptualise aesthetic practice as a secondary elaboration upon ideological elements, an artistic formation entails ideological mechanisms which it transforms in a specific (“aesthetic”) way. In the original: “Whenever you got business trouble the best thing to do is to get a lawyer. Then you got more trouble, but at least you got a lawyer.” (Chico in: Marx Brothers, At the Circus, 1939.) – In the present paper, I re-elaborate certain motifs of my past theoretical attempts; I also re-analyse some cases that I have, in a different way, worked upon in the past. The present example was first used in: Beseda besedo (Ljubljana: ŠKUC, 1984). 38 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 2. The conclusion of the first argumentation figures as the argument of the second argumentation: “Having a lawyer –” and leads to the second conclusion: “you got more trouble.” 3. The third argument: “But at least you’ll have a lawyer.” – invites the addressee to draw a conclusion of her-his own. Sequences written in italics are left unspoken. The articulation of the first argumentation upon the second one is secured by the double inscription of “having a lawyer”, presented first as a remedy to the trouble, and next as its source. The economical procedure of the double inscription of a single signifier into two differently oriented argumentations contributes to the effect of the witticism. The third inscription completes it. It seems that we should more closely consider the mechanism that combines polysyllogistic linking of arguments (conclusion of the preceding argumentation operates as the argument of the following argumentation) with an allusion to an absent sequence that generates the meaning of the utterance. (1) Although Serbs are inclined to authoritarian government, it will depend upon the opposition and the civil society whether Serbia will become authoritarian. Vili Einspieler, Authoritarian government without opposition – Elections in Serbia, Delo, Ljubljana, 15. 3. 2014 In grammar “although” is a concessive subordinate conjunction: for our purpose, we will say that it inverts the conclusion which would normally follow from the clause it introduces. Like: Although the weather is fine, I will not go for a walk. Although I studied a lot, I failed the exam. Or, in general terms: Although A is an argument for the conclusion C, the speaker is not going to conclude to C. Interpretation of the “although-utterances” obviously hinges upon the assumption that, were it not for the expression “although”, the argumentation would run: Rastko Močnik | 39 The weather is fine, I will go for a walk. I studied a lot and I passed the exam. The link that connects the argument (or the ground) and the conclusion (or the claim) is called warrant by Stephen E. Toulmin and topos by Oswald Ducrot. This link is not explicitly mentioned in the utterance: it is tacitly proposed by the speaker and admitted by the addressee. In our examples, Ducrot would reconstruct the connecting links as: “When the weather is fine, it is to be expected that the walk is pleasant” and “If one studies, it is to be expected that one passes the exam”. The “missing link” determines the meaning of the utterance – and is not perceived as “missing” either by the speaker or by the interpreter. Contrary to Toulmin and Ducrot, we will not conceive it as a frozen stereotype that hovers above a given discursive universe and determines the cultural horizon of a communicational community. We will rather conceptualise it as a fragment of the “discourse of the other” (čužoe slovo) in the Bakhtinian sense, to which the utterer and the interpreter spontaneously refer while producing the sense of their intercourse. As long as it is undergone in the manner of a reified Aristotelian topos,7 it is the material support of ideological interpellation that reproduces the existing ideological constellation. If it is made to operate as a piece of discourse towards which the explicit sequences of an utterance polemically point, it may effectuate a disruptive interpellation, and it may become, in Vološinov’s words, “the arena of the class struggle”. One cannot easily imagine the link which in (1) connects the argument to the conclusion.8 On the other hand, readers of Ljubljana daily Delo have no difficulty understanding it. We may surmise that an ordinary Delo-reader interprets (1) as: “Although Serbs are inclined to authoritarian government, it will depend upon the activities of the opposition and the civil society after the elections whether Serbia will become authoritarian”. 7 8 Cf. Aristotle’s definition of the topos: “[…] those opinions are ‘generally accepted’ which are accepted by every one or by the majority or by the philosophers – i .e. by all, or by the majority, or by the most notable and illustrious of them.” Aristotle, Topics, Book I, Chapter 1, translated by W. A. Pickard. There would be no problem to interpret an utterance like: “Although Serbs are inclined to authoritarian government, they are not likely to elect an authoritarian government this time” . 40 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 Understanding of (1) seems to depend upon a particular representation of the multi-party parliamentarian system according to which the electoral body does not have much to say once the elections are over. Although the sequence that would convey such a representation is missing from (1), its writer and his readers seem to be able to accede to the meaning it generates. The missing link is proposed as self-evident and by way of a tacit suggestion smuggled into the communicational interaction as one of its material supports. Completed with the missing sequence, (1) would run as follows: (1’) Although Serbs are inclined to authoritarian government, the attitude of the body politic will not affect the final political outcome, whatever the result of the elections; it will depend upon the opposition and the civil society whether Serbia will become authoritarian. Note that the utterance has the structure of a double enthymeme: the missing conclusion of the first argument figures as the missing argument of the final conclusion: Argument1 Although Serbs are inclined to authoritarian government, Conclusion1 the attitude of the body politic will not affect the final political outcome, whatever the result of the elections; Argument2 [as] the attitude of the body politic will not affect the final political outcome, Conclusion2 it will depend upon the opposition and the civil society whether Serbia will become authoritarian. Consequently, it is not only the obvious element of chauvinism that supports the ideological operation in (1) (i.e., Serbs as an authoritarian nation); much more performing is the non-obvious element that presents the bourgeois parliamentarism first as “normal” and second as beneficent, since it corrects the Serbs’ sinister mores. The tacitly suggested component is doubly inscribed in the argumentation scheme: first as the conclusion of the first argumentation sequence and next as the argument of the following one. The scheme of (1) could be represented as follows (the explicit components are in bold and the tacitly suggested components are in italics): Rastko Močnik | 41 A1 C1 = A2 C2 This seems to be a frequent ideological mechanism. The following utterance offers its expanded version. (2) Without Crimea, Ukraine probably has an even better chance to become a reformed democratic state. It will be more pro-European, since it lost so much pro-Russian population. Roman Szporluk, professor emeritus, Harvard University, interview in Delo, Ljubljana, 12. 4. 2014 Completing the missing sequences, we can re-write (2) as follows: Argument1 Ukraine lost a lot of pro-Russian population. Conclusion1 [therefore] it will be less pro-Russian. Argument2 [as] Ukraine will be less pro-Russian, Conclusion2 it will be more pro-European. Argument3 [as] Ukraine will be more pro-European, Conclusion3 it will be more democratic. Argument4 [As] Ukraine will be more democratic, Conclusion4 it has a better chance to become a reformed democratic state. It is the tacit components that construe semantic features which support the argumentation: the opposition “pro-Russian vs. pro-European” and the equation “pro-European = democratic”. The poly-enthymemic scheme is thus a flattening formalisation of a polyphonic process where “orientation towards another discourse” (in the Bakhtinian sense: ustanovka na čužoe slovo) produces ideological effects. The reference to another discourse generates the meaning of the utterance, and occurs automatically in the act of interpretation. Consider the following argumentation: (3) There are no more Stalinists in our Party; we liquidated the last one yesterday. (3) would not produce the comical effect it does were it not for the reference to another discourse that undermines its seemingly logical argumenta- 42 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 tion. The reference intervenes between the argument “We liquidated the last Stalinist yesterday” and the conclusion “therefore there are no more Stalinists in our Party”. The reference that triggers the humorous effect is automatic with everybody who masters the particular “Stalinist-Party” jargon: Argument1 We liquidated the last Stalinist yesterday; Conclusion1 [therefore:] we resorted to Stalinist methods. Argument2 [As] we resorted to Stalinist methods, Conclusion2 there are no more Stalinists in our Party. (??) Until now, we have been considering cases where the argument and the conclusion were explicitly stated, while the conclusion could only be reached from the argument by the mediation of “another” discourse which secured the connection C1 = A2. The following is an utterance where only the first argument is explicitly proposed, and the interpreter has to provide both the mediating sequence and the final conclusion. (4) This is a choice between Europe and the Balkans. Slovene Prime minister Janez Drnovšek, interview, Dnevnik, Ljubljana, 3. 6. 1995 (4) can be analysed as follows: This is a choice between Europe and the Balkans. Argument1 Conclusion1 [therefore:]it is the choice between civilisation and barbarism. [As] it is the choice between civilisation and barbarism, Argument2 Conclusion2 one/we/you can only chose Europe. (4) actually offers you a choice: you can chose Europe either because it is civilised or because it is the opposite of the barbaric Balkans. The horizon of democratic deliberation here stretches between Balkano-phobia and Europhilia. Utterances (1) – (4) share the common feature that their interpretation or their “uptake” depends upon the interpreter’s reconstruction of the “other” discourse to whom they refer – not in their meaning, but by way of their structure, by the constraints of their argumentation procedure. However, this strictly formal completion of the utterance yields its meaning: the interpreter, by completing the utterance with the sequence towards which it is oriented, Rastko Močnik | 43 assumes this decisive ideological component and, by the act of understanding, in a certain way “ratifies” the ideological element. This is the mechanism of ideological interpellation; or, better yet, this is one of the mechanisms of ideological interpellation, the one that relies, in Bakhtin’s terminology, upon one-directional double-voicedness.9 We will call this type of ideological interpellation interpellation by identification, since the interpreter, by identifying her/himself with the addressee of the utterance, transforms her/himself into the individual, interpellated as the Ego (and not directly as the subject, as in Althusser’s famous formula).10 Before analysing the second type of interpellation, we shall examine a transitional kind that emerged at the beginning of Western individualism in French classical tragedy. We shall consider the case of Chimène in Corneille’s Le Cid. However, rather than taking the elaborated way in which Corneille presents Chimène in his tragedy, we shall look at the blunt ideological presentation of Chimène’s dilemma that Corneille found in a Spanish historia and which struck his mind. After quoting the passage in Spanish, Corneille comments: Ceux qui entendent l’espagnol y remarqueront deux circonstances: l’une, que Chimène, ne pouvant s’empêcher de reconnaître et d’aimer les belles qualités qu’elle voyait en don Rodrigue, quoiqu’il eût tué son père, alla proposer elle-même au roi cette généreuse alternative, ou qu’il le lui donnât pour mari, ou qu’il le fît punir suivant les lois; l’autre, que ce mariage se fit au gré de tout le monde. (Corneille, Avertissement, 1648.) How did Chimène arrive at the idea to propose this generous alternative to the monarch? We can reconstruct her reasoning as follows: 9 10 In chapter 5 “Discourse in Dostojevskij” of Problems of Dostojevskij’s Poetics (1963: Problemy poètiki Dostoevskogo, Moskva: Sovetskij pisatel’), Bakhtin gives a classification of discourses where he first distinguishes single-voiced discourse (edinogolosnoe slovo) from double-voiced discourse (dvugolosnoe slovo). The differential feature of the double-voiced discourse is its orientation towards another discourse (ustanovka na čužoe slovo). The double-voiced discourse can be one-directional (where the directions of the two discourses are the same) or pluri-directional (where the two directions differ). Parody is a multi-directional double-voiced discourse. Examples of one-directional double-voiced discourse are stylisation, skaz’, Icherzählung. Or, in Freudian terms: the interpreter … 44 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 Argument1 I have a choice. Conclusion1 [therefore:] I am free. [As] I am free, Argument2 Conclusion2 I can delegate my being free to the monarch. The sequence relies upon the triple inscription of the signifier “free”: first the familiar double inscription at the articulation C1 = A2, and next the third inscription in C2 that changes the direction of the argumentation and transforms freedom into subjection. It is perhaps this almost Hobbesian logic in Chimène’s reasoning that fascinated Corneille: the transition from the first argument to the second is secured by the reproductive interpellation C1 = A2, while the disruptive third inscription ends up in the act of subjection. Chimène’s tour de force consists in accomplishing the act of subjection as an act of freedom. This seems to be an extravagant illustration of Althusser’s intuitive equation of subjectivation with subjection. Chimène’s case as presented in the Jesuit father Juan Marianna’s chronicle thus combines interpellation by identification and the mechanism that we will analyse as interpellation by subjectivation. For subjectivation is also the effect of a double inscription of a signifier, only that now the signifier is inscribed in two differently directed discourses. We will exemplify it with the utterance that Rancière offers as a paradigmatic case of political subjectivation:11 11In Au bords du politique (Paris: Gallimard, 2004) Jacques Rancière actually remains within the limits of an intuitive notion of political subjectivation. Although he rightly opposes subjectivation to identification, this seems more an essayistic determination a contrario than the production of a problem field. – We can notice an analogous inability to proceed from philosophical intuition to theoretical conceptualisation already in Rancière’s contribution to Lire Le Capital (Le concept de critique et la critique de l’économie politique des “Manuscrits de 1844” au “Capital”). There Rancière meticulously analyses Marx’s “genesis of the value form” and rightly claims that the theory of the possibility of the “impossible” simple-exchange equation radically distinguishes Marx from the classical political economy. However, Rancière purports that the instance of overdetermination (that makes the “impossible” equation possible) is the capitalist mode of production and not the simple commodity production (Louis Althusser and others, Lire Le Capital, Paris: PUF, 1996, 121). By overlooking Marx’s initial distinction between the simple commodity production Rastko Močnik | 45 (5) We are all German Jews!12 There is a relevant difference in the way how the double inscription, the pivot of ideological mechanism, operates in Marchais’s “original” and in the students’ riposte. Marchais’s utterance proposes the standard interpellation by identification, anchored in the non-uttered redoubled sequence C1 = A2. In the students’ slogan, the double inscription is more complex: the doubly inscribed element “German Jew” refers simultaneously to the con- 12 and the capitalist production (which is also an epistemological break with the classical political economy), Rancière runs into serious difficulties, and finally fails to interpret Marx’s concept of die verwandelte Formen, the converted forms. Rancière’s philosophical blunder blocks theoretical analysis since, “if we ask ourselves about the structure of the relations among the classes in a given society, […] we are asking ourselves, in the first place, about the ‘transformed forms’ specific to this society” (Étienne Balibar, Concepts fondamentaux du matérialisme historique, op. cit., 450; my translation). – It is the same incapacity to develop a theoretical problem field that prevents Rancière to conceptually articulate his concrete example (“Nous sommes tous des juifs allemands”, Au bords du politique, 120) as a disruptive ideological interpellation within the class struggle that was bringing down the “structure of the relations among the classes” in a critical moment of history of French imperialism and Euro-Atlantic core-capitalism. According to the official site of the National Assembly of the French Republic (http://www.assemblee-nationale.fr/histoire/mai_68/ chronologie.asp, 14. January 2012) the slogan “Nous sommes tous des Juifs et des Allemands – We are all Jews and Germans” appeared for the first time on 22 May 1968 on a poster for the manifestation against the interdiction of the stay in France issued against Daniel Cohn-Bendit a day before; the same source states that demonstrators gathered that evening in front of the National Assembly shouted the slogan “We are all German Jews”. Already on 3 May, L’Humanité, the official daily of the Communist Party of France, published a text by Georges Marchais, the organisational secretary of CPF, condemning “the agitation that goes against the interests of the mass of students and favours fascist provocations”, led by the Movement of 22 March “under the direction of the German anarchist Cohn-Bendit”. The slogan “Nous sommes tous des Juifs allemands – We are all German Jews” acquired notoriety at the manifestation in the Latin Quarter in Paris on 31 May. (I thank Todor Petkov for his investigation into the background of the students’ slogan.) 46 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 tested phantom utterance and to the un-uttered argument that introduces the counter-argumentation. Contrary to Marchais’s interpellation by identification where the double inscription relays two discourses having the same direction, students’ interpellation by subjectivation articulates two discourses pointing at opposite directions. Marchais The Movement of 22 March is led by a German anarchist; Therefore it is led by a false revolutionary. The Movement is led by a false revolutionary; therefore it is a false revolutionary movement. Students However, we are all the leaders of our movement; therefore: We are all German Jews. The decisive feature that makes for the interpellation by subjectivation is the inscription of the same sequence into two discourses with opposite directions. We can call this kind of double inscription counter-inscription.13 However, the direction of the second argumentation that is opposite to the direction of the first (Marchais’s) argumentation is produced by the second inscription of the sequence “German Jews”. And so is the reference to the “other” discourse, the unspoken argument A2 that opposes the argument A1. The subjectivating sequence operates in a contradictory way: it only acquires meaning by the reference to the A1 it opposes; and it can oppose A1 because it is treated as a signifier in its pure materiality “before” any eventual meaning. In this way, it carries the polemics with its own occurrence in the “other” discourse: in Vološinov’s words, it re-articulates itself into “the arena of the class struggle”. Thirty years later Daniel Cohn-Bendit, adapting the slogan to the spirit of the epoch, offered a different interpretation: he transformed revolt into a politics of identity, and thus reduced the disruptive interpellation by subjectivation to 13 We could also call it “allotric” inscription, from the Greek allótrios: belonging to another, foreign; contrary, contradictory; alienated, nonadequate. Rastko Močnik | 47 a curious interpellation which is disruptive subjectivation with respect to the contested racist phantom (the counter-inscription of “German Jew”) – and is reproductive interpellation by identification with respect to the hegemonic identitary ideology of the nineties (the C1 = A2 inscription of “marginalised person”):14 Phantom statement Students according to Cohn-Bendit, 1998 A German Jew is leading the movement; therefore a marginalised person is leading the movement. [As] we identify with the marginalised, We are all German Jews. The contradictory mechanism of Cohn-Bendit’s re-interpretation, combining identification by identification with interpellation by subjectivation, is analogous to Chimène’s treatment that led to the voluntary alienation of freedom to the monarch. The same mechanism that introduced individual freedom at the beginning of the modern epoch is abolishing it at the end of Modernity. At the beginning, subjectivation was achieved through subjection to the monarch, at the end it is trapped into self-righteous polemics against a phantom opponent. At the beginning, interpellation by identification was supported by the double inscription of the sequence “I am free”, at the end the reproductive redoubled sequence announces identification with the “marginalised”. 14 “Slogan qui reprenait une phrase de Georges Marchais, qui m’avait traité d’anarchiste allemand pour faire jouer la phobie antiboche: les étudiants à Nanterre ont crié ce qu’il n’avait pas osé dire: ”juif allemand“. Depuis, l’anathème raciste contre l’enragé est devenu anathème antiraciste. Et ce slogan a servi de support au refus de l’exclusion sous toutes ses formes: ‘Nous sommes tous des immigrés’, ‘Nous sommes tous des étrangers’, ‘Nous sommes tous des sanspapiers’. Il traduit une identification d’une partie de la jeunesse avec ceux qui sont en marge de la société”. (Nous sommes tous des juifs allemands. Interview with Daniel Cohn-Bendit, L’Express, 16 April 1998. http://www.lexpress.fr/informations/nous-sommes-tous-des-juifsallemands_628699.html#pjTjK6fT6pv5JJMM.99; 12 May 2014.) 48 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 Political practice and theoretical practice At the beginning of this paper, we showed how particular theories of ideology produce specific political consequences. At this point, we cannot as yet speculate about eventual political consequences of the above sketched theory; however, we can already show that our theory makes it possible to describe the articulation between political and theoretical practices. We shall examine this articulation on the relatively simple historical example of Lenin’s polemics against otzovizm.15 At a first glance, we can resume the two opposing position in the debate as follows: Otzovists The Duma is a reactionary political apparatus, therefore we should boycott it. 15 Lenin However, the Duma is also an ideological apparatus, therefore we shall use it as a platform for our agitation and propaganda. After 1906, sharp debates arose in the Russian Social-democratic Labour Party about whether to participate in the “Second Duma” or to boycott it. The radical left wing advocated a boycott with the argument that the Duma is a monarchical and bourgeois political apparatus and should therefore be destroyed, together with the bourgeois monarchy, by the proletarian revolution. Against this position, called “otzovizm” (from the Russian verb “отозвать” – “to call back, to recall” /the representatives of the revolutionary parties from the Duma – the tsarist parliament/), Lenin argued that, in class-terms, the Duma was even worse, since it was the political apparatus of the landlord and reactionary bourgeois counter-revolution; however, the Duma was also an ideological apparatus and, as such, it should be used by revolutionary parties for their agitation and propaganda, as a subsidiary field of struggle integrated into the over-all class struggle predominantly led outside the Duma and whose immediate political goal was the formation of a constituent assembly by revolutionary means. The positions opposed in this debate were both theoreticaally justifiable: but only one was politically correct. By developing a superior theory of the Duma as political and ideological apparatus, Lenin was able to impose the politically correct response to a historical situation. Rastko Močnik | 49 In this immediate form, the debate opposes two ideological discourses. If we reconstitute the missing link C1 = A2 in the otzovist discourse, we obtain: Otzovists The Duma is a reactionary political apparatus, therefore it is unsuitable to our political work. It is unsuitable to our political work, therefore we should boycott it. Lenin intervened at the place of the un-uttered sequence C1 = A2 that binds together the argument and the conclusion of the otzovist ideological argumentation. He developed the concept of “political work” that is implicit in his polemics and can be restored as follows:16 1. Political work is not only the work within the frame of bourgeois political apparatuses. On the contrary: revolutionary political work is primarily performed outside the bourgeois political sphere, it is the selforganisation of the proletariat. The main dimension of revolutionary political work is the construction of an autonomous proletarian political apparatus, i.e., the organisation of a proletarian party. The proletarian party engages in two dimensions of the proletarian class struggle: a. In agitation, propaganda, critique, exposure (of the “real” nature of other parties): i.e., in ideological work. b. However, the main dimension of the proletarian struggle in this historical conjuncture is a direct revolutionary struggle: strikes, uprisings etc. whose goal is the convocation of a constituent assembly by revolutionary means. 2.. Political work is performed also, although not primarily, in ideological apparatuses: and it will be possible to transform the Duma into an ideological apparatus and there to carry out a partial and subordinate ideological work. 16 We resume Lenin’s implicit theory of political work from: the two articles in Proletariy of 9 July and 21 August 1906; and from Lenin’s interventions at the V. Congress of the Russian Social-Democratic Labour Party (30 April - 19 May - 13 May - 1 June, 1907). 50 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 In Lenin’s polemics, the binding missing link is provided by a transposition of theoretical discourse onto ideological discourse. In the implicit theoretical discourse, Lenin introduces a subtle double distinction: first the dominant distinction between two types of revolutionary practice, and the two apparatuses that correspond to this distinction (the political apparatus and the ideological one). And next, within the ideological practice, the subordinate distinction between the primary ideological practice carried out among the “masses” (“education”) and the secondary ideological practice. The secondary ideological practice is the one performed within the bourgeois political apparatus, transformed by this practice itself into a subaltern ideological apparatus of the proletarian politics.17 This complex theoretical construction is condensed within the ideological discourse into a distinction that appeals to (ideological) intuition, the distinction between a partial form of the proletarian class-struggle and “the struggle of the proletariat as a whole”. An important practical consequence follows: the part should be subordinated to the whole.18 17 18 Lenin presented the difference between the main political work among the masses and the subordinate political operations in the Duma as follows: “The second point is devoted to an explanation of the relation between direct “legislative” activity in the Duma, and agitation, criticism, propaganda, organisation. The workers’ party regards the connection between work within and without the Duma very differently from the way the liberal bourgeoisie regards it. It is necessary to stress this radical difference of views. On the one hand, there are the bourgeois politicians, enraptured by their parliamentary games behind the backs of the people. On the other hand, there is a contingent of the organised proletariat that has been sent into the enemy camp and is carrying on work closely connected with the struggle of the proletariat as a whole. For us there is only one, single and indivisible, workers’ movement – the class struggle of the proletariat. All its separate, partial forms, including the parliamentary struggle, must be fully subordinated to it. For us it is the extra-Duma struggle of the proletariat that is decisive”. (Report of the Commission Formed to Draft a Resolution on the State Duma, 18 /31/ May, V. Congress of the RSDLP, 1907.) Lenin explicitly underlines the asymmetry between the parliamentary form of the proletarian struggle and its extra-parliamentary forms: “The part must conform to the whole, and not vice versa. The Duma may temporarily serve as an arena of the class struggle as a whole, but only if that whole is never lost sight of, and if the revolutionary tasks of the class struggle are not concealed”. (Vladimir I. Lenin, Report of the Commission Formed to Draft a Resolution on the State Duma, May Rastko Močnik | 51 Lenin However, the Duma is also an ideological apparatus, therefore it can be made into the arena of a subordinate and partial dimension of our political work. It can be made into the arena of a subordinate and partial dimension of our political work; therefore we shall use it as a platform for our agitation and propaganda. Theory intervenes at the place of the double inscription: the doubly inscribed sequence is “our political work”. The signifier “our political work” is doubly inscribed both in the otzovist and in Lenin’s discourse at the locus of the nonuttered ideological sequence that provides the binding component C1 = A2. In the otzovist discourse, it belongs to a spontaneous and intuitive notion of political practice. In Lenin’s discourse, however, the signifier, before entering the concrete discursive formation, already belongs to two radically heterogeneous discourses, to the theoretical and to the ideological discourse. In the theoretical register, it is a component of the complex conceptual field structured by theoretical distinctions (“political / ideological”, “dominant aspect / subordinate aspect”, “proletarian practice-apparatus / bourgeois practiceapparatus” etc.) that produce a theoretical problématique. In the ideological register, the signifier “our political work” is both a projection of a theoretical concept onto the ideological field, and as such a projection, an ideological notion participating in the ideological opposition “part/whole”. In this case, the redoubled sequence “political work” supports, within the ideological argumentation, the trivial interpellation by identification. Its counter-inscription operates in another dimension – within the relation between ideological discourse and theoretical discourse. Here, the heterogeneity of the two inscriptions of the same signifier does not originate in the opposed directions of the two discourses, since theoretical discourse cannot have an ideological direction. The “allotric” character of the double inscription resides in the fact that the signifier “political work” operates as a (theo- 18 (31), 1907, The Fifth Congress of the Russian Social-democratic Labour Party; in: Vladimir I. Lenin, Collected Works, Volume 12, Moscow: Progress Publishers and Foreign Languages Press, http:// www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1907/5thcong/12.htm accessed 22. July 2013). 52 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 retical) concept in the theoretical discourse and as an (ideological) notion in the ideological discourse. Interpellation by subjectivation is thus achieved in the dimension that articulates the heterogeneous theoretical and ideological discourses. The specificity of this particular kind of interpellation by subjectivation resides in its being approachable through theoretical elaboration and thus not being dependent upon the spontaneity of ideological mechanisms. We see that Lenin turned an internal party debate into an opportunity for theoretical elaboration. We also see that his theoretical elaboration produced ideological effects within the interior party debate and political effects in the proletarian class struggle “as a whole”. This may well be one of the characteristic features of the Leninist practice: the capacity to turn fraction strife into theoretically productive and practically efficient practice; and the complementary ability to translate theoretical achievements into practical tools. This is a concrete historical instance of the privileged relationship that proletarian political practice enjoys with theoretical practice. We can map Lenin’s theoretico-political practice upon the scheme we have presented in another context:19 19 Historical transformation and epistemological discontinuity, Filozofija i društvo – Philosophy and society, XXIV (4), 2013. There, the scheme is presented as follows: “A historically given technical composition of labour power [at the time t] is confronted by a political composition of the working class historically produced by the workers’ class struggle [at the time t]. Although at every particular historical moment the class struggle is determined by the particular technical composition imposed upon the labour power by the dominant mode of production, class response to such a technical composition is the response of the working class, not of the particular labour power trapped in its given historical technical composition. It is in this sense that class composition is political: it effectuates a recomposition of the entire class, of all the various sectors of workers involved in various historically existing modes of production, dominant or not, and in the many variants of the dominating mode. Class composition is political as far as it challenges the ‘technical determinism’ of various historical technical compositions and reaches beyond the divisions imposed upon the labour power by the technical existence of the capital as constant capital. By destroying the fragmentation of workers resulting from the existence of various technical compositions of the labour force as various historical types of capital domination and exploitation, political class composition not only produces a political unity of the working class, it also challenges Rastko Močnik | 53 means of productiont technological unityt resistance technical composition of labor powert theoretical to theory: knowledge analysis destruction resistance criticism political compositiont political composition of the working classt-1 resistance to criticism Lenin’s intervention starts as “criticism” against the mechanical transposition to the present of the previously successful former political composition of the working class. (Or, more precisely, Lenin opposes the eventual present re-actualisation of a component of the previous class-composition, the boycott of the Duma). Lenin then switches to the theoretical register and develops an ad hoc analysis of historical conjuncture; he anticipates “knowledgeable” resistance from the bourgeois side (the “liberals”); having the domination of the dominating mode of production. While political composition of the working class results from the class struggle of the working class under the conditions primarily determined by the technical composition of the labour force, the technical composition of the labour force results from the class struggle of the capitalist class combating the working class political composition [at the previous historical moment, i.e. at the time t-1]. Accordingly, the technical composition of the labour force [at the time t] is the response of the capitalists’ class struggle against the historically antecedent political composition of the working class [at the time t-1]. This would mean that the working class has a historical advantage over the capitalist class under the condition that they succeed in their political class composition. Permanent technical revolution as one of the basic features of the capitalist mode should accordingly be considered not only as the consequence of the competition among individual capitals to appropriate extra-profit (as it is perceived by the capitalist ideology), it should primarily be conceived as the result of the permanent struggle of the capital to break down the political class composition of working classes.” (Idem, 53; http://instifdt.bg.ac.rs/tekstovi/FiD/2013/FiD-42013/03_Mocnik_2013-4.pdf ; accessed 11 May 2014.) 54 | Belgrade Journal for Media and Communications #6 constructed the basic conceptual inventory, Lenin translates these concepts into ideological notions and returns to the ideological register where he combats resistances of the representatives of the previous class-composition (the Mensheviks), finally proposing the new political line that will result in the new class-composition, adequate to the new situation. Rastko Močnik is a sociologist who teaches theory of ideology, theory of discourse and epistemology of the humanities and social sciences at the Faculty of Philosophy, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia. Visiting professor at the Faculty for Media and Communications, Belgrade. Co-chair of the International Board of Directors of the Institute for Critical Social Studies, Sofia and Plovdiv. Member of the international advisory board, Eszmélet, Budapest. Member of the international advisory board, Sociologičeski problemi, Sofia. Member of the editorial board, Vestnik Permskogo universiteta – Filosofija, psihologija, sociologija, Perm. Member of the editorial board, Vestnik Novosibirskogo gosudarstvennogo universiteta. Istorija, filosofija. Vypusk: Žurnalistika, Novosibirsk. Member of the editorial board of the online journal Transeuropéennes, Paris. Member of the editorial board of the publishing house Založba /*cf., Ljubljana. Doctor honoris causa at the Plovdiv University “Paisiy Hilendarski” (2005). Rastko Močnik | 55
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz