University of Birmingham Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars

University of Birmingham
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars: Why They
Don't Talk to Each Other, and Why They Should
van Biezen, Ingrid; Saward, Michael
DOI:
10.1017/S1537592708080043
License:
None: All rights reserved
Document Version
Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record
Citation for published version (Harvard):
Van Biezen, I & Saward, M 2008, 'Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars: Why They Don't Talk to Each
Other, and Why They Should' Perspectives on Politics, vol 6, no. 01, pp. 31-35. DOI:
10.1017/S1537592708080043
Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal
Publisher Rights Statement:
© Cambridge University Press 2008
Eligibility for repository: checked July 2014
General rights
When referring to this publication, please cite the published version. Copyright and associated moral rights for publications accessible in the
public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners. It is a condition of accessing this publication that users abide by the
legal requirements associated with these rights.
• You may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication.
• Users may download and print one copy of the publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial
research.
• If a Creative Commons licence is associated with this publication, please consult the terms and conditions cited therein.
• Unless otherwise stated, you may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain.
Take down policy
If you believe that this document infringes copyright please contact [email protected] providing details and we will remove access to
the work immediately and investigate.
Download date: 15. Jun. 2017
|
|
䡬
Articles
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars:
Why They Don’t Talk to Each Other, and
Why They Should
Ingrid van Biezen and Michael Saward
Despite their importance to one another, the current literatures on political parties and normative democratic theory continue to
develop largely in mutual isolation. Empirical studies of contemporary political parties and party systems tend to have little to say
about the meanings and possibilities of democracy, and therefore also about the varied potential roles of political parties within it.
Meanwhile, contemporary democratic theorists quietly sidestep the issue of whether political parties perform a legitimate function
in democracies. This lack of mutual engagement is regrettable, in particular given the pervasive erosion of popular support and
legitimacy of political parties as representative institutions. In this article we explore the key reasons for democratic theorists and
scholars of political parties so rarely taking on each others’ core concerns, and we outline the key ways in which this mutual disengagement is mutually impoverishing. We will also suggest ways forward, by pinpointing and illustrating potentially productive areas
of engagement which might serve to deepen our understanding of democracy’s present and its possible futures.
or public institution—less than big companies or trade
unions, and far less than institutions such as the army or
police, or even the United Nations and the European Union
itself.4 Indeed, levels of distrust in political parties, in the
advanced industrial democracies and elsewhere, are now
so high that they are almost beyond scale.5
From this perspective, it is particularly important to
reflect on the functions traditionally assigned to parties in
the processes of democracy, and to ask how the apparently
declining capacity of parties to perform their representative functions can be reversed, or alternatively how both
parties and democratic systems more generally can adapt
to the shift of those functions to other arenas. Do parties
need to be reinvented? If so, what design tools are available, and how could they best be used?
Political science should be able to provide resources to
understand and perhaps to help to address these corrosive
tendencies and pressing concerns. But there is a strong
case for arguing that it has deprived itself of a capacity to
do so, due to a curious, persistent, and ultimately indefensible divide between two distinct sub-disciplinary
domains: democratic theory (DT) and the study of political parties (PP). Any meaningful discussion of concerns
with democracy and democratic legitimacy requires that
empirical developments are assessed with reference to theories of democracy and that normative postulates can be
evaluated in relation to empirical realities. The contemporary challenges to political parties, as part of a broader
crisis of representation, heighten the degree to which the
empirical and the normative need each other as we seek
espite many recent successful cases of democratization, democracy arguably suffers from serious problems of disaffection.1 Among the most acute
challenges to contemporary democracies is a pervasive erosion of popular support for representative democratic institutions. Increasing discontent with politicians and political
parties is a key part of this erosion.
The widespread perception that parties are procedurally necessary for the effective functioning of democracy
does not translate into their being widely supported or
respected. This syndrome is clearly evident, with parties
today often being seen as both the institution most susceptible to corruption,2 and one of the least trusted public
institutions. A growing number of U.S. citizens are increasingly disenchanted with their political parties.3 In the European Union, parties enjoy less trust than any other private
D
Ingrid van Biezen is Reader in Comparative Politics at the
University of Birmingham, UK (i.c.vanbiezen
@bham.ac.uk). Michael Saward is Professor of Politics at
the Open University, UK ([email protected]). The
authors are grateful to Richard S. Katz and Jeremy Jennings
and two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments
and suggestions. In developing our arguments, we also
benefited from conversations with Robert Dahl, Russell
Dalton, Ian Shapiro, workshop participants at the ECPR
Joint Sessions, and graduate students at Yale University.
Part of this research was supported by the British Academy
(research grant SG 38612).
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 21
DOI: 10.1017/S1537592708080043
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
䡬
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
new ways to trace and express links between democracy as
an existing practice and democracy as an unfulfilled ideal.
In this light, it is regrettable that, despite their importance to one another, the current literatures on political
parties and normative democratic theory continue to
develop to an extraordinary degree in mutual isolation.
While assuming that political parties are inevitable for
modern democracy, empirical studies of contemporary parties, party organization, and party systems tend to have
little to say about the varied meanings and possibilities of
democracy, and therefore of the varied potential roles of
political parties within it. Conversely, modern democratic
theory is noticeably silent on the question whether political parties have a legitimate place and function in a democracy. In this article we will back up these claims—noting
that where there are exceptions they tend to prove the
rule—and argue that this mutual neglect is a serious problem which threatens to prevent us taking advantage of
promising areas for potential mutual engagement. We
explore the key underlying reasons why democratic theorists and scholars of political parties should so rarely take
on each others’ core topics and concerns, and sketch just
how this mutual disengagement is mutually impoverishing. The article will, however, suggest ways forward by
pinpointing potentially productive areas of engagement
which, if pursued, might just serve to deepen our understanding of democracy’s present and its possible futures.
Finally, by way of illustration we indicate how building on
theory insights into deliberative democracy and party scholars’ insights into party configuration and organization could
be productive—and, in the light of the pressures that parties (and representation) are under, politically highly
relevant.
Political Theory versus Political
Science
The divide between democratic theory and the study of
political parties can be seen as one part of the broader
disconnection between the sub-discipline of political theory
(or political philosophy—the terms are taken as interchangeable for present purposes) and political science more
generally. Recently, Shapiro has argued that an ongoing
process of professionalization and specialization has dissociated political philosophy from the rest of political science, and has separated normative from empirical theory,
“with political philosophers declaring a monopoly over
the former while abandoning the enterprise of ‘positive’
political theory to other political scientists.” As a consequence, “normative theory . . . is no longer informed, in
the ways that the great theorists of the tradition took it for
granted that political theory should be informed, by the
state of empirical knowledge of politics.” This separation
has not only resulted in an increasing tendency of normative political theory to downgrade concerns over practical
feasibility but “has also fed the tendency for empirical
political theory to become banal and method driven—
detached from the great questions of the day and focused
instead on what seems methodologically most tractable.” 6
Arguably, modern political philosophers have always
been more aware of the nature of their activity and the
way in which their sub-discipline connects to the rest of
political science than their colleagues in other branches of
the discipline.7 Among political theorists in particular,
therefore, the problematic dissociation of political philosophy from the wider activity of political science has not
gone unnoticed. Gunnell, in Between Philosophy and Politics, for example, expresses concern with the “alienation”
of political theory from substantive political problems.8
In Reappraising Political Theory, Ball suggests that political
philosophy develop some of the “sensibilities of those
among our fellow political enquirers who are conventionally classified as ‘empirical’ political scientists.” 9 In Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, Dryzek observes a “nearuniversal tendency among political theorists to treat
empirical reality in terms of a few stylized facts, rather
than attending seriously to the findings of empirical political science.” 10
Kelly suggests that, if political theory is to continue to
command interest and respect within the discipline, “it
does more to re-engage with political science,” which it
can do “by challenging the terms of much that goes on in
political science.” In so doing, political theory could provide a support structure for what political scientists do by
conceptual clarification and theory construction, and would
act to clarify and challenge the normative dimensions of
the theories and questions that political scientists work
with.11 At the same time, political scientists should take
more notice of the concepts and theories developed by
political philosophers. Indeed, Shapiro’s cited observations are more than a critique of political theory’s navelgazing. While he condemns the theorists for seeing
themselves engaged “in a specialized activity distinct from
the rest of political science,” his is as much an assault on
triteness and triviality in empirical political science as it is
on the narcissism of political theory.12
These overviews may seem exaggerated, but we would
agree that they are largely accurate. There are many pressures which drive sub-disciplines away from mutual
engagement, from the internal organization of academic
departments to increasing journal specialization to certain research accounting and funding procedures. Whatever the causes, the diagnosis is clear enough; to move
towards tentative prescriptions, we need to address a range
of problems that arise from this large-scale disjunction.
The specific case of the linking of democratic theory and
research into political parties is just one such problem,
though (as we hope to show) one of real significance.
Among the various modes of non-communication
between political philosophers and political scientists, our
22 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
of interest (as opposed to affection) and political (as
opposed to religious) principles are typical of the modern
world: “Parties from principle, especially abstract speculative principle, are known only to modern times and are,
perhaps, the most extraordinary and unaccountable phenomenon that has yet appeared in human affairs.” 15 At
best, however, Hume accepted parties only as an unpleasant consequence of free government. Edmund Burke was
the first to see that see that parties had a positive and
necessary use for democracy. In Thoughts on the Cause of
the Present Discontent (1770) he made what has subsequently been described as “the first argument in the
history of political philosophy for the respectability, not
merely the necessity, of parties.” 16
Over the course of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, political philosophy gradually came to terms with
the continued institutionalization of political parties and
their de facto inevitability as permanent elements of the
political system (though strong anti-party sentiments continued to permeate many theories of government and
democracy). The reality of the political party received a
final and decisive push with the advent of mass democracy
and the introduction of universal suffrage. As the size of
the democratic polity increased with the consolidation of
large-scale nation-states, direct links between the state and
the individual became increasingly unrealistic, a fact which
further legitimized the status of parties as intermediary
institutions between individual citizens and the state. More
or less contemporaneous with this development was the
shift in the dominant meaning of democracy; in the late
1700s Madison dismissed democracy, understood as
Athenian-style direct democracy, in favour of republican
government. In just over 100 years, Madison’s republicanism was well on the path to becoming itself the dominant
meaning of democracy.
Until at least the early twentieth century, as the works
of major scholars of political parties such as Ostrogorski,
Michels, and Weber demonstrate, the empirical study of
political parties remained intimately related to democratic
theory.17 To be sure, Ostrogorski and Michels in particular were primarily concerned with democracy within parties, and the undemocratic and oligarchic tendencies of
bureaucratic mass parties in particular, and not with democracy as a political system based upon competition between
parties. However, their theoretical and empirical analyses
of the functioning of political parties are clearly related to
the theory of democracy. Ostrogorski’s solution to what
he saw as the suffocating internal discipline of mass parties, i.e., to create a polity without permanent parties,
underlines how he sought to reconcile liberalism with the
idea of popular sovereignty, thus addressing a fundamental concern that pervaded much of the nineteenth century. Michels implied that parties should be seen as obstacles
to, or the very antithesis of, democracy, at least to the
extent that the “iron law of oligarchy” should be seen also
concern here centers on the meaning and interpretation
of “democracy.” We do not argue that theory and empirical work on a range of democratic institutions have not
been mutually engaged—they have, in various ways. But
this work, it is fair to say, focuses much more on the
“hardware” of democracy rather than the “software” of
mediating institutions like political parties. For example,
Lijphart’s consensus and majoritarian models, Dahl’s
account of the constitutive features of polyarchy, Guinier’s discussion of electoral rules, and Mansbridge’s rethinking of representation engage with characteristics and
trajectories of a range of background institutions—
electoral systems, electoral and other rights, executive
accountability, the accountability of individual members
of Congress, and so on.13 Such authors clearly engage
with democratic institutions to help to generate theoretical insights. Notwithstanding such efforts, engagement
between work on democratic theory and political parties
specifically has remained exceptional.
From that perspective, and with specific reference to
work in democratic theory and on political parties, a key
challenge for political theorists lies in fostering more critical conceptual engagement among scholars of political
parties and the elucidation of the implicit normative
assumptions underlying many of their approaches. Democratic theorists, at their best, problematise democracy,
drawing out shifting and competing meanings. Some of
this work may involve uncomfortable implications for the
place of parties in democratic politics, today and in the
future. However, when addressing empirical reality and
advancing practical solutions for the improvement of the
quality of democracy, democratic theorists should be less
reluctant to acknowledge the reality (and indeed the potential) of the political party and to incorporate the empirical
findings of party scholars.
Party scholars, on the other hand, when addressing normative and empirical issues of democracy, could benefit
from developing a greater sensitivity to the broader significance of the place and role of political parties in modern
democracy, and a greater awareness of the conceptual and
theoretical dimensions underlying democracy. We will pick
up a range of such issues in what follows.
Back to the Future?
Both democratic theorists and party scholars could find
inspiration in the great thinkers of the past, as the two
particular ‘schools’ have not always been disconnected.
Indeed, until the mid-twentieth century it was often precisely through the concept of democracy that normative
political theory and empirical political science were closely
linked. In the eighteenth century, Hume was the first
among the major political philosophers to take up the
subject of parties.14 In his essay Of Parties in General (1742)
he observed that parties founded on some real difference
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 23
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
to apply to the organization of the state itself. Weberian
analysis, on the other hand, suggests that strong and responsible political leadership may be necessary for the healthy
functioning of democracy, principally because it serves to
prevent the politicization of an unaccountable bureaucracy. On this view, a lack of democracy within parties is
not necessarily consequential for democracy at the system
level because, as Sartori would later put it, “democracy on
a large scale is not the sum of many little democracies.” 18
The Mysterious Absence:
Contemporary Democratic Theory
and Parties
䡬
So, the deep linkage of party (and partisan) interests with
philosophical and theoretical reflection on democracy was
strong and varied in a range of classic sources. It was in the
twentieth century—and arguably in the 1960s and 1970s
in particular, as the behavioural revolution in political science advanced while normative political theorizing suffered something of a crisis of identity and relevance—that
the study of democratic theory and of political parties
separated and diverged. Empirical and institutional work
on democracy was still sometimes combined with theory
construction and conjecture, as we have seen. But parties
specifically tended to be bypassed by democratic theorists,
and those scholars specializing in political parties tended
to do so quite separately from the concerns of democratic
theorists. In this section we briefly offer support for our
view that this separation is real. In the next section, we
explore the more significant question about why this separation has occurred and been sustained.
Arguably it was Schumpeter in the 1940s who most
influentially reconciled parties with democracy, by defending a minimal conception of democracy in which the circulation of party elites in power through elections became
both its essence and justification. In recent years, however,
the theory of democracy has by and large become detached
from analysis of the character and roles of political parties,
despite a few notable exceptions such as Robert Dahl or
Giovanni Sartori, both of whom have published normative studies of democracy as well as empirical studies of
democratic institutions and political parties. As Sartori
observes, however, as scholars of political parties we are
“travelling more and more through the ever-growing jungle of party polities without really knowing where we
started, let alone where we are heading.” 19 Even here,
these authors have often separated out consideration of
parties and issues in democratic theory; Democracy and its
Critics (Dahl) and The Theory of Democracy Revisited (Sartori), arguably their major works of democratic theory
respectively, have little to say about political parties. And
key parts of Dahl’s work have displayed unresolved tensions between his expression of the democratic ideal and
parties and other institutions which he regards as being at
the core of modern democracy or polyarchy.20 One can
criticize these tensions and still applaud the categorycrossing work of Dahl; the tensions themselves point
towards the agenda of work whose relative absence is the
very thing we are bemoaning here.
Schattschneider’s observation that “the political parties
created democracy and that modern democracy is unthinkable save in terms of the parties” 21 has become an oftcited conventional wisdom among party scholars. Parties
have come to be seen as necessary for democracy, even
amidst increasing concern that their actual functioning is
inadequate for a healthy performance of democracy.22
Underlying the debates about the contemporary performance of existing parties and party systems, there are
fundamental disagreements about the meaning of democracy and the role of political parties within it. What that
conception of democracy is, however, remains unclear.
Complaints about the decline of party, the growing disengagement from partisan politics, increasing dissatisfaction with and distrust in parties and politicians, the
weakening of their representational and governmental roles,
and the problems of accountability, responsiveness, and
legitimacy, all rest upon, usually implicit, normative
assumptions concerning what is valuable about democracy and about how democracy should work.23 But with
relatively few exceptions,24 even when these assumptions
are made explicit, they generally are simply stated as selfevident truths, rather than being recognized as contentious choices.25
Just as scholars of political parties tend to disregard the
variety in conceptions of democracy, contemporary democratic theorists generally fail to acknowledge the variety
in functions and types of party. If not ignored altogether,
parties are often at best understood one-dimensionally, as
monolithic entities or mysterious black boxes. In particular in varieties of democratic theory belonging to the strands
of participatory democracy and civic republicanism (including recently prominent strands of deliberative democracy), political parties are conspicuous by their marginality
or absence. Even in theories of democracy that are less
averse in principle to the notion of interest representation
and the existence of intermediary structures, the status
accorded to political parties is quite trivial. Theories of
associative democracy, for example, which argue for voluntary citizen associations as the central institutions of
governance, have little to say about the role of political
parties in democratizing civil society or the state, or the
extent to which self-governing voluntary associations should
replace or complement the activities of political parties.26
In the same vein, the more recent theories of deliberative
democracy, while not necessarily unsympathetic to the
notion of representation, define few, if any, of the linkages
between “representatives” and “constituents” in terms of
party, with parties typically regarded as belonging to the
wrong side of the aggregation-deliberation dichotomy.27
24 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
and new forums and other institutions which may embody
democratic ideals. There are exceptions—Christiano to
some degree, Phillips and Budge for example 40 —but they
are isolated ones. It is something of an irony that in one of
the earliest and most influential articles in the dominant
deliberative democracy strand, Joshua Cohen noted that
“the question is how we can best approximate the deliberative conception. And it is difficult to see how that is
possible in the absence of strong parties, supported with
public resources.” 41 Similarly, Bernard Manin insisted that
parties make an essential contribution to democracy.42 It
is fair to say that the suggestions of these early theorists of
deliberative democracy have largely been ignored since.
More generally, indeed, the implicit understanding of representation in political theory seems to be one in which
representation occurs through the presence or actions of
individual elected politicians conceived largely in isolation from parties or party structures.
The absence of political parties from these domains of
democratic theorizing is quite stark, and is evident in a
range of contemporary democratic theory topics and
debates. Key parts of the literature on “participatory democracy” in the late 1960s to the early 1980s bypassed parties
to look instead at functional and radically decentralized
modes of participation.28 Parties are rarely mentioned in a
prominent exploration of democracy’s “outer and inner
edges.” 29 Fishkin largely sets parties aside from preferred
“deliberative polls” in “the quest for deliberative democracy;” 30 Gutmann and Thompson’s advocacy of a different brand of deliberative democracy is profoundly focused
on principles, and parties do not get a mention.31
Parties play a marginal, and to a degree a suspect, role in
Young’s otherwise extensive examination of the politics of
inclusion and democracy,32 and the same is often true of
general texts that seek to engage democratic theory on a wide
canvas (e.g., works by Beetham and Saward).33 A rich array
of formal and informal institutions and practices bearing
on deliberation are considered in the key essays on deliberative democracy gathered by Fishkin and Laslett,34 but parties barely rate a mention as deliberative, non-deliberative,
or potential deliberative bodies or participants; Christiano
notes the role of parties as potential deliberative bodies, but
they play a strongly subordinate role to principles and more
hardware elements of his discussion of “fundamental issues
in democratic theory.” 35 Similar comments can rightly be
made of other noted democratic theory texts, such as those
by Dryzek, Macedo, and Benhabib, that engage in particular with the dominant deliberative thread in democratic
theory.36 Implicitly, parties are not seen as real or ideal
vehicles of democratic deliberation—a key theme to which
we return in the final section. Muirhead has commented
rightly that “while there are many and varied strains of the
deliberative ideal—from abstract philosophical accounts
like those of Habermas and Rawls to quite practical treatments like those of Gutmann andThompson or Fishkin—in
general, none give an extended role to party or partisanship’.37 Parties likewise are also bypassed, for the most part,
in other leading democratic theory accounts of the ways in
which (it is argued) democracy needs to be reinvented or
reformed, for example in discussions of green democracy 38
and cosmopolitan and transnational democracy.39
Of course this is a selective sample. Nevertheless readers can judge for themselves our basic claim: contemporary democratic theorists rarely consider the necessity, roles,
promise, or democratic character of political parties, and
often simply neglect them. Rather, they focus on an array
of principles, moral dilemmas, institutional hardware and
design, individuals as actors and citizens, “the people,”
Why Democratic Theorists and Party
Scholars Don’t Talk to Each Other
With so many topics and concerns in common—not
least the fundamental health of democracy—why is there
such a divide between democratic theory and the study
of political parties? We have hinted at some reasons; in
this section we approach the issue explicitly and more
systematically. We think that there are at least four key,
and interrelated, characteristics of the different literatures’ approaches to democracy within which the core
reasons can be located; these are referred to as “domains
of difference.” These domains are: (1) dominant epistemology approach, addressing fundamental issues of how we
know what we know; (2) the level of analysis, dealing
with different tendencies to prioritize the focus on certain evident features of polities; (3) definitions of key
terms, above all democracy, and (4) positioning of analyses on issues of substance and procedure. No doubt there
are different ways of carving up fundamental differences
dividing the two literatures concerned. But we hope to
show that these four domains are fundamental. Further,
there are clear relationships between the four domains.
For example, an epistemological approach that prizes normative thinking is more likely to emphasize substance
over procedure (or at least to see procedures in terms of
principled points of substance). Likewise, scholars of political parties will in part emphasize procedures since their
epistemological preferences for empirical approaches induce
scepticism about positing essential substance. These different approaches have deep roots and extensive influence on the focus and style of the different literatures.
These characteristics, as well as the broader nature of the
different approaches, the reasons for them, and their consequences, are schematically represented in table 1.
The first domain of difference concerns the different dominant epistemological approaches of democratic theory and
the study of political parties. Although perhaps less directly
related to the treatment of democracy per se, these positions have an immediate bearing on it, as well as being related
to the other characteristics. Broadly speaking, democratic
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 25
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
Table 1
Democratic Theory (DT) and the Study of Political Parties (PP): Different approaches to
democracy
Domain
of difference
Nature
of difference
Reasons
for difference
Epistemological position
DT: prioritizes normative
approaches
PP: prioritizes empirical
approaches
DT: grounded in a philosophical tradition that favours
deductive and axiomatic
reasoning
PP: grounded in a tradition
of logical positivism/
empiricism that favours
perception and observation
Level of analysis
DT: focuses on macro/
micro level
PP: focuses on meso level
DT: is ‘grand theory’; concerned with the constitutive
features of the system
PP: is ‘middle-range’
theory’; concerned with
processes within the
system
Defining terms
DT: sees ‘democracy’ as
an abstract and changeable idea as well as a contingent practice
PP: sees ‘democracy’ as
contextual and exogenous
to its object of analysis
DT: emerges prior to modern representative government; continued scepticism
of large scale ‘democracy’
on the level of the modern
nation-state
PP: emerges after the
settled conviction that
systems of representative
government equal
‘democracy’
Substance vs. procedure
DT: emphasizes the substantive aspects of ‘democracy’
PP: emphasizes the
procedural aspects of
‘democracy’
DT: uses a currency of
principles (e.g. equality,
freedom) which have a
timeless and moral quality
PP: focuses on how systems operate and how
timeless principles are
actualized
䡬
theory tends to prioritize normative approaches, concentrating on the ideals and fundamental principles of democracy, while the study of political parties tends to prioritize
empirical approaches, focusing primarily on the workings
Consequences
of difference
DT: strength of the argument arises from abstract
reasoning and internal
coherence; the idea is
more important than the
empirical examples; uses
selected and isolated
cases as occasional
illustrations
PP: based on the study of
empirical practice; strength
of the argument arises
from references to concrete external cases; normative assumptions are
absent or implicit
DT: object of analysis
focuses on the wider system and the justification of
states; focuses on constitutions and individual rights
as ‘hardware’ of the
system
PP: object of analysis
focuses on the mediating
structures between the
individual and the state;
focuses on parties as ‘software’ of the system
DT: nostalgia for earlier
conceptions of direct democratic and republican government; inherent
suspicion of intermediary
structures
PP: largely a-historical;
ignores the existence of
competing conceptions of
‘democracy’; operates
within uncontested parameters of ‘democracy’
DT: focuses on (substantive normative dimensions
of) policies
PP: focuses on (procedural
dimensions of) politics
of democratic institutions in actual practice. The main reason for this methodological difference is that democratic
theory largely emerged out of, and remains grounded in, a
philosophical tradition that favours deductive reasoning from
26 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
democracy does “need” parties; partisanship generally is
often seem as something to be overcome, an obstacle to
democratic reasoning,45 and parties can deflect concerns
with the common good (note the clear overlaps with themes
in classic historical contributions, discussed earlier). While
the study of political parties focuses on the intermediary
structures between the individual and the state, the higher
level of generality of democratic theory tends to deflect its
attention from specific institutions, such as political parties, whose operation does not comfortably fit into its
broader intellectual orientation or framework. As a consequence of its level of abstraction democratic theory is
concerned with the whole, not with parts; it takes a resolutely system-level view of its object. This explains some
of its traditional suspicion of political parties, as a party is,
by definition, only part of the whole. Further, because
parties unite people on the basis of competing ideological
principles and opposing interests, they are not by their
very nature geared towards more objective perspectives on
the whole.46
Each of these concerns, in turn, has an impact on how
the fundamental concept at hand, democracy, is defined
and understood in the two literatures. With regard to the
defining terms, therefore, to study democracy means something altogether different for the democratic theorist than
it does for the scholar of political parties. This observation
brings into focus the third domain of difference. For the
democratic theorist, democracy is an abstract and changeable idea as well as a contingent practice. For the scholar
of political parties, on the other hand, democracy is largely
contextual and exogenous to its object of analysis. In order
to understand why this should be the case it is important
to underline the sequence in which democratic theory
and the study of political parties developed in relation to
the establishment of representative government. Democratic theory developed prior to the emergence of modern
representative government. Until surprising recently
democracy meant direct, face-to-face democracy, a meaning stretching back to its Greek origins over 2,500 years
ago. The idea of unmediated, face-to-face politics still hovers in the background as an implicit—and sometimes foregrounded as an explicit—baseline against which to measure
degrees of democracy in different contexts.47 As a consequence, there is a lingering, detectable apprehension about
the broadening of the notion of democracy to the level of
the modern nation state and thus (it is normally assumed)
consigning any notion of more direct, or strongly participative, democracy to the historical dustbin. As Dahl
observes, the large scale of modern nation-states created a
conflict “between the theory and practice of representative democracy and earlier conceptions of democratic and
republican government that were never wholly lost.” 48
The skepticism of democratic theory towards large-scale
democracy is reflected in a certain “polis envy” 49 and a
persistent suspicion of intermediary structures.50
abstract axiomatic principles, while the study of political
parties is rooted in a later tradition of logical positivism that
favours empirical exploration and the verification and falsification of empirically observable evidence.
This means that for the democratic theorist clarifying
and debating the democratic ideal remains more important than (and the necessary precondition for) exploring
actual empirical examples. The primary force of the argument derives from abstract reasoning and internal coherence rather than a correspondence between theoretical
claims and empirical reality (the latter is often more than
just a negligible concern, but not often with specific reference to political parties). Empirical examples serve a
purpose primarily as selective and isolated illustrations of
the argument. To scholars of political parties, on the other
hand, empirical observations are vital to theory building,
whether inductively or deductively conceived, and contentions and claims only hold true to the extent that they
can be supported by empirical evidence. Normative ideas
are often taken to be largely irrelevant—it remains implicit
that we already know what democracy is, and why it is
valuable. From that perspective, arguments about ideal
models of democratic deliberation arising from speculative contract theories (as Cohen’s does, through Rawls, for
example),43 may have points of interest but are unscientific, speculative, and perhaps backward-looking.
For the study of democracy in particular, this means
that the concern of the democratic theorist lies primarily
with the foundations that constitute the democratic polity, while for the student of political parties it lies with the
actual functioning of the institutions within it. This brings
us to the second, and related, domain: the level of analysis. Democratic theory and the study of political parties
see themselves as operating at different levels of generality.
Democratic theory is often grand theory, while the study
of political parties operates largely at the middle-range
level. While democratic theory focuses primarily on the
macro (or system) level and its links to the autonomous
individual at the micro level, the study of political parties
concentrates mainly on the meso level of the political system. Because democratic theory is essentially concerned
with the constitutive features of the democratic state and
their moral justification, it tends to focus its attention on
the broader system. Moreover, modern democratic theory
arises largely from liberal traditions of philosophy. As contractarian sub-traditions of liberal philosophy have been
extremely influential in democratic theory, these have biased
the latter towards the constitution of states rather than the
processes operating within states.44
Democratic theory, therefore, often concentrates on
questions of constitutionalism and individual rights, which
it sees as the important hardware of democracy. Parties are
seen as software and as less basic to democracy in temporal, organizational, deliberative, or normative terms. Democratic theorists, indeed, convey real doubt as to whether
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 27
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
䡬
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
In addition, as we have hinted above, democratic theory
largely emerges out of traditions of thinking about politics which stress individualism, on the one hand, and the
collective (including the collective interest), on the other.
There is little scope for what lies in between that dyad, for
mediating institutions and organizations such as political
parties. In fact, the existence of political parties was fundamentally incompatible with both the liberal democratic
tradition rooted in the resolute individualism of Locke
and the radically communitarian and anti-representative
democratic tradition inspired by Rousseau, both of which
in their different ways are difficult to marry with partisan
institutions, which by their very nature both transcend
individual interests and refute the existence of some sort
of “general will.” 51
The analysis of political parties, by contrast, emerged
only after the notion that systems of representative government are democracy had more or less settled. Studies
of political parties, therefore, tend to be rather a-historical.
They ignore the variety in both historical and contemporary conceptions of democracy and tend to accept elections, and the narrow interpretation of representation
associated with them, as benchmark democratic practice.
Relatedly, they also tend largely to operate within the
uncontested parameters of existing democratic systems
without any systematic questioning of their democratic
quality. While many empirical studies of political parties
and democracy will accept the notion that democracy
belongs to the category of “essentially contested concepts,” the literature is not very good at “making democracy strange,” to use the old anthropological way of
formulating the first necessary step in analysis. Such
approaches can sometimes be seen as committing the “definitional fallacy” 52 namely assuming that a system is democratic simply because it fits a type that is commonly
regarded as being democratic.53
The fourth domain of difference is that of substance
versus procedure. Whereas democratic theory tends to
emphasize the substantive aspects of democracy, the study
of political parties emphasizes the procedural aspects of
democracy. To do political philosophy is to write about
morality, about issues pertaining to rightness and wrongness, which lends itself to theorizing about substance,
not procedures.54 Democratic theory tends to use a currency of fundamental principles such as freedom, equality, and justice, which have a timeless and moral quality.
Detailed empirical examples may be explored, but these
tend to be selected in the light of, and strongly driven by,
principled ideals with deeper roots. The study of political
parties, on the other hand, focuses on how systems operate and concentrates on how these principles are deployed
in a core domain of actual democratic practice. This in
turn means that democratic theory is often influenced by
broader political philosophy tendencies to focus on the
substance of policy rather than on the political process,
since policies can, arguably, be right or wrong, moral or
not, in principle. Policies lend themselves to substantive
normative analysis, allowing political philosophers to stipulate what states should do (or refrain from doing) in
policy terms, selectively ignoring the procedural aspects
of democracy that form the ground on which political
parties operate, thereby almost deliberately detaching itself
from ordinary politics.
Why Democratic Theorists and Party
Scholars Should Talk to Each Other,
and How They Could
There are many good reasons for rectifying the contemporary lack of communication between democratic theorists and scholars of political parties. Political parties occupy
an ambiguous position in modern democracies, which is
in part a product of the tension between their de facto
inevitability as key institutions of modern democracy and
their increasing inability to perform the representative functions that legitimized their emergence and that are widely
seen as essential to the quality of democracy. The centrality of political parties can be demonstrated empirically by
the fact that they are firmly rooted in the established western democracies, and have rapidly acquired relevance in
the more recently established democracies which have
emerged out of what Huntington has called the “third
wave,” 55 to the point that it is difficult even to conceive of
a contemporary democratic polity without political parties. However, the failure of the empirical study of parties
to take questions of democratic theory to heart, and to
identify the relationship between normative and institutional prescriptions (difficult as it may be to unite the two
paradigms) is a cause for serious concern, particularly given
the important challenges faced by modern democracy.
Modern democracy, as Hardin puts it either “cannot
entail massive citizen participation or it is irrelevant to
actual practice in modern politics.” 56 Modern democracy
thus depends on mediation, and therefore requires mediators. Democratic theorists need to take on board much
more fully the mediating software—above all and despite
their many challenges, parties—at the meso level of polities. It is here that pristine conceptions and principles are
modified and acted out. In other words, it is crucial to
incorporate these mediating structures and linkage mechanisms into democratic theory, and it seems equally evident that it is precisely through the agency of party that
state and society can be interlinked. However inadequately they may do it, parties gather and bundle disparate preferences and interests and attempt to articulate
collective visions out of varied and diverse particularities.
Democratic theorists often propose new mediating
structures—deliberative bodies, participative budgeting,
and so on—but leap too blithely over the existing, if troubled, core mediating devices, namely parties.
28 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
Table 2
Core Concerns and Overlapping Interests of Democratic Theorists (DTs) and Party
Scholars (PPs)
DTs
PPs
A1. The value and justification of democracy rooted in
equality r parties as vehicles of equality
A2. Hierarchical structures of political parties and
electoral representation r realization of political
equality
B2. Electoral and party systems/party organization r
impact of institutional structures on the patterns of
democratic deliberation
C2. Centralized and nation-based organization of major
parties r effect of mechanisms of direct
participation on democratic quality
D2. Party systems and types of party organization r
effect of electoral strategies/party system
cartelization on capacity for inclusion
B1. The conditions for ideal democratic deliberation r
parties as deliberative bodies
C1. Decentralisation and subsidiarity to deepen
democracy/increase participation r local party
organizations as empowering institutions
D1. Need for the inclusion of new voices and interests
(including the ‘politics of presence’) r ‘open party’
their internal structures, their incentives to foster procedural equality in governance institutions, and their policy
programs for addressing wider social inequalities affecting
citizens’ sense of political efficacy and participation rates,
are all relatively neglected but critical parts of such discussions. Party scholars could gain from attempting to pinpoint the extent to which different parties and party system
configurations realize the democratic ideal of equality in
practice. This might take the form of renewed, theorydriven attention to the extent of openness and inclusion
of party members in internal structures. It may further
involve investigation of the commitments of parties to
democracy and the support of the democratic process;
contra Downs,58 do parties have an incentive to deepen or
bolster system-wide democratic practice, or are they in
fact vote-winning machines for whom “democracy” is one
more piece of handy rhetoric?
We return to B, deliberation, shortly, for reasons we
shall make clear.
With regard to C, participation, decentralizing tendencies within democratic theory—oriented towards getting
power closer to the people—might engage much more
fully the local-national nexus in party systems and structures, and ask, for example, to what extent decentralized
parties might act as a surprisingly subversive vehicle for
disrupting the resolutely national (and therefore highly
indirect and often distant) focus of democratic politics.
Democratic theorists might also reflect on the role of parties in linking the local with the national, or on empowering the people through the agency of party in the
democratization of decision-making structures and governing processes at the level of the nation-state. And indeed,
since cosmopolitans and greens within democratic theory
have been concerned to explore democratization in the
international arena, links between parties in different coun-
Both theories of liberal democracy and deliberative
democracy offer some potential to extend and to reconnect in this respect, as neither is in principle averse to the
notions of representation and mediation. However, further progress would require a deeper appreciation and analysis of the place and functions of parties as the principal
mediators in the democratic system. Even arguments for
new mediating or representative institutions that might
afford a deeper realization of democratic norms in practice need to deal with the issue of whether they can or
should supplement or replace party-based processes.
What are some of the key areas in which this renewed
engagement should occur? Consider a snapshot of selected
core concerns of democratic theorists and party scholars
respectively:
Each of the items in the left column of table 2 can be
seen as democratic theory demands on democracy, and a
set of areas in which democracy might be extended or
deepened. They reflect the widespread conviction in democratic theory that the process of democratization is always
unfinished, and that democracy is always an imperfectly
realized ideal. Each of the items in the right column, deriving largely from the study of parties and party systems,
can be seen as either constraints on the supply of democracy or vehicles through which the demands might in part
be met. Both columns also include suggestions how both
fields might take on board and engage more directly with
each others’ concerns.
With regard to A, equality, democratic theorists could
gain by considering how, and to what extent, parties, in
present or transformed configurations, can act as vehicles
for the democratic ideal of equality. Discussions of equality lie at the heart of justifications of democracy,57 but
these are often individualized and decontextualized discussions. The capacities of parties to promote equality in
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 29
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
䡬
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
tries, as well as the organization of international parties,
ought to be explored. Party scholars might take less for
granted the national basis of democracy and ask, for example, to what extent the dominance of national party organizations underpins the persistence of a minimal democratic
politics and undermines a more diverse, local and even
direct or participatory democratic politics. They might
also further explore how the increased use of mechanisms
of direct democracy, both inside and outside party channels, for decision-making and candidate selection impact
on democratic ideals for deepening democracy.
For D, inclusion, democratic theorists’ concerns about
facilitating the representation of new and marginalized interests in democracies could focus less on general institutional
fixes (such as quotas for women) or exotic imports and creations (citizens juries, for example), and more on the democratic potential of provocative ideas like the “open party”—a
party in which its grassroots members, and perhaps also supporters more broadly, are responsible for setting political
and policy goals. In other words, they could engage more
fully in a discussion on how a deeper realization of democratic inclusiveness might be achieved through a modification or transformation of the existing representative
institutions rather than ignoring the party-based process
or tacitly assuming that it is best replaced by other
structures. Students of parties, on the other hand, could fruitfully consider the extent to which parties fail to prioritize
the inclusion of concerns of the marginalized in their
search for electoral pre-eminence and government office,
and how in turn they may unwittingly act as brakes on the
deepening of democracy. Do parties lack a democracysupporting incentive to build long-term capacity as
opposed to maximizing short-term gain? On the level of
the party system, they could examine the extent to which
the formation of “cartel parties” has encouraged the exclusion or effective marginalization of certain interests and
thus undermined a more inclusive democratic politics, and
explore possibilities to counteract current trends towards
less inclusiveness.59
In all of these areas, and others, each camp has much to
learn—or perhaps more to the point, much to be provoked by—in the different orientation of the other one.
So, democratic theorists need to engage more, for example, with the constraints and opportunities which the realities of parties and party systems embody with respect to
the realization of core democratic ideals. And party scholars need to engage more with the demandingness, restlessness, and changeability of those ideals, as well as with
difficult issues of how far empirical realities offer a sufficient realization of democratic ideals.
Clearly the four areas are closely related. Participation
is not the same as inclusion but the demand for one can
often be a demand for the other. Inclusion might involve
issues about citizenship, raising questions about the boundaries of the political community and who is to be included
in the equality concern. Deliberation is not necessarily a
basis of, or a producer of, equality, but issues of equal
access to deliberative forums are crucial to the claims of
deliberative theorists. We lay the issues out here as we do
for clarity’s sake.
Of course, it is one thing to call for more engagement,
and point towards how it might be done. It is tougher
actually to do the work. So let us try to put this partly
right by spelling out for illustrative purposes what it might
mean to follow our own injunction for our second democratic demand B, deliberation. We do not have space to
be much more than indicative in so doing.
Scholars of political parties have largely ignored the
“deliberative turn” in democratic theory. And theorists of
deliberative democracy have largely ignored political parties. Even when they recognize the limited contribution
deliberation can make to democratic politics and governance, democratic theorists still do not discuss parties.60
This may be because theorists see parties as part of the
problem of political disaffection and voter ignorance, and
not part of a potential solution. Or because the deliberative ideal has roots in thinking oriented to the general
interest, roots which influence their preference for certain
alternative devices—citizens’ juries and deliberative polls
for example—and steer them away from suspect partisan
institutions like parties (and thus, according to Budge’s
critique, taking “the politics out of politics.”) 61
But what if both party scholars and democratic theorists took up Cohen’s early challenge to explore parties as
vehicles for deliberative democracy? Deliberation, theorists argue, can produce more informed preferences and
enhance legitimacy, although the ultimate purpose of
deliberation—the education and development of citizens, the forging of a broad consensus, etc.—has a real
impact on the sites and mechanisms of deliberative democracy. Consider first parties themselves as sites of deliberation. We need to accept, of course, that parties are
partisan, but that need not mean narrowly partisan. Parties have to sell a general interest vision to voters. And,
especially in an era where relatively fixed class roots of
party ideologies are loosening, there is arguably more
scope for deliberation over alternative party visions, programmes, and policies. Parties could be umbrellas for
positive deliberation over alternative proposals, all still
within the broad ideological “frame” of the party. There
may be scope to increase party memberships (in steep
decline in many countries) if genuine opportunities to
deliberate over policy are seen to be available.62 Carefully
managed, rebranding a party as committed to internal
openness and transparency through deliberative processes may carry strategic benefits—there is no need to
deny that parties are driven, at least in part, by voteseeking objectives. Internal deliberative forums need not
be non-partisan; deliberation that engages partisan stakeholders can also be effective.63
30 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
Analysts could also look at decentralist and consultative
mechanisms already present in party organization, exploring and perhaps deepening democratic deliberation on
the back of them (with potential benefits in terms of identification, legitimation, and even strategic advantage). Such
mechanisms could include bottom-up policy-making,
degrees of local party autonomy, party primary elections
and other participative modes of candidate selection, and
party conferences. Further, there is little reason why morefavoured deliberative mechanisms, such as deliberative polls,
could not be deployed within party debates.
Next, consider parties as potential promoters of societal
deliberation. Party competition clearly fosters societal deliberation, through the media and otherwise—observers
might analyze the quality and extent of this deliberation,
and how parties do (and might) contribute to both. Could
parties take part in policy and candidate debates more
often and more prominently—perhaps even to their strategic advantage? Could they, in this light, sponsor citizen’s
juries or consensus conferences, rather than the more narrow focus groups that are often more favoured by parties?
Even more broadly, what of the different incentive structures inherent in different electoral systems for promoting
inter-party and diffuse societal deliberation? Perhaps the
shift to cartel parties, ironically enough, could foster deliberation, since the latter is sometimes easier to engender in
more elite contexts.64
Observers might pay closer attention to deliberation
between parties in legislatures. To what extent are parties
vehicles for deliberation as well as representation in that
context? And how can the potential complementary nature
of these two roles be enhanced? Further, at a time when
environmental and other issues are leading us to question
the very idea of domestic policy, deliberation’s capacity to
work across borders and contexts may be enhanced by
parties engaging for example with sister parties in other
countries through policy deliberation. More generally, the
value of party-fostered diffuse and episodic societal deliberation, not confined to one specific mechanism or device,
has been under explored.
In these brief comments there is a range of hypotheses,
born of looking past the mutual disregard that is the core
topic of this article. Refining and exploring these hypotheses would require new orientations for both democratic
theorists and party scholars. The former would need, for
example, to engage with parties as unavoidable, if flawed,
vehicles of policy aggregation and political representation;
to recognize deliberation’s limits; to work with institutional constraints; and to recognize the grey zone between
particular and general interests. The latter would need, for
example, to accept that democracy is inevitably a normative notion and take on board the power of the deliberative ideal; to recognize the potential of deliberative devices
as supplementing and potentially improving party legitimacy and procedures; and to recognize the importance of
critical questioning of party contributions to the quality
of democracy, and deliberation. By such routes, new ways
for scholars to address the widespread disaffection with
politics in general, and parties and politicians in particular, may be opened up. And that would be significant for
the relevance and utility of political science.
Conclusion
If it is true, as Bryce argued at the beginning of the twentieth century, that modern representative democracy cannot function without political parties, current developments
indicating that parties are losing their capacity to act as
agents of representation have far-reaching implications for
the nature of democracy.65 In order to address the fundamental tension between the centrality of parties and their
marginalization in an area quintessential to any modern
democracy, both normative theories of democracy and
empirical studies of political parties are of vital importance. In particular when faced with the challenges of
consolidating more recently established democracies, resolving problems arising from the changing nature of parties
in the established democracies, or addressing the democratic deficit of the European Union and other transnational organizations, it is imperative that empirical
observations can take guidance from normative theories
and that normative claims are grounded in empirical reality. For that reason, the literatures on political parties and
democratic theory should engage more frequently, substantially, and imaginatively with one another. In this article, we have outlined several of the reasons why the two
strands might have parted ways and sketched various ways
in which they could possibly re-engage with one another.
It is only when they do that we can try to make sense of
the place of parties in contemporary democracy and,
indeed, of the nature of modern democracy itself and its
potential futures.
Notes
1 See, for example, Pharr and Putnam 2000.
2 Van Biezen and Kopecký 2007.
3 American National Election Studies show, for example, that in the late 1950s approximately 70 per cent
of the American public felt they could trust government to do the right thing, or that politicians cared
what people think; see Dalton 2004. By 2004, these
figures had dropped to 46.5 per cent trusting the
federal government to do the right thing always or
most of the time, and only 34.3 agreeing that politicians cared what people think (2004 ANES).
4 A recent Eurobarometer study (2003, 59.1), for
example, revealed that parties were the least trusted
of all institutions on which opinions were sought,
with an overall balance of trust of ⫺59 per cent (i.e.
only 16 per cent of respondents trusting them and
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 31
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
䡬
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
75 per cent distrusting them). The next least trusted
institution were big companies (⫺28 per cent); trade
unions recorded a balance of trust of ⫺13 percent,
the EU ⫹6, the UN ⫹12, the police ⫹39, and the
army ⫹42 per cent; Eurobarometer 2003, 59.1.
On the public images of parties, see Dalton and
Weldon 2005.
Shapiro 2002, 597.
Kelly 2006, 47.
Gunnell 1986.
Ball 1995, 60.
Dryzek 2000, 26.
Kelly 2006, 52.
Shapiro 2002, 596. See also Green and Shapiro
1994.
Lijphart 1999; Dahl 1989; Guinier 1995; Mansbridge 2003.
Sartori 1976, ch. 1.
Hume, quoted in Scarrow 2002, 35.
Mansfield, quoted in Scarrow 2002, 37.
Ostrogorski 1902; Michels 1962 [1911]; Weber
1946 [1918].
Sartori 1965, 124.
Sartori 1976, 24.
See the argument in Saward 2001.
Schattschneider 1942, 1.
This seeming incompatibility between the perceived
necessity of parties, on the one hand, and their
representative inadequacy, on the other, is indicative
of a changing conception of political parties and
democracy. More particularly, it reflects an ideational transformation of political parties away from
the voluntary private associations which perform
public roles and occupy government positions, to
the party as a special type of public utility or public
good for democracy; Van Biezen 2004.
Daalder 2002, 54.
A noticeable exception is Katz 1997, who links the
questions and issues raised by normative democratic
theory to the empirical analysis of elections and electoral systems. Other significant exceptions include Katz
and Mair 1995, who analyze various models of party
organization in relation to the underlying conceptions of democracy. See also Pomper 1992.
Katz 2006, for example, shows how various strands
of popular sovereignty and liberal theories of democracy and competitive party systems contain widely
divergent assumptions with regard to a range of
issues, including the ideal number of parties, the
cohesiveness of parties, their goal orientation, the
internal constraints on the party leadership, or the
relationship between parties and social cleavages.
See for example Hirst 1994. A compelling account of
a highly decentralized democracy based on servicedelivery through voluntary associations, Hirst’s approach
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
32 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
leaves major gaps in terms of where persisting national
parliamentary and party politics may fit. His schema
clearly allows for them in a federated structure, but
they are left largely undiscussed.
Johnson 2006, 48.
See for example Pateman 1970, Bachrach 1967, and
Barber 1984. MacPherson’s advocacy of a Soviet-style
pyramidal party structure was an exception of sorts,
but was based largely on a rejection of empirical realities of existing political parties; MacPherson 1977.
Shapiro and Hacker-Cordon 1999.
Fishkin 1991; Fishkin and Luskin 2000.
Gutmann and Thompson 1996.
Young 2000.
Beetham 1999; Saward 1998.
Fishkin and Laslett 2003.
Christiano 1996.
Dryzek 2000; Macedo 1999; Benhabib 1996.
Muirhead 2006, 715; see also Budge 2000.
Dobson 1996; Dryzek 2000; Eckersley 2004.
Held 1995; Dryzek 1999.
Christiano 1996; Phillips 1995; Budge 1996, 2000.
Cohen 1989, 32.
Manin 1987, 357.
See Saward 2000.
Some theorists have expressed frustration at how
general normative prescriptions are discussed in
isolation from their institutional implications or
embodiment (e.g. Smith 2000).
Muirhead 2006.
Debate about the often blurred distinction between
theory and ideology raises a further issue. One can
argue that normative political theories are not as
different from party ideologies as their progenitors
often imply. Such theories can be seen as particularly
sophisticated versions of partisan ideological arguments, expressed in a different idiom but belonging
ultimately to the same genus.
Barber 1984.
Dahl 1989, 30.
Fishkin 1991, 119 n.31, attributes this term to
Bruce Ackerman.
There are varied suggestions in contemporary democratic theory that proximate or face-to-face politics is
superior to mediated or distant connections. Although the language of “authenticity” is often
treated with scepticism in their writings, Fishkin and
Luskin’s (2000) account of the deliberative poll,
Dryzek’s (2000) account of localism and ecology,
and Phillips’s (1995) work on the ‘politics of presence’ all display something of this tendency.
Or, as Daalder argues, the source of the rejection of
party can be found in two bodies of thought. On
the one hand, there were the defenders of the traditional political order “who saw in the rise of party an
|
|
䡬
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
unwanted invasion of the terrain of the state, which
as the guardian of long-term transcendental interests
threatened to fall victim to private interests of a
short-term nature.” On the other hand, there were
the defenders of the sovereign and free individual,
“who opposed what they regarded as they tyranny of
party, which would do away with freedom of individual action and thought for the sake of collectivist
organizations led by irresponsible elites”; Daalder
2002, 41.
Holden 1974.
See the discussion of this and related issues in Skinner 1973.
For a good example of the tensions between substance and procedure in recent democratic theory
building—and the perceived need to defend oneself
against charges of “proceduralism”—see Gutmann
and Thompson 2003.
Huntington 1991.
Hardin 1999, 169.
Equality above all other values is invoked in philosophical discussions of democracy’s value. See Dahl
1989, Saward 1998, and Beetham 1999.
Downs 1956.
Inter-party relations in the era of the cartel party,
according to Katz and Mair 1995, are characterized
by a pattern of inter-party collusion rather than
competition, whereby the main parties work together and take advantage of the resources of the
state to ensure their collective survival, making it
difficult for newcomers to enter the system and
challenge the status quo.
See Shapiro 1999; Walzer 1999.
Budge 2000.
See, for example, Mair and van Biezen 2001.
Hendriks, Dryzek, and Hunold 2007.
On elitist tendencies in a focus on deliberation, see
Offe 1997.
Bryce 1921, 119.
Biezen, Ingrid van. 2004. Political parties as public
utilities. Party Politics 10 (6): 701–22.
Biezen, Ingrid van, and Petr Kopecký. 2007. The state
and the parties: Public funding, public regulation and
party patronage in contemporary democracies. Party
Politics 13 (2): 235–54.
Bryce, James. 1921. Modern Democracies. New York:
Macmillan.
Budge, Ian. 1996. The New Challenge of Direct Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
_. 2000. Deliberative democracy versus direct
democracy—plus political parties! In Democratic
Innovation: Deliberation, Representation and Association, ed. Michael Saward. London: Routledge.
Christiano, Thomas. 1996. The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 1989. Deliberation and democratic
legitimacy. In The Good Polity, ed. A. Hamlin and P.
Pettit. Oxford: Blackwell.
Daalder, Hans. 2002. Parties: Denied, dismissed or
redundant? A critique. In Political Parties: Old Concepts and New Challenges, ed. Richard Gunther, José
Ramón Montero, and Juan J. Linz. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Dahl, Robert A. 1989. Democracy and Its Critics. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Dalton, Russell J. 2004. Democratic Challenges, Democratic Choices: The Erosion of Political Support in Advanced Industrial Democracies. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Dalton, Russell J., and Steven Weldon. 2005. Public
images of political parties: A necessary evil? West
European Politics 28 (5): 931–51.
Dobson, Andrew. 1996. Representative democracy and
the environment., In Democracy and the Environment,
ed. W.M. Lafferty and J. Meadowcroft. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar.
Downs, Anthony. 1956. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row.
Dryzek, John S. 1999. Transnational democracy. Journal
of Political Philosophy 7: 30–51.
_. 2000. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Eckersley, Robyn. 2004. The Green State: Rethinking
Democracy and Sovereignty. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Fishkin, James S. 1991. Democracy and Deliberation:
New Directions for Democratic Reform. New Haven
and London: Yale University Press.
Fishkin, James, and Peter Laslett, eds. 2003. Debating
Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
Fishkin, James S., and Robert C. Luskin. 2000. The
quest for deliberative democracy. In Democratic
References
American National Election Studies (ANES). 2004.
www.electionstudies.org
Bachrach, Peter. 1967. The Theory of Democratic Elitism.
Boston: Little, Brown.
Ball, Terence. 1995. Reappraising Political Theory: Revisionist Studies in the History of Political Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Barber, Benjamin. 1984. Strong Democracy. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Beetham, David. 1999. Democracy and Human Rights.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Benhabib, Seyla, ed. 1996. Democracy and Difference.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 33
䡬
䡬
|
|
䡬
Articles
䡬
|
Democratic Theorists and Party Scholars
Innovation: Deliberation, Representation and Association, ed. Michael Saward. London: Routledge.
Green, Donald, and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of
Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications
in Political Science. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Guinier, Lani. 1995. The Tyranny of the Majority. New
York: Free Press.
Gunnell, John G. 1986. Between Philosophy and Politics:
The Alienation of Political Theory. Amherst: University
of Massachusetts Press.
Gutmann, Amy, and Denis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, MA, and London:
Belknap Press.
_. 2003. Deliberative democracy beyond process.
In Debating Deliberative Democracy, ed. James
Fishkin and Peter Laslett. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishing.
Hardin, Russell. 1999. Liberalism, Constitutionalism and
Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Held, David. 1995. Democracy and the Global Order.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hendriks, Carolyn M., John S. Dryzek, and Christian
Hunold. 2007. Turning up the heat: Partisanship in
deliberative innovation. Political Studies 55 (2):
362–83.
Hirst, Paul. 1994. Associative Democracy. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Holden, Barry. 1974. The Nature of Democracy. London:
Thomas Nelson.
Huntington, Samuel P. 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.
Johnson, James. 2006. Political parties and deliberative
democracy? In Handbook of Party Politics, ed.
Richard S. Katz and William Crotty. London:
Sage.
Katz, Richard S. 1997. Democracy and Elections. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
_. 2006. Party in democratic theory. In Handbook
of Party Politics, ed. Richard S. Katz and William
Crotty. London: Sage.
Katz, Richard S., and Peter Mair. 1995. Changing models of party organization and party democracy: The
emergence of the cartel party. Party Politics 1 (1):
5–28.
Kelly, Paul. 2006. Political theory: The state of the art.
Politics 26 (1): 47–53.
Lijphart, Arend. 1999. Patterns of Democracy. New
Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Macedo, Stephen, ed. 1999. Deliberative Politics. New
York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mair, Peter, and Ingrid van Biezen. 2001. Party membership in twenty European democracies, 1980–2000.
Party Politics 7 (1): 5–21.
Manin, Bernard. 1987. On legitimacy and political
deliberation. Political Theory 15 (3): 338–68.
MacPherson, C.B. 1977. The Life and Times of Liberal
Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mansbridge, Jane. 2003. Rethinking representation.
American Political Science Review 97 (4): 515–28.
Michels, Robert. 1962 [1915, 1911]. Political Parties:
A Sociological Study of the Oligarchical Tendencies of
Modern Democracy Trans. Eden and Cedar Paul.
Reprint. New York: Free Press.
Muirhead, Russell. 2006. A defense of party spirit.
Perspectives on Politics 4 (4): 713–27.
Offe, Claus. 1997. Micro-aspects of democratic theory:
What makes for the deliberative competence of
citizens? In Democracy’s Victory and Crisis, ed.
A. Hadeniu. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ostrogorski, Mosei. 1902. Democracy and the Organization of Political Parties. 2 vols. New York: Macmillan.
Pateman, Carole. 1970. Participation and Democratic
Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pharr, Susan J., and Robert D. Putnam, eds. 2000.
Disaffected Democracies: What’s Troubling the Trilateral
Countries? Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Phillips, Anne. 1995. The Politics of Presence. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pomper, Gerald M. 1992. Concepts of political parties.
Journal of Theoretical Politics 4: 143–59.
Sartori, Giovanni. 1965. Democratic Theory. New York:
Praeger.
_. 1987. The Theory of Democracy Revisited.
Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers.
_. 1976. Parties and Party Systems: A Framework for
Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Saward, Michael. 1998. The Terms of Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
_. 2000. Less than meets the eye: Democratic legitimacy and deliberative theory. In Democratic Innovation: Deliberation, Representation and Association, ed.
M. Saward. London: Routledge.
_. 2001. Making democratic connections: Political
equality, deliberation and direct democracy. Acta
Politica 36 (Winter): 361–79.
Scarrow, Susan E., ed. 2002. Perspectives on Political
Parties: Classic Readings. New York and Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Schattschneider, E.E. 1942. Party Government. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Shapiro, Ian. 1999. Enough of deliberation: Politics is
about interests and power. In Deliberative Politics, ed.
S. Macedo. New York and Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
_. 2002. Problems, methods, and theories in the
study of politics, or What is wrong with political
science and what to do about it. Political Theory 30
(4): 596–619.
34 Perspectives on Politics
䡬
|
|
䡬
Shapiro, Ian, and Casiano Hacker-Cordon, eds. 1999.
Democracy’s Edges. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Skinner, Quentin. 1973. The empirical theorists of
democracy and their critics. Political Theory 1 (3):
287–306.
Smith, Graham. 2000. Toward deliberative institutions.
In Democratic Innovation: Deliberation, Representation
and Association, ed. Michael Saward. London:
Routledge.
Walzer, Michael. 1999. Deliberation, and what else? In
Deliberative Politics, ed. S. Macedo. New York and
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Weber, Max. 1946 [1918]. Politics as a vocation. In
From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, trans. and ed.
H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Young, Iris Marion. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
䡬
March 2008 | Vol. 6/No. 1 35
䡬