Draft paper -- Please do not quote without permission from the author The Bureaucratic Politics Model and Poliheuristic Theory Dr Klaus Brummer University of Erlangen-Nuremberg Institute for Political Science Kochstr. 4 91054 Erlangen Germany Phone: +49 – 9131 – 85 22 004 Email: [email protected] Paper prepared for British International Studies Association (BISA) Annual Conference 2009 14-16 December 2009 Leicester, UK Abstract This paper aims at enhancing the explanatory power of the bureaucratic politics model (BPM) and contributing to the discussion on theoretical integration in Foreign Policy Analysis (FPA). It commences with a brief outline of the model’s three core propositions (stand-sit proposition, bargaining proposition, resultants proposition). The paper moves on to discuss the BPM’s major deficiencies. They relate to a lack of clarity concerning the formation of the actors’ policy preferences and a limited specification of the conditions under which unintended compromise solutions, that is, resultants, occur. The paper puts forward suggestions as to how to overcome those shortcomings. Concerning the formation of the actors’ policy preferences, the paper argues that the BPM’s stand-sit proposition could be integrated into the framework of poliheuristic theory in the form of a “noncompensatory bureaucratic loss aversion variable.” This variable leads to the elimination of options that are unacceptable for the actor’s organization (in addition to the ones that are unacceptable for the actor due to political concerns as already suggested by poliheuristic theory). As to resultants, the paper specifies the conditions under which results are more likely than resultants. However, the paper argues those conditions seldom materialize. Therefore, resultants are the likely outcomes of bargaining processes among bureaucratic actors with diverging policy preferences and different power potentials. Future research might want to systematically account for the impact of domestic (e.g., coalition governments) and international (e.g., multilateral security institutions) constraints on the decision-making processes along the lines of the revised BPM. Introduction Ever since the publication of Graham Allison’s “Essence of Decision” and Morton Halperin’s “Bureaucratic Politics and Foreign Policy” in the first half of the 1970s, the bureaucratic politics model (BPM)1 has been one of the most frequently applied frameworks in Foreign Policy Analysis (FPA).2 At the same time, it is safe to say that the model has also been among the most heavily contested concepts in the field.3 At first glance, the parsimony of the BPM is truly appealing. The model focuses on bargaining processes between bureaucratic actors within government. Actors are driven by the interests of their respective organizations. Decisions result from the interaction of the actors’ competing policy preferences. At its core, the BPM puts forward three propositions. One relates to the sources of the actors’ policy preferences (stand-sit proposition), another to the type of interaction among the actors during the decision-making processes (bargaining proposition), and still another to the character of decisions that are eventually adopted (resultant proposition). However, as will be discussed in greater detail below, the BPM is not true to itself. Its core propositions are plagued by ambiguity. Most importantly, the BPM neither specifies the interplay between structural/bureaucratic influences and agent-specific motivations on the formation of actors’ policy preferences nor the conditions under which resultants (instead of results) arise as outcomes of the decision-making process. This paper aims at augmenting the explanatory power of the BPM by clarifying its core propositions. It proceeds as follows. The first section outlines the BPM’s three core propositions.4 Building on the criticism that the model has received, the second section puts forward suggestions as to how the BPM’s core propositions could be specified. In the concluding section, the paper points to domestic and international constraints that might impede the impact of bureaucratic politics on decision-making and that therefore should also be incorporated in an analytical framework that centers on the BPM. 1. Core Propositions of the Bureaucratic Politics Model The first core proposition of the BPM is neatly summarized in the well-known aphorism “Where you stand depends on where you sit” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 307).5 Hence, an actor’s bureaucratic position strongly impacts his6 policy preferences. The “mission” of the bureaucratic actors is to pursue and realize the interests of their organization. In the second edition of “Essence of Decision,” Allison explicated what exactly the aphorism meant in his understanding – and what it did not. Allison argued that the word “depend” does not indicate a deterministic relationship between an actor’s bureaucratic position and his policy stance. Rather, it “merely” suggests that an actor’s position strongly affects his preferences. As a result, an actor’s stance can be more or less reliably inferred from his position. The “long 1 Although Allison also refers to the BPM as “governmental politics model,” this paper sticks to the original term, which is also the one most commonly used in the literature. 2 Allison (1971); Allison and Zelikow (²1999); Halperin (1974); also Allison and Halperin (1972). The model was applied, for instance, in Valenta (1980); Smith (1985); Holland (1999); Jäger and Oppermann (2006); Fuhrmann and Early (2008). 3 See, for instance, Holsti (1972); Krasner (1972); Art (1973); Ball (1974); Freedman (1976); Caldwell (1977); Steiner (1977); Smith (1980, 1989); Rosati (1981); Hollis and Smith (1986); Bendor and Hammond (1992); Welch (1992); Rhodes (1994); Kaarbo (1998); Bernstein (2000). 4 Rosati (1981: 236-238) proposes four partially different core propositions. 5 The aphorism is also known as “Miles’s Law,” a senior civil servant who, according to Welch (1992: 120), was the first to formulate it. 6 For the sake of readability, “his” refers to both male and female actors. 2 version” of the aphorism now reads “where one stands is influenced, most often influenced strongly, by where one sits. Knowledge of the organizational seat at the table yields significant clues about a likely stand” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 307).7 This qualification to the stand-sit proposition means that factors other than the bureaucratic position are also seen as exerting at least some influence on the formation of the actors’ policy preferences. This seems particularly true regarding agent-specific factors. Indeed, Allison and Zelikow (²1999: 298) argue that “each person comes to his or her position with baggage in tow. The bags include sensitivities to certain issues, commitments to various projects, and personal standing with and debts to groups in society… [P]eculiarities of human beings remain an irreducible part of the mix.” In a similar vein, Halperin (1974: 16) emphasizes the importance of “personal experiences, intellectual baggage, and psychological needs” – in addition to the actor’s bureaucratic position. Hence, although bureaucratic imperatives have substantial influence on an actor’s policy stance, individual policy preferences have to be taken into account as well. The implication of this “human factor” is that if individual X follows individual Y in a certain bureaucratic position, it does not necessarily mean that X also advances the same policy preferences as Y did. However, as discussed in greater detail below, the BPM remains silent about how bureaucratic and individual factors interact with respect to the preference formation of actors. Turning to its second core proposition, the BPM argues that the competing preferences of bureaucratic actors clash in political bargaining processes. It is “the pulling and hauling that is politics” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 255) that leads to government decisions. Bureaucratic actors seek to maintain or even increase the influence of their organization, to realize the organization’s mission, and to safeguard the organization’s capabilities to pursue its mission (Halperin 1974: 24-62). Differences in interests between organizations lead to conflicting problem perceptions among bureaucratic actors. What is more, even if actors share a common understanding of the policy issue in question, it is very likely that their subsequent suggestions concerning the appropriate ways and means to tackle the issue diverge (Holland 1999: 221). Either way, following from differences in organizational interests, conflicting policy preferences among actors are all but inevitable: Both by character and in practice, most players ‘represent’ a department or agency along with the interests and constituencies their organization serves. Because their preferences and beliefs are related to the different organizations they represent, their analyses yield conflicting recommendations (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 256). Bureaucratic actors that are involved in the bargaining processes not only differ concerning their policy preferences but also with respect to power. Generally speaking, power is understood as “effective influence on government decisions and actions” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 300).8 It comprises three elements: advantages of actors in bargaining processes, an actor’s will and ability to use those advantages, and the perception of the other players involved in the process of those aforementioned points. Power is distributed unevenly between the actors. Hence, an actor’s power is relative, since it is always measured against the power of other actors. There are several sources for bargaining advantages of actors. They include “formal authority and responsibility (stemming from positions)” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 300). In other words, power is inherent in bureaucratic positions and hence in structure. The position determines what an actor can do and must do. It could privilege or discriminate against an actor. 7 Already in 1972, in a joint article with Morton Halperin, Allison qualifies the stand-sit proposition. Allison and Halperin (1972: 44) argued that “priorities and perceptions are shaped by positions (emphasis added).” 8 See Kaarbo (1998: 74-77) for a critical engagement with the BPM’s/Allison’s concept of power. 3 However, an actor’s impact on results, and hence his power in bargaining processes, is not exclusively determined by structural factors, that is, by the power that flows from his bureaucratic position. Again, actor-related factors come to the fore (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 300). They include an actor’s expertise and his ability to control the flow of information. Both aspects enable actors to define problems or options for action. Another quality that enhances an actor’s power is his access to other actors with bargaining advantages, provided he has also the ability to persuade those actors of his own policy stance.9 The inclusion of an individual dimension of power, in addition to structural sources of power, is important. If power was anchored exclusively in bureaucratic structures, then the representative of one institution, that is, the representative of the institution with the most structural power, would prevail in each and every bargaining process. This would be the case independent from the respective representatives of the institutions involved in the process. Other institutions would see their policy preferences realized only if their structural power had been augmented beforehand. By contrast, if the individual capabilities of the institutions’ representatives are also taken into account, the potential outcomes of the bargaining processes open up considerably. It is not pre-determined from the outset whose preferences will prevail. Hence, independent from structural changes, institutions that are less powerful in structural terms but that do have outstanding representatives may also succeed in bargaining processes. Put differently, it is not a given that X is equally likely to prevail or fail in the bargaining processes with other key actors like his predecessor Y did (as a purely structural argument would suggest). The third core proposition concerns the nature of the outcomes of the bargaining processes among bureaucratic actors. Here, the BPM argues that those outcomes are best described as “resultants” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 294). Resultants are unintended compromise solutions that no actor originally pursued as a solution for the problem under scrutiny.10 Depending on their structural and individual power, all actors contribute to a small or large extent to the compromises. Such solutions appear to be the “logical” outcome, since the actors involved in the bargaining processes not only advance competing policy preferences but usually are also not powerful enough to impose their will (and hence the one of their organization) on the other actors. Overall, this means that the decisions of a government are not the result of a rational decision-making process but of “compromise, conflict, and confusion of officials with diverse interests and unequal influence” (Allison and Zelikow ²1999: 295). 2. Revising the Bureaucratic Politics Model The three core propositions of the BPM as described above have been called into question from various angles. The stand-sit proposition has met criticism because of the unclear interaction of structural/bureaucratic and agent-specific factors on the formation of the actors’ policy preferences. The idea of decision-making as bargaining processes between competing actors from different organizations has been questioned because of its overly competitive interpreation of politics. Closely interlinked to the aforementioned point has been criticism of the BPM’s stipulation of unintended compromise solutions as the usual outcome of decision9 Of course, access to other actors could have either individual (e.g., personal bonds) or structural (e.g., ex-officio membership in committees) causes. 10 Despite the “irrational” outcome of the bargaining processes, the actors themselves do act rationally when trying to realize their policy preferences (see Welch 1992: 118; Rhodes 1994: 1-2). However, as stated above, they usually lack the power to achieve this end. 4 making processes, since this would neglect rational outcomes resulting from less competitive decision-making processes. The following paragraphs discuss in turn the criticism that the stand-sit proposition (2.1) and the bargaining and resultant propositions (2.2) have received and put forward suggestions as to how the propositions’ deficiencies might be overcome. 2.1 The Formation of Actors’ Policy Preferences At the heart of the BPM lies the stand-sit proposition, that is, the ability to infer an actor’s policy preferences from his bureaucratic position. As mentioned above, this connection is not supposed to be deterministic in a sense that the bureaucratic position is the only factor that influences the actors’ preferences. Rather, the bureaucratic position is one of several determinants, albeit a crucial one. In addition to the bureaucratic position, the model introduces agent-specific factors as having an impact on the actors’ stances. However, the BPM is not clear about how structural and agent-specific factors interact on the formation of the actors’ preferences. The criticism that the stand-sit proposition has received for that reason can be grouped into two categories: “empirical criticism” and “conceptual criticism.” The empirical criticism takes the discussion of the Cuban Missile Crisis in Allison’s “Essence of Decision” as its starting point. The objection is that the policy positions of some actors (their stand) cannot be explained by their bureaucratic positions (their sit) (e.g., Ball 1974: 77). Whether this criticism holds true for the Cuban Missile Crisis is secondary to this paper’s discussion. What has to be taken into account, though, are cues put forward in the discussion of the Cuban Missile Crisis with respect to certain groups of bureaucratic actors for whom the stand-sit proposition supposedly cannot hold true. According to Krasner, there are actors that cannot be assigned to certain bureaucratic institutions. As a result, they also do not pursue a certain bureaucratic interest. “Decisionmakers (…) often do not stand where they sit. Sometimes, they are not sitting anywhere” (Krasner 1972: 165). Krasner refers to actors, such as former secretaries, who are brought into decision-making processes on an ad-hoc basis. One could reply, however, that former secretaries might very well have the interest of “their” former ministry in mind when giving advice to acting decision-makers. A second group of actors – actors that Krasner refers to as not having bureaucratic interests of their own – consists of those whose loyalties rest primarily, or even solely, with the top decision-maker, in the case of the U.S. president. Such a stance could be due to relational ties (e.g., John F. Kennedy and Robert Kennedy) or the result of a person being appointed by the president, leading to a sense of gratitude and/or dependence. In his discussion of the decision-making process in the context of the American hostage rescue mission in Iran in 1980, Smith (1985: 17-18) refers to the latter group as “presidential supporters.” Clearly, relational ties between a nation’s top decision-makers are rare exceptions. Presidential supporters, in turn, might very well have a bureaucratic position to defend, namely the one of the president. Following Smith, presidential supporters strive for maintaining or augmenting the president’s reputation and ability to act. Hence, bureaucratic interests could also be identified for this group. In short, the empirical criticism, according to which several groups of actors do not have bureaucratic interests, seems not fully convincing. 5 Figure 1: The Formation of the Actors’ Policy Preferences According to the BPM Agent’s bureaucratic position organizational interests (“sit”) strong influence Agent’s policy preference (“stand”) some influence Agent’s individual preferences and interests peculiarities of individual actors connection between structural and agentbased influences on the formation of actors’ policy preferences not specified The “conceptual criticism” on the stand-sit proposition is more instructive. It centers on the mentioned opening of the BPM for non-structural/ non-bureaucratic explanatory variables. This opening is perceived as overloading the model. By including agent-specific factors as potential explanations for an actor’s policy preferences, the clearly-defined stand-sit proposition has gotten frayed (see figure 1). For instance, Bernstein (2000: 140) argues that the BPM tossed into the mix for the governmental ‘players’ a medley of other causal factors, reaching well beyond the standing/sitting connection, to explain their behavior: their personalities, backgrounds, personal loyalties, and other matters. Thus, the seeming near-parsimony (…) dissolved (…) into a grab bag of influences (…). If an individual’s representing a particular bureaucracy (standing/sitting) was not key, what influence was crucial in explaining an actor’s willingness to compromise in particular ways but not in others, and to create certain alliances but not others in the pulling and hauling? In a similar vein, Bendor and Hammond (1992: 318) complain that the model “incorporates so many variables that it is an analytical kitchen sink. Nothing of any possible relevance appears to be excluded (…). [A] model that includes everything explains nothing.” Welch (1992: 121) even gets the impression that “at points Allison seems actively to deny any theoretical relationship between a player’s position and his or her preferences or perceptions.” What those authors rightly point out is that the influence of bureaucracy, and hence of structure, was reduced as a result of the qualification of the stand-sit proposition. At the same time, it remains unclear when and to what extent the influence of the bureaucracy comes into play. Ultimately, one could even ponder over whether bureaucracy exerts any impact at all on the actors’ policy preferences. The problem with the fundamental criticism of the stand-sit propositions discussed so far is that it leaves open the question as to how one can grasp the influence of bureaucratic structures on actors. Two answers can be found in the literature. One might be labeled “simplification,” the other “specification.” The former makes the case for the severing of the connection between bureaucratic structures and agency. To explain foreign policy decisions, the focus should rest on either structures or agency. However, as only agents can make decisions but not structures,11 simplification is more or less synonymous with dismissing bureaucratic structures altogether as an explanatory variable in favor of a focus on agents. For instance, Art (1972: 472-473) complains that the BPM is not clear about the circumstances and policy issues in which the bureaucratic position is supposed to strongly influence, if not 11 See the discussion of the agent-structure problem below. 6 determine, an actor’s policy stance. Moreover, he points out that the stand-sit proposition has received several qualifications, above all by the incorporation of the actors’ individual characteristics. The way forward proposed by Art (1972: 470, 473-476) is to dismiss the impact of bureaucratic structures and focus instead on agents, above all on their mind-sets. Jervis (1976: 26-28) makes a similar point. He argues that the generalizations inferred from the BPM with respect to expected policy outcomes must not take into account the values and beliefs of individual actors. Otherwise, the impact of bureaucratic structures – which Jervis fundamentally calls into question – gets lost. Conversely, “specification” calls for a more clear-cut elaboration of the connection between agents and structures. The work of Hollis and Smith points in this direction. Like Art, Hollis and Smith (1986: 270) hold the opinion that the individual actors involved in the decisionmaking processes play a much larger role than the BPM gives them credit for. Accordingly, their aim is to strengthen the role of persons and personality within the BPM. In addition, they want to overcome the notion of actors as being “mouthpieces or puppets of the bureaucracies that send them into the fray” (Hollis and Smith 1986: 273). Contrary to Art, however, Hollis and Smith do not advocate the renouncement of structural factors in favor of individual ones. Instead, they call for an integration of structure and agency (Hollis and Smith 1986: 285). In their opinion, an actor’s bureaucratic position influences the actor’s preferences and interests but it does not determine them. In this sense, the actor’s preferences are no longer seen as being exogenously given (by the bureaucratic structures). Rather, the endogenous formation of preferences is also possible. Against this backdrop, they reformulate the stand-sit aphorism to “[w]here you stand would depend both on where you sit and on how you think” (Hollis and Smith 1986: 273). Following Hollis and Smith, both bureaucratic/structural and individual/agency-based factors are important and must therefore be taken into consideration. Stern and Verbeek make a similar point. They argue that the reduction of the stand-sit proposition to solely structural aspects is a fundamental misconception about the BPM. A more accurate understanding of the proposition “entails the recognition that factors other than organizational affiliation have an impact on officials’ preference formation” (Stern and Verbeek 1998: 206). In short, an actor’s policy preference cannot fully be explained by referring to his bureaucratic position alone. Agent-specific factors also play a role. At the same time, an actor’s preference cannot fully be explained by referring solely to his individual perceptions, mind-set, etc. Bureaucratic factors also impact the actor’s policy stance. Therefore, an explanation of actors’ policy preferences must account for both structural influences and agent-specific motivations. Two questions arise from the aforementioned: first, how to grasp agent-specific motivations? Second, how to integrate agent-specific motivations and structural influences on the formation of actors’ preferences? Poliheuristic theory (e.g., Mintz 2003, 2004) gives cues with respect to the first question. The theory integrates elements of cognitive and rational choice theories of decision-making. It conceptualizes decision-making as a two-stage process. During the first stage, the cognitive elements dominate. Actors use heuristics that help them simplify complex policy questions. The theory assumes that leaders overvalue losses. Hence, they are driven by the desire to avoid them. Actors reduce the set of options available to them by applying a “noncompensatory principle.” The principle stresses that potential benefits of a choice could not compensate for potential losses. Therefore, actors eliminate options that would yield unacceptable returns, that is, considerable domestic political costs or losses. There are several ways as to how this “noncompensatory political loss aversion variable” (Mintz 2004: 9) could be operationalized (e.g., threat to leader’s political power; drop in popularity; prospects of electoral defeat; intra-party rivalry; external challenge to the regime). During the second 7 stage, the rational elements of the theory come to the fore. Once all politically unacceptable choices are eliminated, actors choose “their” option by making recourse to analytic processing. The selection criteria are risk-minimization and benefit-maximization. Mintz (2004: 6-7) summarizes the gist of poliheuristic theory as follows: Poliheuristic theory postulates that when making decisions, policy makers employ a two-stage decision process consisting of (a) rejecting alternatives that are unacceptable to the policy maker on a critical dimension or dimensions and (b) selecting and alternative from the subset of remaining alternatives while maximizing benefits and minimizing risks. Hence, poliheuristic theory highlights that both cognitive and rational factors have to be taken into account if one seeks to understand the formation of actors’ policy preferences. The theory also shows how cognitive and rational factors are interconnected. However, turning to the second question that was raised above, the theory does not account for structural influences, and hence for the core of the stand-sit proposition. Yet, a structural dimension could be introduced into the poliheuristic theory framework by adding a “noncompensatory bureaucratic loss aversion variable.” Accordingly, during the first stage, actors not only eliminate options that might be politically costly to them.12 In addition, they eliminate options that seem unacceptable to their organization. Operationalizations of this variable include a loss of the organization’s political influence, a decrease in budget and/or personnel, a possible lowering of morale, or a challenge to the organization’s autonomy or essence (see Hudson 2007: 76-80). Integrating the insights of the BPM and poliheuristic theory not only contributes to overcoming the former’s problems in accounting in a systematic fashion for both structural and actor-specific influences concerning the formation of actors’ policy preferences. What is more, it also enhances the applicability of poliheuristic theory, since it seems that the theory runs into difficulties if applied to parliamentary systems. Indeed, poliheuristic theory’s claim to be a decision-making theory appears accurate primarily (or maybe only) if there is just one crucial decision-maker who is “calling the shots”, such as the president in the case of the United States. Conversely, in parliamentary systems of government the decision of one governmental actor (even if it is the decision of the head of government) is rarely identical with the ultimate decision of the government as a whole. Thus, in parliamentary systems it might be more accurate to conceive of poliheuristic theory as a viable tool to identify the policy preferences of key actors which are involved the decision-making process on the issue under scrutiny. Obviously, after having identified the preferences of the key actors (by using poliheuristic theory in its original form or expanded version as presented above) one needs to explain how the more often than not competing preferences of the individual governmental actors13 are aggregated into the collective decision of the government. Here, the BPM’s second and third core propositions concerning bargaining processes among governmental actors that lead to unintended compromise solutions seem to fit quite nicely. In sum, building on the work of Hollis and Smith, who argue for a stronger emphasis to be placed on agents and their idiosyncrasies, and poliheuristic theory, which shows the interaction of cognitive and rational factors, the formation of actors’ preferences is conceptualized as a two-stage process. During the first stage, options that are unacceptable to the actor from both a political and a bureaucratic/organizational viewpoint are eliminated. 12 The political emphasis of poliheuristic theory (e.g., DeRouen 2003: 12-13) also fits nicely with the BPM’s focus on politics (Kaarbo 1998: 71-72) during the bargaining processes. 13 Certain characteristics of parliamentary systems, such as coalition governments and the allocation of “mirror departments” (such as foreign affairs and defense) to different coalition partners, appear conducive for the emergence of competing policy preferences within the executive. 8 During the second stage, actors choose rationally their preferred option from the remaining alternatives. Their selection is guided by two aims: risk minimization and benefit maximization. Hence, the bureaucratic position (the “sit”) does not determine an actor’s policy stance (the “stand”). However, the bureaucratic position exerts a significant (selective) influence on the formation of the actors’ policy preferences. Figure 2 shows the model of preference formation that integrates poliheuristic theory and the BPM’s stand-sit proposition. Figure 2: A Two-Stage Process of the Formation of Policy Preferences Stage 1: Cognitive dimension Stage 2: Rational dimension actors’ values and perceptions actors’ intentions and goals heuristic shortcuts dominate analytic processing dominates leads to elimination of leads to the selection of “the” policy option to be pursued; selection based on riskminimization and benefitmaximization unacceptable options: * noncompensatory political loss aversion: elimination of options that are politically not acceptable for the actors Actor’s policy preference (“stand”) * noncompensatory bureaucratic loss aversion: elimination of options that are not acceptable for the actors’ organization (the actors’ “sit”) 2.2 Decision-Making Processes and Their Outcomes Before turning to the decision-making process, a brief excursion to the debate on the agencystructure problem is in order. The debate shows how structure and agency are interconnected. It starts from the assumption that human agents and social structures cannot exist separately from each other. This is why a separate analysis of structure and agents is impossible. Structures are assigned an enabling as well as a constraining effect on agents insofar as they “open up certain possibilities of action at the same time as they restrict or deny others” (Giddens 1984: 173-174). It must be emphasized, though, that structures do not impose a certain behavior on actors. What they do is to establish a certain framework. How actors fill this framework with life is up to them. Referring to the state as structure, Wight (2006: 189) argues that “[i]f the state has agency it can only be accessed through the agency of individuals.” The proposition that it is individuals who do the acting and not structures holds true for structures other than the state as well, including bureaucracies. What is more, agents and agents’ decisions feed back on structures (as well as on the agents themselves), thereby possibly altering the structures. The paper will return to this point below. What follows from the debate on the agency-structure problem is the necessity to analyze both structures and agents in the course of the decision-making processes. Hence, this calls for the development of analytical concepts that take both agents and structures into account (Wight 2006: 293). The BPM does just that, since the bargaining processes among key actors is strongly influenced by structural factors as well as the actors’ individual skills. After actors have formed their policy preferences (as outlined above), interagency decision-making – and hence the “pulling and hauling” – commences. The BPM conceptualizes the interaction of actors as a bargaining process. The actors that are involved in the process differ not only with respect to their policy preferences but also with respect to power. There are two sources for the latter: one is structural, the other agent-specific. Concerning structure, differences result 9 from an unequal distribution of power among the ministries. The discussion of the agentstructure problem showed that bureaucratic structures not only constrain actors but also enable them by generating options in the interaction with other actors. Indeed, structure is one of the major sources of actors’ power. Concerning agents, differences in the actors’ proficiencies and skills augment or decrease their leverage in the bargaining processes. However, with no actor being sufficiently powerful enough to impose his will on the others, bargaining processes frequently end with a “resultant,” that is, an unintended compromise solution that no actor had pursued as his policy preference. Allison and Halperin (1972: 7071) remark that “[i]n most cases, the policy and action decisions were compromises (emphasis added).” Both the competitive (bargaining) notion of politics that characterizes the interaction among the actors during the decision-making processes and the idea of unintended compromise solutions, as the usual outcomes of those processes, were called into question by Freedman. Freedman (1976: 436-437) argues that Allison based his models on a false dichotomy between logic on the one hand and politics on the other hand (“logic/ politics dichotomy”). Indeed, he contends that it is this false dichotomy that made the distinction between the rational actor model (RAM) and the BPM possible in the first place. According to Freedman, “logic” is connected with the RAM, in which shared values and rational decision-making dominate the policymaking process. Conversely, “politics” represents the core of the BPM and points to conflicting values and clashing interests. Hence, logic and politics are presented as mutually exclusive avenues of policymaking. Freedman contests this dichotomy. He argues that both logic and politics, and hence both rational and political components, are present in policymaking processes. In his point of view, they are “two ends of a continuum. At one end all is rationality; at the other all is politics” (Freedman 1976: 441). Accordingly, the distinction of the policymaking process as either rational or political is wrong. Policymaking, or politics in general, is not synonymous with competition and conflict (Freedman 1976: 445). What is more, since the BPM’s notion of politics is incorrect, its proposition concerning the outcomes of policymaking (or decision-making) processes must be equally faulty. Put differently, if policymaking processes are not only about bargaining and competition but also allow for rational action based on shared values, then the outcomes of those processes are not necessarily unintended compromise solutions, that is, resultants. Freedman’s criticism could be countered insofar as the BPM does not preclude results as outcomes of policymaking (or decision-making) processes. As mentioned above, Allison and Halperin expect resultants to emerge “in most cases.” Hence, in other (and fewer) cases, decision-making leads to (rational) results. In short, the BPM is open to both resultants and results. In this sense, Stern and Verbeek (1998: 207) argue that the explanatory power of the BPM is not limited to resultants. Rather, due to the model’s focus on the interaction of agents from different organizations, it is also useful when trying to account for decision-making processes in which one actor prevails. However, the model’s lopsided application primarily to the political system of the United States has obscured this strength of the BPM, according to Stern and Verbeek (1998: 207). Art (1973) criticizes another aspect of the BPM’s resultants proposition, namely the latter’s allegedly unintended character. He posits that compromise solutions might very well be consistent with the intentions of the actors. Indeed, Art argues that actors already enter bargaining processes with the expectation of compromises as their outcome. More often than not, the distribution of power between the actors involved in the process leaves no other option. Although actors differ in power, usually none is powerful enough to simply impose his will on the others. Therefore, if a solution is to be reached at all, the price for arriving there is compromise. Since actors are aware of this necessity from the outset, they incorporate 10 the need for compromise solutions in their initial bargaining positions. Art (1973: 471) summarizes his argument as follows: In our system, the cost of consensus is compromise; but the participants know that before they begin their policy battles. (…) The point, then, is that the compromise that results from the pulling and hauling was deliberately intended by the participants. The exact nature of the compromise that results may be unintended or unforeseen, but not the initial intent to achieve some sort of a compromise (emphasis in the original). In this paper, “politics” and the character of the results of the bargaining processes among bureaucratic actors are conceptualized as follows. In line with Freedman, “politics” is not synonymous with clashing interests. Rational policymaking is possible. Therefore, the outcomes of the decision-making processes are not necessarily unintended compromise solutions. Hence, not only resultants but also results (understood as the realization of one actor’s – or all actors’ – initial policy preference) are possible outcomes of the decisionmaking process. Results seem possible under several circumstances. First, one actor is so powerful that he simply imposes his will on the other actors involved in the bargaining process. Although individual skills are important, a strong structural power base that emanates from the actor’s bureaucratic position is a necessary condition in this context. Second, the actors’ policy preferences are congruent. Given the impact of structure on the preference formation of actors, this would presuppose that the preferences/aims of the ministries are also more or less identical. However, since ministries not only look at a policy issue from different angles but also are first and foremost interested in maintaining or augmenting their power (usually to the detriment of the others), the likelihood of this option appears limited. Third, the demands that the different structures impose on the actors are not mutually exclusive. Therefore, actors could make use of their discretion (within the boundaries set by the political and bureaucratic constraints in stage one of the policy preference formation process) and carve out a solution that corresponds to the preferences of all actors, and hence ministries, involved. This demands openness on the part of the individual actors for “arguing,” that is, openness to being persuaded by the better argument, even if this runs counter to one’s own beliefs. As Thomas Risse (2000: 9) puts it: In arguing mode, actors try to convince each other to change their causal or principled beliefs in order to reach a reasoned consensus about validity claims. And (…) they are themselves prepared to be persuaded. Successful arguing means that the ‘better argument’ carries the day, while one’s (material) bargaining power becomes less relevant. Yet the scope for arguing within bargaining processes as devised by the BPM (and particularly the revised stand-sit proposition) seems limited. During those processes, actors could make use of their discretion to adapt their preferences within the range of choices as set by stage one of the policy preference formation process. However, if an actor leaves the range of choices established by political and organizational imperatives, this would impose high costs either for his political career or for his organization (which, in turn, would very likely also impact the actor’s political prospects). This is why rational actors are unlikely to venture such a move. Overall, then, arguing might lead to minor adjustments of policy preferences but not to fundamental changes.14 In short, results are possible. However, they are not very likely, since the preconditions necessary for them to emerge as an outcome of the decision-making process are difficult to 14 Since the idea of arguing implies much deeper changes, this is surely a very narrow notion of the concept. 11 materialize. Hence, following Freedman, decision-making (or policymaking) processes are located in a continuum whose one end is “pure” rationality (where actors share values and results are the outcomes of the process) and whose other end is “pure” politics (where actors fight for influence/power and resultants are the outcomes). Since the actors involved in the decision-making process are bureaucrats with different policy preferences and power potential, most processes should be located far closer to the “political end” of the continuum. Therefore, the outcomes of those processes are far more likely to be resultants. This holds particularly true for non-presidential political systems with coalition governments (Stern and Verbeek 1998: 207). Resultant or result: Bureaucratic bargaining develops into a decision (as the output of the decision-making/bargaining process).15 The decision sees its practical implementation in foreign policy actions. Actions, in turn, trigger outcomes, and it is those outcomes that feed back on structures and agents (figure 3). As the debate on the agent-structure problem pointed out, those feedback processes could cause changes in the bureaucratic structure, for instance with respect to competences or budgets. Since the feedback not only affects structures but also agents (Brighi and Hill 2008: 120), changes in the agents’ perceptions and values or their goals and intentions are also possible. The expectation is that changes on part of the agents are more likely than on part of the more stable structure. In any case, changes in structure and/or agents will affect the policy preferences that actors will pursue in subsequent bargaining processes on the same (or at least similar) issue. Hence, they will also affect future foreign policy decisions.16 Figure 3: Feedback Process Decision-making process Bargaining among bureaucratic actors that are involved in the action-channel with competing policy preferences (“stands”) and different power potentials Decision result or resultant (as outcome of the bargaining/ decisionmaking process) Foreign Policy Action and Outcome implementation of decision and outcome of the decision Feedback (on structure and actors, and hence also on the policy preferences that actors bring to the bargaining processes) 15 Bargaining processes might also end with a decision for inaction or with no decision at all. Although there is no subsequent “practical” implementation in form of actual foreign-policy actions, such (non-)decisions also generate an outcome that feedback on structure and agents. 16 The dynamic component, which results from the incorporation of the factors time and policy outcomes, can be found in a model put forward by Carlsnaes (2008: 97-98). See also Brighi and Hill (2008: 118-126). 12 3. Conclusion The primary aim of this paper was to augment the explanatory power of the BPM by clarifying the model’s three core propositions. The first proposition – the stand-sit proposition – concerns the formation of the bureaucratic actors’ policy preferences. The proposition highlights the strong impact of bureaucratic imperatives on actors’ policy stances. At the same time, the BPM is open to agent-specific motivations as well. However, the model is silent on how structural and agent-specific factors are interrelated. The paper sought to overcome this deficit by introducing a “noncompensatory bureaucratic loss aversion variable” into the framework of poliheuristic theory. This way, structural/bureaucratic as well as agent-specific factors (as well as cognitive and rational elements) are combined in a concept on the formation of actors’ preferences. This integrative effort is in line with Hudson (2007: 165), who proposes integrated frameworks for FPA in general, and Kaarbo (1998: 72), who argues for a combination of the insights of bureaucratic politics with other, more recent perspectives. Poliheuristic theory surely falls into that category. Core propositions two and three relate to the character of the decision-making process and the latter’s outcome respectively. The decision-making process is conceptualized as a political bargaining process among bureaucratic actors (bargaining proposition), and the outcomes of those processes are perceived as resultants, that is, unintended compromise solutions (resultant propositions). Taking up Freedman’s criticism of the BPM, this paper sees the decision-making process as being pursued on a continuum. At one end is full rationality; at the other is pure politics. The paper shows under what conditions the emergence of results based on rational decision-making processes are likely. However, given differences in preferences and power among the bureaucratic actors that are involved in the decision-making process, the latter is significantly more likely to be characterized by bargaining that, in turn, leads to resultants. After having put forward suggestions as to how the BPM’s core propositions could be specified, the next step would be to systematically account for domestic and international constraints that might impact decision-making processes that evolve along the lines described above. Domestic constraints might include the influence of coalition governments, parliaments, parties, the media, and public opinion. One hypothesis would be that parliamentary systems are particularly conducive for bureaucratic politics. For instance, the role of prime minister is considerably weaker compared to that of the U.S. president. What is more, prime ministers more often than not head multiparty coalition governments, with the latter impacting the government’s decision-making in various respects (e.g., Kaarbo 1996; Kaarbo and Beasley 2008). Already those few points suggest that decision-making in parliamentary systems with coalition governments is very likely to be located rather closely at the political end of Freedman’s continuum between logic and politics. This, in turn, means that resultants (instead of results) – and hence one of the hallmarks of the BPM – are likely outcomes of decision-making. International constraints, in turn, include a country’s membership in international institutions. One hypothesis would be that a country’s integration in multilateral security institutions reduces the impact of bureaucratic politics on a country’s decision-making with respect to the deployment of armed forces. Decision-making in such contexts, for instance in the European Union (EU), usually comprises two phases. Phase one is about whether or not a mission should be deployed at all. For member states of the multilateral institution, this means that they have to decide in advance on a position that is to be pursued during multilateral bargaining processes. Specific details of the mission are usually not agreed in this first phase. In phase two, a country has to decide on its actual contribution to a mission. Another round of 13 bureaucratic politics within each participating state begins. In short, there are two rounds of bureaucratic politics: first on the decision on the mission as such, and then on the actual contribution to the mission. Hence, there are two occasions in which ministries could clash. For instance, a foreign ministry could be strongly interested in conducting an international peacekeeping mission (e.g., for diplomatic or humanitarian reasons), including a significant contribution of the country to the mission. Conversely, a ministry of defense could argue against both the mission as such and a strong participation in the mission in particular, for instance due to overstretch or a lack of capabilities. Nonetheless, bureaucratic politics could be less salience in such situations, since a country might be heavily constrained in its decision on whether or not to participate in a mission (phase one) due to peer pressure from fellow member states of the security institution. Consequently, the impact of bureaucratic politics might be stronger in phase two, when ministries wrestle about the actual contribution to a mission. Taking up another point of criticism of the BPM, the impact of those potential domestic and international constraints on the BPM could be formulated for political systems other than the American one. Indeed, the model is patently U.S.-centered, since it was developed with the U.S. (presidential) system of government in mind and also mostly applied to the U.S. system. However, the BPM is claimed as having a much broader explanatory power. The dynamics that the BPM reveals are supposed to be discernable in other systems of government as well.17 Put differently, the BPM claims explanatory power also for non-presidential systems of government. Allison and Halperin (1972: 43) express their hope that the BPM “is sufficiently general to apply to the behavior of most modern governments in industrialized nations.” It is high time to test systematically whether this is actually the case. References Allison, Graham T. (1971): Essence of Decision. Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. New York: Harper Collins. Allison, Graham T. (1980): Comment by Graham T. Allison. In: Studies in Comparative Communism, Vol. 13/4, 327-328. Allison, Graham T., and Morton H. Halperin (1972): Bureaucratic Politics: A Paradigm and Some Policy Implications. In: World Politics, Vol. 24/Supplement: 40-79. Allison, Graham, and Philip Zelikow (²1999): Essence of Decision. Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. New York et al.: Longman. Art, Robert J. (1973): Bureaucratic Politics and American Foreign Policy: A Critique. In: Policy Sciences, Vol. 4/4, 467-490. Ball, Desmond J. (1974): The Blind Men and the Elephant: A Critique of Bureaucratic Politics Theory. In: Australian Outlook, Vol. 28/1, 71-92. Bendor, Jonathan, and Thomas H. Hammond (1992): Rethinking Allison’s Models. American Political Science Review, Vol. 86/2, 301-322. Bernstein, Barton J. (2000): Understanding Decisionmaking, U.S. Foreign Policy, and the Cuban Missile Crisis. A Review Essay. In: International Security, Vol. 25/1, 134-164. Brighi, Elisabetta, and Christopher Hill (2008): Implementation and behaviour. In: Smith, Steve et al. (eds.): Foreign Policy. Theories, Actors, Cases. Oxford: Oxford UP, 117-135. Caldwell, Dan (1977): Bureaucratic Foreign Policy-Making. In: American Behavioral Scientist, Vol. 21/1, 87110. Carlsnaes, Walter (2002): Foreign Policy. In: Carlsnaes, Walter et al. (eds.): Handbook of International Relations. London/Thousand Oaks/New Delhi: Sage, 331-349. 17 Allison and Zelikow (²1999: 256) argue that “[s]tudents of crisis behavior in many governments readily find examples where actions can only be explained by the turmoil or bargaining of internal politics.“ In a similar vein Allison (1980): 327. 14 Carlsnaes, Walter (2008): Actors, structures, and foreign policy analysis. In: Smith, Steve et al. (eds.): Foreign Policy. Theories, Actors, Cases. Oxford: Oxford UP, 85-100. DeRouen, Karl Jr. (2003): The Decision Not to Use Force at Dien Bien Phu: A Poliheuristic Perspective. In: Mintz, Alex (ed.): Integrating Cognitive and Rational Theories of Foreign Policy Decision Making. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 11-28. Freedman, Lawrence (1976): Logic, Politics and Foreign Policy Processes: A Critique of the Bureaucratic Politics Model. In: International Affairs, Vol. 52/3, 434-449. Fuhrmann, Matthew, and Bryan R. Early (2008): Following START. Risk Acceptance and the 1991-1992 Presidential Nuclear Initiatives. In: Foreign Policy Analysis, Vol. 4/1, 21-44. Giddens, Anthony (1984): The Constitution of Society. Outline of the Theory of Structuration. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press. Halperin, Morton H. (with the assistance of Priscilla Clapp and Arnold Kanter) (1974): Bureaucratic Politics and Foreign Policy. Washington, D.C.: Brookings. Holland, Lauren (1999): The U.S. Decision to Launch Operation Desert Storm: A Bureaucratic Politics Analysis. In: Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 25/2, 219-242. Hollis, Martin, and Steve Smith (1986): Roles and reasons in foreign policy decision making. In: British Journal of Political Science, Vol. 16/3, 269-286. Holsti, Ole R. (1972): Book Reviews: Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. In: Western Political Quarterly, Vol. 25/1, 136-140. Hudson, Valerie M. (2007): Foreign Policy Analysis. Classic and Contemporary Theory. Lanham et al.: Rowman and Littlefield. Jäger, Thomas, and Kai Oppermann (2006): Bürokratie- und organisationstheoretische Analysen der Sicherheitspolitik: Vom 11. September zum Irakkrieg. In: Siedschlag, Alexander (ed.): Methoden der sicherheitspolitischen Analyse. Eine Einführung. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag, 105-134. Jervis, Robert (1976): Perception and Misperception in International Politics. Princeton: Princeton UP. Kaarbo, Juliet (1996): Power and Influence in Foreign Policy Decision Making: The Role of Junior Coalition Partners in German and Israeli Foreign Policy. In: International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 40/4, 501-530. Kaarbo, Juliet (1998): Power Politics in Foreign Policy: The Influence of Bureaucratic Minorities. In: European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 4/1, 67-97. Kaarbo, Juliet, and Ryan K. Beasley (2008): Taking It to the Extreme: The Effect of Coalition Cabinets on Foreign Policy. In: Foreign Policy Analysis, Vol. 4/1, 67-81. Krasner, Stephen D. (1972): Are Bureaucracies Important? (Or Allison Wonderland). In: Foreign Policy, No. 7 (Summer), 159-179. Mintz, Alex (ed.) (2003): Integrating Cognitive and Rational Theories of Foreign Policy Decision Making. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Mintz, Alex (2004): How Do Leaders Make Decisions? A Poliheuristic Perspective. In: Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 48/1, 3-13. Rhodes, Edward (1994): Do Bureaucratic Politics Matter? Some Disconfirming Findings from the Case of the U.S. Navy. In: World Politics, Vol. 47/1, 1-41. Risse, Thomas (2000): “Let’s Argue!” Communicative Action in World Politics. In: International Organization, Vol. 54/1, 1-39. Rosati, Jerel A. (1981): Developing a Systematic Decision-Making Framework: Bureaucratic Politics in Perspective. In: World Politics, Vol. 33/3, 234-252. Smith, Steve (1980): Allison and the Cuban Missile Crisis: A Review of the Bureaucratic Politics Model of Foreign Policy Decision-Making. In: Millennium, Vol. 9/1, 21-40. Smith, Steve (1985): Policy Preferences and Bureaucratic Position: The Case of the American Hostage Rescue Mission. In: International Affairs, Vol. 61/1, 9-25. Smith, Steve (1989): Perspectives on the Foreign Policy System: Bureaucratic Politics Approaches. In: Clarke, Michael, and Brian White (eds.): Understanding Foreign Policy. The Foreign Policy Systems Approach. Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 109-134. Steiner, Miriam (1977): The Elusive Essence of Decision. A Critical Comparison of Allison’s and Snyder’s Decision-Making Approaches. In: International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 21/2, 389-422. Stern, Eric, and Bertjan Verbeek (1998): Whither the Study of Governmental Politics in Foreign Policymaking? A Symposium. Introduction. In: Mershon International Studies Review, Vol. 42/2, 205-210. Valenta, Jiri (1980): Czechoslovakia and Afghanistan: Comparative Comments. In: Studies in Comparative Communism, Vol. 13/4, 332-342. Welch, David A. (1992): The Organizational Process and Bureaucratic Politics Paradigms. Retrospect and Prospect. In: International Security, Vol. 17/2, 112-146. Wight, Colin (2006): Agents, Structures and International Relations. Politics as Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. 15
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz