3>7qj tic9 IN THE BEGINNING WAS THE WORD: HEBRAIC INTERTEXTUALITY AND CRITICAL INQUIRY OF AMBROSE BIERCE THESIS Presented to the Graduate Council of the University of North Texas in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS By Rodney L. Streng, B. J. Denton, Texas August, 1990 Rik Streng, Rodney L., In the Beginning Was the Word: Intertextuality and Critical Inquiry of Ambrose (American Literature), August, 1990, This study corroborates Hebraic Master of Arts Bierce. 111 pp., 1 diagram, bibliography, 43 titles. theories that ordinary representation of narrative time as a linear series of "nows" hides the true constitution of time and that it is advantageous for us as readers and critics to consider alternatives to progressive reality and linear discourse in order to comprehend many of Ambrose Bierce's stories, for his discourse is fluid and metonymic and defies explication within traditional of intertextuality encourages western limitless language concepts. considerations The Hebraic theory in textual analysis language is perceived as a creative and dynamic force, not merely mimetic. such it offers a means for reconsideration of fundamental theories concerning the natures of language and time in Bierce's stories. since As TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter I Chapter Chapter II III Postmodern Readings ........................................ Time in the Many Different Worlds Past, Present, Future: of Ambrose Bierce ......................................... Backtracking: Two Languages, Two Heritages ................ 1 16 38 Chapter IV Ambrose Bierce and Traditional Hebraic Intertextuality . . . . . . . 61 Chapter V The Essence of Backtracking and Pressing Onward: Postmodernism and Hebraic Intertextuality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 iii TABLE OF ILLUSTRATIONS, CHARTS, AND DIAGRAMS Diagram 3:1..........................................................50 IV CHAPTER I POSTMODERN READINGS: THE NATURE OF HEBRAIC INTERTEXTUALITY Calling criticism a "religious war" hermeneutics finds its heritage and pointing out that modem in Biblical hermeneutics, Susan declares that modern literary criticism is "a kind of substitute Handelman theology" (xiii). Today critics find themselves in the wake of the overthrow of the "New Critical Gospel of formalism" so prevalent during the 1930s and 1940s (Handelman 179). The "Book of 'Books" is no longer perceived as divine; the critical "Text" has supplanted it. Without absolutes, critics enjoy their freedom to create "a variety of ideologies, sects, and systems whose true believers battle out their quasi-religious wars" xiii). (Handelman What Handelman calls a religious war may stem from a misconception about the nature of narrative and what comprises a text. Barbara Herrnstein Smith points out that as refined as contemporary narrative theory may be, it seems to suffer from what she identifies as "a number of dualistic concepts and of which betrays a lingering strain of models, the continuous generation naive Platonism and the continued appeal to which is both logically dubious and methodologically distracting" Handelman says that rigid (209). structuralism rests on "a Hellenistic dream of logic, order, form, and lucidity," a dream which she says fails to recognize the elusive quality of narrative and the text (180). misconceived. Herrnstein Smith also believes that narrative and the text are She rejects the traditional two-leveled in which a "story" contains the content of a narrative 1 model of narrative, that and a "discourse" 2 communicates that would narrative it. She suggests instead that that model be replaced with one allow narratologists as something other than objects, events, or ideas" (222). conformity narrative as or formal and "functions of these narratologists perceive Her understanding addressed "representations of of any individual specific, discrete To do so would prevent the "expectation of a correspondence anything else" formal properties to regard between (Herrnstein Smith multiple interacting as the rigid and any of the properties 222). Herrnstein conditions" formal what properties of a Smith views other of a narrative of what she terms "multiple interacting conditions" (222). will be later. The misperceptions Herrnstein of narrative Smith could well regarding the nature and text cited by Handelman be the basis of Ambrose Bierce's short stories have remained, for the continuing uncertainty short story technique. to a large extent, critically and That unexplored Bierce's until the past decade indicates the traditional difficulty readers and critics have had in understanding him as a writer. difficulty. narrative, Bierce's stylistics contribute much to this But the impediment of many critics is their dualistic model of that "naive Platonism" Herrnstein "logically dubious and methodologically scrutiny, Bierce's structure. that so aptly distracting" (209). stories do not reflect this dualistic points out as Even under careful concept of narrative His fusion of time and events and his atypical treatment of what are traditionally narrative's Smith called reality and dream prohibit clear assessment of the character, Bierce's at least within "combination of realism structuralist narratology. and romantic more than one critic to despair of ever classifying Thus, extravangance Bierce's stories" we has find led (Woodruff 3 91). He has been placed by some "squarely within" the naturalist tradition (Wiggins 46) and called by others a "precursor of contemporary experimental fiction" (Davidson 20). In this thesis I will study five of Bierce's short stories, "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," "The Death of Halpin Frayser," "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field," "The Man and the Snake," and "A Psychological Shipwreck," and will reach possible interpretations of Bierce's traditionally assigned to them. critical writings other than those I will revise the traditional critical theory and readings of Bierce's short stories by considering intertextuality, a theory of narrative criticism more Hebraic akin to what Herrnstein Smith advocates when she proposes conceiving of narrative as a social transaction. She suggests: that an alternative conception of language views strings of discrete signifiers that represent utterances corresponding not as sets of discrete signifieds, but as verbal responses-that is, as acts which, like any acts, are performed in response to various sets of conditions. These conditions variables consist of all those circumstantial of which every utterance is a function. these conditions are conventionally implied by and psychological Although some of and are, accordingly, inferable from the linguistic form of an utterance, they are not confined to and cannot be reduced "signifieds." to specific "referents" or (222) Herrnstein Smith advocates individual narratives as (actualize, manifest, map, rejecting sets or of any narratological model "surface-discourse-signifiers express) sets of which that views represent underlying-story-signifieds" 4 (222). Instead, narratives should be understood to be a narrator's verbal responses "shaped and constrained by . . . sets of multiple interacting conditions" (Herrustein construct listeners Smith 222). a narrative: or readers "context addressed" and material and to them"; and "such psychological telling the tale and knowledge, are "multiple Hebraic narrative meanings" act" fostering (Handelman xiv). desires, theory relationship expectations, corresponds Traditionally, memories, When the traditional that within a interpretability" that "interpretation opposed to what the Hebrews' Rabbis on the assumption "endless but that interpretation-as divine "particular the narrator's theory of intertextuality, of textual interpretation Thus, the Rabbis maintained inseparable, central interests, mode of textual interpretation. based their theory xiv). as the nature of including (222). Smith's proposed identifies setting," variables as the narrator's motives for and prior experiences" Handelman text "the all the particular Herrnstein Rabbinic She suggests that the following variables (Handelman and text were not only to incarnation-was Christianity proclaimed the that the word, God, had become incarnate in Christ, it claimed to have the "final and of the now 'Old' Testament text" (Handelman xiv). Handelman contends that the very "history of interpretation . . . has been . determined by the schism between Jews issue of proper interpretation and Christians of the text" (xiv). precisely . validating interpretation over the She holds that Christianity eventually divorced itself from Judaism and married with Greek philosophy, establishing itself throughout Western culture (xiv). the Roman Empire to become a foundation of As Handelman explains, "In literary criticism, major modern theorists, from Coleridge and Wordsworth to Arnold, Eliot, and the New 5 Critics, or more recent figures such as Northrop Frye, are heavily indebted to their respective Catholic or Protestant concepts meaning" (xiv). rejected With their deference to Greek thought, Western critics have the validity of Hebraic play in literary of word, logos, text, and criticism. intertextuality and neglected the role it can But Handelman points out that the last century has seen "the fall of Christianity's prestige" and the increasing "entry of the Jews into the full intellectual life of Europe" (xv), both of which introduced variety of questions which previously traditional concerning the had been precluded criticism representing "failures," physical "ruptures," reveal Heidegger's and words narrative text, perceived entitites. "absences" to function mimetically, But such terms infiltrating between language comprise as a system as "discrepancies," literary critical thought awareness of the lack of and the world. Hebraic thought, has never understood language to function mimetically. which questions simply by the foundation upon which and the post-structuralists' mimetic correspondence however, of the rested. Language is traditionally of signs nature a language are thought actually to contain Instead, the the essence of being, and the text is thought to include more than the written word-all experiences correspond to and interact to create the final text. Herrnstein Smith's proposed theory of intertextuality language narrative assert a more theory and intimate Handelman's Rabbinic correspondence between and the world than that of mere representation. the Reader: Affective Stylistics," that unwittingly reflects elements Stanley Fish proposes of Hebraic Oman Thus, both In "Literature a theory intertextuality (25). in of literature To "RON"" 6 understand Hebraic intertextuality further, let us consider some of Stanley Fish's ideas that have come to be known as reader response theory. To answer the question how it is that different readers reach different readings, Fish articulated the theory that readers "make" literature. theory was reactive to Wimsatt and Beardsley's essay on the affective His fallacy, which pointed out the danger of solipsism in attributing meaning to the reader and which instead upheld the text as the generator of meaning (2). Fish wrote "Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics" to articulate his belief that meaning is created by the reader. Fish points out in the 1980 printing of Is There a Text in this Class? that he "would not now subscribe to the tenets put forward" in "Literature in the Reader: which was published in 1970 (Fish 22). Affective Stylistics," But Fish does still struggle to address accusations that the theory is merely solipsistic on the one hand and "a recent turn of the new-critical screw" (7) on the other. My interest in "Literature in the Reader" lies in Fish's insistence that the reader must somehow be a part of the generating of meaning, that the text is not self-sufficient. To explain his theory, Fish constructs the following sentence to analyze: That Judas perished by hanging himself, there is no certainty in Scripture: though in one place it seems to affirm, and by a doubtful word hath given occasion to translate it; yet in another place, in a more punctual description, it maketh it improbable, overthrow it. and seems to (23) I will accompany Fish's analysis of this sentence with my own explanation of how each of his points parallels in some way the theory of Hebraic intertextuality. I 7 Fish begins his explanation of how meaning is determined by stating that this particular sentence about Judas says nothing. saying nothing is one of "progressive decertainizing" Here the strategy of He notes the (Fish 23). range of possibilities in meaning in the phrases "there is no," "doubtful," "certainty," "improbable," perceptions of meaning "seems." Then he traces the shifts in readers' each new phrase. with Fish blames the inefficiency of the statement on its "refusal to yield a declarative statement" (25). ceases to ask the question, "What does this sentence mean?" to ask, "What does this sentence do?" But Fish and instead begins In thus shifting his perception of the nature of an utterance, he finds that the text : . . . is no longer an object, a thing-in-itself, but an event, something And it is that happens to, and with the participation of, the reader. this event, this happening-all of it and not anything that could be said about it or any information one might take away from it-that is, I would argue, the meaning of the sentence. (Fish 25) Fish's statement parallels Hebraic intertextuality in that it allows words to be a dynamic power which can initiate and activate, a creative force. Fish identifies the problem of the sentence's meaning as the "suspension of the reader between the alternatives its syntax momentarily offers" according shift of the reader's perspective on it. (26) and the "What is a problem if the [sentence] is considered as an object, a thing-in-itself, becomes a fact when it is regarded as an occurrence" (Fish 26). Likewise, Hebraic intertexuality allows nothing to remain outside the scope of the text, not readers or their prior experiences, not the written composition, letter, or any of their alterations. All not the syntax, the word, the such elements compose the text, for the 8 of the reading, the action initiated by the text is perceived to be the experience words. To accept the statement as meaningful the statement is attributed a logical meaning. does not necessarily mean that Fish does not require that a sentence be logical in order to have meaning; he allows for juxtaposition instead. Juxtaposition is the position of two objects being side by side or close together, "both of which lead in spite of their differing positions to equal consequences" (Kunst 986). "Here . . . is the 'logic of Handelman explains: metaphor' which Riceour articulated, wherein the logical action takes place in a 'transgression' of ontology" so that juxtaposition can be thought of as the display of something which simultaneously is and is not, existing on the 53). boundary of the same and the different (Handelman displayed in Fish's second example: We see this best "Nor did they not perceive the evil plight" (25) from Milton's Paradise Lost (I, 335). Fish explains that as readers attempt to determine whether they (fallen angels) did or they did not perceive the evil plight, the questions which arise due to the ambiguity of the statement are part of the statement's meaning, even though they take place in readers' minds, not on the page. "Subsequently, we discover that the answer to the question . . . is, 'they did and they didn't"' (Fish 26). He explains that Milton the angels do perceive, or exploits the two senses of the word "perceive": experience, the physical repercussions of their fall, but they do not perceive, or comprehend, the moral repercussions. perceive That the fallen angels do and do not their plight illustrates juxtaposition. element of Hebraic intertextuality, Juxtaposition for it allows is a critical for progressive interpretation. Because intertexuality presents a process, not a product, it relies on an 9 of a contiguous awareness upon juxtaposition, whole a continuous and generates series further interpretations based of possibilities of meaning within each element, even those as minute as the letters composing the words. Fish too conceives of interpretation as a process. returns to his sentence about Judas For example, he and argues that readers' responses to the ninth word in the sentence will be shaped by their responses to the first eight Here we see his inclination toward perceiving interpretation as a words. linear progression. "The basis of the method is a consideration of the temporal flow of the reading experience, and it is assumed that the reader responds in terms of that flow and not to the whole utterance" (Fish 27). In doing so, Fish defines interpretation as a decoding of a set of instants and a process by which a temporal hierarchy so that the decoding becomes the readers construct event. Fish explains that because readers are presented with the clause Judas perished by hanging himself" "That first, before reading "There is no certainty in Scripture," the status of assertion is in doubt. Fish says that if the clauses were reversed and read "There is no certainty in Scriptures that Judas perished by hanging himself," readers would be offered a perspective which would be confirmed rather than challenged by the words which follow it (2728). Ultimately, it would be "a difference in meaning" (Fish 28). Fish maintains that any statement, any word, cannot help but provide experience. experience. This experience, as far as Fish is concerned, is a sort of linguistic Readers are presented with linguistic experiences for their viewing, the value of which "is predicated on the idea of meaning as an event" (Fish 28). Something, he says, is occurring, there is some activity, some creation by virtue of the words in readers' minds. Any sentence, any word, is 10 Thus, he ultimately concludes that "actively there, doing something" (Fish 30). a different meaning results when words are reorganized. understood, though, that a different meaning does not result power (Boman 69), from To conceive of words as reorganization as much as a different experience does. "actively there, doing something" It could be (Fish 30) is to attribute to words another characteristic of Hebraic a vivifying intertextuality. Because, for Fish, meaning in literature is activity, the result of a process engaging readers and a written composition, Fish suggests that "there is no direct relationship between the meaning of a sentence and what its words mean . . . solely responsible for meaning. language ceases to be the information an utterance gives, its message, is a constituent of, but certainly not to be identified with, its meaning" (32). The information, that signified by the words, does not provide the sentence's complete meaning but is included within the decoding experience to comprise meaning. Thus, it might be said that for Fish words do not merely represent the world and texts reflect it. Instead, words and texts become one element of the world, within it and simultaneously creating it. inherent Instead of allowing logic to cancel out possibilities of meaning, a metonymy involving the world and language allows readers to recognize that the written composition is incomplete, merely one constituent of the entire experience, or activity of interpretation. Hebraic intertextuality relies upon this principle of metonymy for its continuous interpretation of all facets of a text (Handelman 75). In "Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics," Fish objects to the idea that meaning is logical and found inherently within the word as opposed to something constructed by the word in its interaction with readers. Fish 11 that language is one constituent in the production of meaning, and advocates that that production utilizes as well the unique reader complete with previous experiences and the circumstances of the reading. in the interpretation of "sentences meaning Such a theory finds (and works) that don't mean anything, in the sense of not making [logical] sense" (Fish 36). Fish finds no difficulty embracing such ideas as those articulated above because "to mean in that discursive way creates the experience that is its meaning; and analysis of that experience rather than of logical content is able to make sense of one With such a statement he has kind-experiential sense-out of nonsense" (37). echoed a major tenet of Hebraic intertextuality. Fish supports his idea of how meaning is produced by rejecting the objective text, calling such a concept a "dangerous illusion" (43). He recognizes the tendency in literary circles to assume that the word contains a "content," that any book or statement or written text of any kind contains everything it needs to exist. Fish argues that the text is not self-sufficient and complete but needs the reader to fulfill it. In doing so he recognizes that he is setting himself up for being charged with presenting solipsism. a rationale for "Of course, it would be easy for someone to point out that I have not answered the charge of solipsism but merely presented a rationale for a solipsistic procedure; but such an objection would have force only if a better mode of procedure were available" (Fish 49). While it may still be solipsism, Fish says he would rather "have an acknowledged and controlled subjectivity than an objectivity which is finally an illusion" (49). Unlike Fish's reader response theory, Hebraic intertextuality does not sacrifice the text for the sake of readers. Nor does Hebraic intertextuality sacrifice readers for the sake of 12 the text. Instead, intertexuality considers readers and the written text to be two elements of a number of wholes. My purpose is not to justify Fish's reader response theory. Nor is it my But I do propose that to familiarize purpose to justify Bierce's stylistics. oneself with Hebraic intertextuality is to open doors upon new paths to follow Handelman literature. contribution to American in our exploration of Bierce's contends that Western critics of the text approach their study "within the context of the Biblical tradition, or in reaction to it" (xiv), relying upon what she terms "substitute in hermeneutic theology" (xiii), or the extensive application has of interpretation" She feels such a "modern science study. of metaphor deeper "theological roots" and that "it is time to bring . . . repressed theological specters to light," to allow a "return of theology into secular systems of thought" (Handelman I intend for this thesis to support Handelman's xviii). contention that the Biblical tradition of hermenuetics has dominated as the mode of interpretation within the study of literary criticism. validate her call for an alternative the traditional Hebraic theory strategy of literary I also seek to criticism incorporating of intertextuality. I do not claim that for the purpose of this study I have chosen the best of Bierce's short stories. Since my interest lies not in a definitive study of Bierce's work, I have merely selected those short stories which best demonstrate my thesis. However, the extremely broad spectrum of Bierce's works, which includes noteworthy stories as well as insignificant tales, will be represented in this study. Grenander calls "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" one of "those remarkable short stories on which . . . [Bierce's] literary reputation rests today" (54-55). This story lies at one end of the spectrum. ..............- "A R-- 13 Psychological which, according Shipwreck," to Woodruff, is a "conventional story" with "commonplace motifs" which "could have been done as well or better by a number of writers" (127) and "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field," on which little or no critical work has been done, lie at the other end. Death of Halpin Frayser" "The and "The Man and the Snake" lie between the two ends and are considered by many to be typical but yet not preeminent What value each of these stories has lies in its examples of Bierce's style. narrative structure and the function of language I will in that structure. provide an analysis of these five short stories to identify the techniques Bierce used to distort time and the world and to attempt to identify what Davidson says is Peirce's "'tychism' (uncertainty or indeterminancy)" (4). Grasping the ambiguity of language outside the traditional logical hierarchy of thought is crucial to the development explain which will Bierce's stories. the most insightful point Bierce made concerning. writing is Perhaps writer works with materials that the great that have no tangible or finite existence, things "mysteriously insubstantial . . . , spirits of dream . . adequately of a theory of literary interpretation existences not of earth . . . , the shadow and the portent" (Works X, 244). Nothing but a writer's own creative imagination makes that writer an artist. Woodruff explains: independence "What Bierce is most conscious of is the imagination's of the everyday world, its ability to carry the mind out of the actual conditions of human limitation. This idea is hardly new; its real importance lies in the appeal it held for Bierce" (93). Woodruff calls Bierce's language "the imagination's liberating power" (93). 14 In order to explain how Woodruff's assertion can be supported with an understanding broadened of Hebraic intertextuality, and I will first survey the scholarly interpretations of the five short stories I have selected. Next, I will introduce elements of the Hebraic philosophy of language and time and a theory of textual interpretation. The traditional interpretations of these stories will then be amended by an application of Hebraic intertexuality. stress Hebraic the value of the interpretations of Bierce's stories. technique I will alternate in reaching No objective in applying the technique will be alluded to other than to indicate that many previous literary critics, some contemporary with Bierce as well as some who view him in retrospect, fail to comprehend: 1) the multiple functions of language, and 2) the resultant uncertainty of language, Peirce's tychism. In doing so, they also fail to grasp all the implications in Bierce's short stories which take advantage of the ambiguous nature of language. An understanding of Hebraic intertextuality can allow readers and critics to understand the strange and elusive nature of Bierce's short stories and their possible multitudes Ambrose When I refer to Greek Several terms I shall be using need clarification. thought, I refer to post-Platonic thought. synonymous language. of interpretations. The terms Hebrew and Israelite are and refer in this paper to those who reject the mimetic nature of I do not by any means intend to imply that Hebrews are the only people who view words as independent agents with creative power. oriental cultures conceive current Judeo-Christian of language as functioning perception of an absolute similarly. world Other However, the and a mimetic language resulted from a fusion of the Hebraic and the Greek. Thus, to indicate how Greek ideas diffused Hebraic ideas in the West, I will concentrate 15 on the Hebraic rather than attempt a general study of the oriental view of language. To survey the entire oriental culture and to contrast that thought with Greek thought would be cumbersome and pointless in this thesis. The term Rabbi refers to the Hebrew scholars whose primary occupation is to interpret the Torah, the written text and God's Word. I will use the term text as the Rabbis conceive it, not only as the written composition, but as all elements of existence surrounding it. Text includes readers and what they bring to the reading, the milieu it came out of, and the milieu it creates. By time I do not mean progressive chronology but a collection of experiences, and by the world I mean existence as human beings know it, including the earth, the universe, and the spiritual world. Let us look first at the way Bierce uses time and the world to affect the reading of his stories. CHAPTER II PAST, PRESENT, FUTURE: TIME IN THE MANY DIFFERENT WORLDS OF AMBROSE BIERCE Critical examinations of Bierce's impressive ideas concerning the writer's work have presented undeniably stylistics and development of theme. The two most significant examinations are Cathy N. Davidson's The Experimental Grenander's Fictions of Ambrose Bierce: Bierce. Ambrose forerunner of post-modernism. Structuring the Ineffable and M. E. Davidson's study identifies Bierce as a Grenander divides Bierce's work into didactic tales and three kinds of mimetic tales, those of passion, those of moral choice, and those of action. Both Davidson and Grenander have devoted a considerable amount of their scholarly energies to retrieving Bierce's work from the neglected state it has so long endured as a result of public and critical ambivalence. Grenander three overshadowing from points out that this ambivalence has resulted issues, Bierce's disappearance in Mexico in 1913, his charisma, and the fact that his "vast literary production has not been carefully investigated" (8, 9). It is true that there is "more popular interest than critical response to his writings" (American Scholarship Critical response should be neglected no longer, for Bierce's writings are the greater part of his mystery. understand the man. Perhaps to understand them is to However, as Grenander points out, "we have not yet developed critical concepts enabling us to deal adequately with his work (9). 16 . . . 1977:241). Literary 17 In this chapter I will review the most widely accepted interpretations of Bierce's work to point out that while they serve quite well to present the difficulties of Bierce's stylistics, they do not resolve the questions raised by those stylistics. I will concentrate on the critical studies of the short stories "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," "The Man and the Snake," and "The Death of Halpin Frayser," as well as the one critical statement made concerning "A Psychological Shipwreck." Crossing a Field." consider Hebraic I know of no critical study of "The Difficulty of My analysis will provide the context within which to intertextuality as a new method for analyzing Bierce's stories. "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" is Bierce's premier story, one he ever wrote" (Woodruff 153). "the best Divided into three segments, the story introduces readers to Peyton Farquhar as he stands on Owl Creek Bridge with a noose around his neck, just before his hanging. omniscient narrator who concentrates who are preparing the hanging. acknowledgment him. on the Next, of his "unsteadfast The scene is described by an actions of the Federal soldiers we are given Farquhar's footing" and the swirling water beneath We are told that "he closes his eyes in order to fix his last thoughts upon his wife and children." Then it appears that the omniscient narrator makes an aloof comment about the water, "touched to gold by the early sun, the brooding mists under the banks . . . ." mind, to his consciousness Then we return to the workings of Farquhar's of a "new disturbance," which he determines to be the ticking of his watch and which "hurt his ears like the thrust of a knife" (11). then These shifts back again, from the narrator's which continue perception throughout the to Farquhar's story, are perception signalled by and free 18 indirect discourse, a "version of indirect reporting . . . freed from syntactic domination by any reporting clause" and characterized adopt the orientation, any in deictic words, of the reported character rather than reporting individual" (Toolan 123). introduces his readers to the opinions characters by a "tendency to An author's and perceptions in order to confuse objective free indirect discourse of one or more reality. In the second section, we return to the day before when Farquhar is informed that Federal troops are repairing railroads at Owl Creek Bridge. he determines to sabotage them for the Southern cause (12). "returns" to the scene with which the story opened, Here The last section and we are told, "As Peyton Farquhar fell straight downward through the bridge he lost consciousness and was as one already dead" (13). We are then informed that he awakened from this state. The rest of the story is a description of each sensation and subsequent thought However, in the last sentence Farquhar experiences the narrator intervenes during again his escape. to inform us that "Peyton Farquhar was dead; his body, with a broken neck, swung gently from side to side beneath the timbers of the Owl Creek bridge" (18). sentence which creates for readers a problem This is the with time in the short story. Readers must realize that time is fluid in the narrative in order to assimilate the story. Fluid time might be understood not to mean stream-like but to mean sea-like, in the sense that time does not exist as a progressive flow but rather as a rhythmic body. narrative Bierce's free indirect discourse is woven throughout the text and provides the first indication of fluid time in the discourse. Clearly, time is critical to "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." To conceive of time in Bierce's short story as linear is to miss much that the story III.In - 111 10 19 If readers refuse to accept that Farquhar "knew that the rope had has to offer. then they prevent themselves broken and he had fallen into the stream" (13), from embracing the text as a whole, the whole of Peyton Farquhar's At the story's last sentence, they will reject the narrative dream or a hallucination, or at the very least, illogical and therefore experience. unacceptable. as a F. J. Logan argues Davidson calls the story a trap (129), while that the story is as logical and "as tightly controlled and meticulously organized as any story is likely to be" (103). However, both critics seek to formulate interpretations of the story based on linear time and are thus led to make erroneous assertions. vital Bierce teases information, insufficient information" "By deliberately Davidson maintains, (55). the reader into drawing withholding inferences But to say that Bierce withholds from information is to imply that there is an ultimate truth to which all information must eventually lead. She assumes that there is an absolute world, an absolute reality which Bierce's work must represent. Logan suggests that Bierce's "drastic fictional distortion of time" (106) indicates that Farquhar is hallucinating (110). But to say that Farquhar is hallucinating is to impose one's own reality on Farquhar's reality, an unwarranted exercise since it assumes that there is an ultimate reality to which all experiences must conform. Logan assumes that his view of the world is more valid than Farquhar's and that since Farquhar's reality does not align with his own, it Setting up as absolute one perception of time must then be an hallucination. and the world is one mistake inherent in modem Other traditional interpretations based on linear, progressive time Western literary of the events in Bierce's and argue that Farquhar's criticism. story are also experience is 20 subconscious, subliminal, James G. Powers proposes that the or a dream. experience, not just a occurrence of the short story's title is a psychological physical one and is thus a dream of some sort (279). accidental He believes that it is not that Bierce describes Farquhar's plunge from the bridge in the active voice: "Farquhar dived-dived as deeply as he could" (15). the passive voice, i.e., "Farquhar was dropped," Bierce indicates By not using that Farquhar is in control of the activities in his head and allows Farquhar to take the initiative in his journey. Powers describes the journey as one composed of "sensations unaccompanied by thought" (13), only two sentences a phrase he excerpts from the narrative. However, Farquhar's "power of thought was restored" (13). experience only as a dream or some other sort of psychological outside the realm of the physical. later the narrative Traditionally, tells us that Powers sees Farquhar's experience in the Western world only dreams are accepted as disjointed or fluid, because they are imagined to be contained within a period of semiconsciousness or unconsciousness. Powers' conclusion indicates that he perceives time as linear. John Crane states that Farquhar "has imposed a temporary reality, the desires of his heart, upon the true reality of his hanging within the confines of the swollen moment of his post-mortem consciousness" (364). that Farquhar has devised his own reality is commendable. His notion But he relegates it to a sphere outside a "real world" and determines that the experiences of Peyton Farquhar must be postmortem since death itself is the end of the progression of events in a subject's life. that Farquhar can only has remained on the Since at the end of the story we know bridge during the entire narrative, assume that Farquhar was hanged and dead before Crane we are informed 21 of the fact by the omniscient narrator. Farquhar's experience postmortem Contrary to Crane, I do not consider and see no reason why it must be. There is no reason to assume that Farquhar dies before "all is darkness and silence!" (18), the last record we have of his experience before we are told by the omniscient narrator that "Peyton Farquhar was dead" (18). Peyton Farquhar never dies. include his death. I submit that His reality is a product of his words and does not Instead, he has used the power of his language to reject linear time and to reconstruct time in order to escape what readers conceive of as the reality of his death. Unlike Peyton Farquhar, who uses the power of his language to escape death, Harker Brayton in "The Man and the Snake" relies on the power of his language to effect his own death. Woodruff considers this story so "inferior in artistic merit as to seem almost a caricature" since it lacks Bierce's mastery at But it is a "suggestive ambiguity or symbolic vitality and compression" (144). fine example of Bierce's ability to uncover other worlds. An ironic tale and what Grenander calls a mimetic tale of passion, "The Man and the Snake" is composed of four sections. In the first section an omniscient narrator tells us that Harker Brayton scoffs at an epigraph describing the power of a snake's eyes to draw forth its victims. Brayton says to himself, "The only marvel in the matter is that the wise and learned in Morryster's day should have believed such nonsense . . . " (142-143). At the end of this section we discover that a snake lies coiled beneath Brayton's bed, beside which he reads in a chair. Section two provides a history and a description of the main character, the same function of the second section of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek 22 Here we learn that the house in which Harker Brayton is a guest Bridge." boasts a large wing designated as "the Snakery," where the host, a doctor of zoology, conducts his experiments. the section removes readers Narrated in the third person omniscient, from a progression of events and thus exhibits fluid time. In section three we return to the confrontation between man and serpent and the same free indirect discourse which shifts between perceptions as we found in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." At one point we are told by an omniscient narrator, "it had occurred to his mind that the act [of notifying a servant of the snake's location] of fear" (145). might subject him to the suspicion But in the next paragraph we read: The reptile was of a species with which Brayton was unfamiliar. Its length he could only conjecture; the body at the largest visible part In what way was it dangerous, seemed about as thick as his forearm. if in any way? Was it venomous? Was it a constrictor? His knowledge of nature's danger signals did not enable him to say; he had never deciphered the code. If not dangerous, the creature was at least offensive. "matter out of place"-an impertinence. setting. It was de.LEW- The gem was unworthy of its (145) In this section of the story we clearly shift from perspective to perspective. Those thoughts I have italicized are Harker Brayton's; the others are those of the omniscient narrator. irresistible -M ,1 4 , , , , '. I ,, . , I, , , " ;, - !:-- , - .*V~ 40 and cannot At the end of section three Brayton finds the snake prevent himself from advancing toward it. 23 The fourth section introduces the doctor and his wife, who, while reading downstairs, hear a "mighty cry" (148) ringing through the house. They find Brayton dead, half underneath the bed, where the doctor finds a stuffed snake with shoe-button eyes. Woodruff claims "we have Harker Brayton, performing incredible contortions, mesmerized by a bogy under the bed" (146). While the snake may Woodruff be a bogy to Woodruff, to Brayton there was nothing bogus about it. insists that "the immobility-the trivial irony-of the taxidermist's art" diminishes the impact of the tale (147): The result is a flawed technique marked by uncertainty of tone, a painful combination of humor and seriousness, and a breakdown in coherence and unity. Instead of the protagonist being pulled apart by things as they are, the story itself starts to unravel, a victim of Bierce's cynical disbelief in its significance or validity. (148) Woodruff's insistence that Brayton is "pulled apart" by things as they are not indicates his inability to consider that what "is not" for him may yet be for someone else. No one is informed until the end of the story that what Brayton sees is a stuffed snake. informed Readers do not know until that revelation that they are of Brayton's perceptions Bierce's only. ability to construct a world for readers parallels Brayton's ability to construct his own world, which includes a living snake coiled beneath his bed. apparently The snake's eyes at first were "two small points of light, about an inch apart. They might have been reflections jet above him, in metal nailheads . . . " (143). of the gas Brayton looks again and the lights are still there, but "They seemed to have become brighter than before, 24 He returns shining with a greenish lustre he had not at first observed" (143). to reading but eventually drops the book and stares "where the points of light shone with, it seemed to him, an added fire" (143). Now his attention "disclosed, almost directly under the foot-rail of the bed, the coils of a large serpent-the points of light were its eyes" (143). sparks, radiating an infinity electric eyes "were two Finally, we read, "the eyes were now of luminous needles" (146) and then the dazzling suns" and "gave off enlarging rings of rich and vivid colors . . . " (143). Bierce uses free indirect discourse to prevent himself from having to inform readers that the snake under the bed is stuffed. the snake was "matter out of place" By telling us (145), Bierce enters Harker Brayton's mind With free and takes readers with him to alter the perspective of the narrative. indirect discourse, Bierce allows his reader to choose for himself what to believe about who is saying what when. The success of the story is in the fact As Davidson that readers do not question what it is they actually follow. explains, "This story especially assesses the human capacity for not discovering the truth" (33). Woodruff asserts that "immobility-the trivial irony-of the taxidermist's art" results in Brayton's being "pulled apart" by things as they are not (29), and this is true in a sense-the art in a stuffed snake is trivial and results in Wiggins agrees and says, "The climax reveals a psychological in autosuggestion" (29). But in another sense neither of these points is true, for Brayton died, which can hardly be thought nothing. that Brayton's study "language clearly reflects his perceptual Davidson explains hyperbole Perception here is almost totally governed by psychological reflects external reality hardly at all" (35). . . . nothing. projection and Since Brayton is unaware that it is 25 Davidson can argue that Brayton's hyperbolic for others, for him it is reality. perceptions are hyperbolic because she has read the end of the story and has Brayton never was privy to such been informed that the snake is stuffed. Harker Brayton attempts information. he is not afraid. to use words to convince himself that Ultimately, however, he succumbs to the words he reads and believes that he has seen a real snake and that it mesmerizes him. attempt to use language While his to construct reality without a snake fails, his firm Wiggins calls Brayton's experience belief in the word dooms him to death. autosuggestive because there is no live snake and yet Brayton dies as a result But Mary Grenander may explain the of his belief in the contrary (29). phenomenon best when she states, "the protagonist reacts emotionally to what She says: he thinks is a situation of extreme jeopardy" (97). Obviously the base of this psychology is the intellectual awareness of danger. Bierce, however, makes the intellectual awareness on which the whole psychology of his protagonist's terror rests a wrong one; hence all the emotional and sensory reactions which follow are erroneous, and readers' inappropriateness perception of this gruesome to the real situation distillation of horror to these tales. is what gives their peculiar (94) But it must never be forgotten that readers do not realize this "gruesome inappropriateness" until the end of the story, and that Harker Brayton never realizes it. In "The Death of Halpin Frayser," another story that Grenander has identified as a tale of mimetic passion, Bierce again uses free indirect discourse. This technique forces readers to follow the text carefully in order to 26 is only the character's reality. realize that what Frayser experiences Structurally identical to "The Man and the Snake," the story is composed of four sections and an epigraph attributed to a hypothetical sage. In the first section, we meet Halpin Frayser awakening from a dreamless sleep in a forest. He whispers a name, "Catherine Larue," the irony of which we fail to Subsequently, we are provided an explanation of why appreciate at this point. he finds himself asleep in a forest. person limited narrator, Normally, narration is offered by a third since it is mere observation, except for the statement, "one of God's mysterious messengers . . . pronounced the awakening word in the ear of the sleeper, who sat upright and spoke, he knew not why, a name, he knew not whose" (396). He falls asleep again and dreams. We travel with him via the omniscient narrator through the forest in his dream until a ghostly apparition appears and the section ends. In section two we are provided information about the character's background, just as we were in section two of "An Occurrence Bridge" and "The Man and the Snake." at Owl Creek In section three, we return to the confrontation with the ghostly apparition, "the thing so like, yet so unlike his mother" (401). Presumably, we still follow Frayser's dream, for we leave section three with the statement, "Halpin Frayser dreamed that he was dead" (402). In the fourth section we accompany a sheriff and his man at arms as they search the woods for a madman recently spotted there. story of Catherine Larue and that the madman is her husband, who murdered her. for whom We learn the the sherrif searches Ultimately they come upon an unidentified body, which we know to be Halpin Frayser's, lying upon im-lismal'aig'amilnlilmonomm NOW 1191ImpaAmmil, M -- WWWWWWAMM 27 Catherine Larue's grave in in the position Frayser adopted in his dream apparition so like and unlike his section three to ward off the strangling When the sheriff remembers that "the murdered woman's name had mother. been Frayser" (408), we understand the irony that Halpin Frayser died unknowingly on his mother's grave apparition murdered Grenander and the double irony that somehow her him. argues that Frayser's dream remains only a dream and that his death is a "realistic external drama" divorced from the dream (110). She points out that when Holker and Jarrelson discover Frayser's body, the dead man "bears all the marks of a man who has been physically strangled, not one who has died of horror" (109). She points to the "signs of furious struggle" (406), "the unmistakable impressions of human knees" beside the body (406), and "a laugh so unnatural" it fills the men with "unspeakable dread" (408). Aptly pointing out that the narrator offers no explanation of these facts, Grenander assigns them to a "realistic external drama" (110). Frayser was murdered by his stepfather. this interpretation, those which She says that All the other clues which contradict "point to a supernatural-and explanation . . . are red herrings" only (111). superficial- Grenander believes that Bierce employs the following epigraph about zombies in order to mislead readers (107): For by death hath been wrought greater change than hath been shown. Whereas in general upon occasion, the spirit that removed cometh back and is sometimes seen of those in flesh (appearing in the form of the body it bore) yet it hath happened that the veritable body without the spirit hath walked. And it is attested of those 28 encountering who have lived to speak thereon that a lich so raised up hath no natural affection, nor remembrance thereof, but only hate. Also, it is known that some spirits which in life were benign become by death evil altogether. (395) But a zombie is a dead human body reanimated. physically strangling a man. As such, it is capable of Thus, it is possible that Frayser was murdered by a zombie. Grenander's Freudian theory that Frayser's dream guilt is unnecessary and gives credit where it is not due. reflects repressed Bierce does inquire in the story, "what mortal can cope with a creature of his dream?" (402). The fact that Frayser dreams is important, not because it explains that he dies from guilt, but because it allows readers to capture Frayser's perceptions of his own death. Grenander's interpretation of the story remains inconsistent with that theme running through Bierce's stories which indicts fear, not guilt, as murderer. While Davidson agrees with Grenander that "The Death of Halpin Frayser" is full of red herrings, her resignation to the fact that "we cannot ask where dream leaves off and reality begins when the man who dreams he diesdies" (110) is more acceptable than Grenander's attempt to resolve irrefutably the mystery of who killed Halpin Frayser. Davidson points out that Bierce tells us, "Vainly [Frayser] sought . . . to reproduce the moment of his sin . . . " (397). Frayser's stumbling amidst the blood-bathed woods is but a vain effort "of tracing life backwards in memory" which he suffers guilt. (397) in order to determine the crime for "If this passage symbolizes anything, it indicates the futility of looking for a moral justification for Halpin's fate," says Davidson 29 "Nothing in the story . . . is certain at all" (104-05), she explains, and (106). then says the story "calls the conventions of reality question" (111). (and 'realism') into Here it is clear that while Frayser may be attempting to explain his experience in terms of retribution for his past sins, he need not, for Bierce tells us that to attempt such an explanation is for naught: he sought . . . " (397). readers cannot level . . . . nightmare "Vainly Davidson sums up her interpretation with: apprehend the death of Halpin Frayser on any logical Interior and exterior worlds, nightmare dream and reality, uncertain past continually meet and merge . . . . must continually reject and problematic present- The joke lies in the fact that readers . . . apparent solutions because they do not . adequately comprehend the complexities elsewhere in the text . . . No one solution can contain evoked by the text . . . . weight of its overload. interpretation. the unsettled and unsettling universe The text . . . cannot sustain itself under the The result is a sham of the whole process of (112-13) It is quite true that "The Death of Halpin Frayser" is Bierce's most complex and difficult tale. In "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" most readers initally assume to be reality what they eventually conclude is actually a dream. In "The Death of Halpin Frayser" what Frayser and most readers initially assume is a dream actually appears to be reality at the end of the story. Frayser's dream is introduced with "He thought he was walking . . . " (396) not "He dreamed he was walking . . . ." The different verbs convey entirely different meanings, regardless of how subtle that conveyance might be. "He thought" reveals the 30 same principle found in "The Man and the Snake" and "An Occurrence Creek Bridge." Because Frayser thinks something, it allows define his reality, for it is what he perceives. at Owl that something to Again, one's words construct He never knows he merely dreams that his mother attacks him; one's world. thus, he knows, having experienced the attack in some form, that she attacks. In "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" the would-be hero believes he has escaped but ends up hanging instead. "The Man and the Snake" mocks a young man's fear of a stuffed snake which eventually kills him. Indeed, most of Bierce's stories do not focus on death as much as they use death to direct our focus toward fear. "A Psychological Shipwreck" and "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field," however, do not. Unlike the other stories, "A Psychological Shipwreck" are not divided into sections. Difficulty of Crossing a Field" and "The Both are extremely short and utilize the first person narrative technique at some point in the Without using free indirect discourse, both succeed stories. questions about time and the world. is "conventional" Shipwreck" in raising Woodruff complains that "A Psychological and "commonplace" (127), the story, nevertheless, presents time as fluid and shows that another world can be created with words. Indeed, the story is about other worlds. A first person narrator, William Jarrett, tells us that he sails aboard the Morrow from Liverpool to New York because he seeks a protracted journey to time reading He meets Janette Harford, who spends her "Denneker's Meditations." subtle, but powerful For her, Jarrett develops attraction which constantly impelled [him] "a secret, to seek her . recover from his failed business. He tells us at one point that he ventured whether she might "assist me ." (495). - 'jQwdw 0 0- 31 to resolve my psychological doubt" (495) about this particular conviction. She turned to look at him. In an instant my mind was dominated by as strange a fantasy as ever entered human consciousness. It seemed as if she were looking at me, an immeasurable not with, but through, those eyes-from distance behind them-and that a number of other persons, men, women and children, upon expressions, whose clustered faces I caught about her, struggling look at me through the same orbs. familiar strangely with gentle evanescent eagerness to Ship, ocean, sky-all had vanished. (495) Here we have the world with which the story itself is concerned another containing world. As if all this activity were merely preliminary, the theme of the story is made clear when Jarrett awakens from his altered state. "Impelled by surely I cannot say what motive" (495), he glances at a page of the book Miss Harford cradles in her lap while she dozes, having apparently fallen asleep during Jarrett's excursion, and reads: To sundry it is given to be drawn away, and to be apart from the body for a season for, as concerning rills which would flow across each other the weaker is borne along by the stronger, so there be certain of kin whose paths intersecting, their souls do bear company, the while their bodies go fore-appointed It may be that this passage provides experience. ways, unknowing. (495) an explanation for the aforementioned But it is most assuredly the context within which "A Psychological Shipwreck" is to be explained, as becomes evident by its conclusion. Here we 32 have an intrusion upon Jarrett's own of the first omniscient person narrative in "Denneker's Meditations" narration. Miss Harford awakens, and Jarrett initiates a discussion with her concerning this passage. Suddenly the barometer falls drastically, the Captain exclaims, "Good God!" and Jarrett tells us, "The form of Janette Harford, invisible in the darkness and spray, was torn from my grasp by the cruel vortex of the sinking ship, and I fainted . . . " (496). He awakes by lamplight "amid the familiar surroundings of the stateroom of a steamer" (496) to recognize "the face of my friend Gordon Doyle whom I had met in Liverpool on the day of my embarkation, when he was himself about to sail on the steamer City of Prague, on which he had urged me to accompany him" (496). Jarrett believes he has been picked up by the passing ship. Initially, Later, he learns that his friend, eloping with Janette Harford but sailing separately to avoid detection, plans to meet her in New York. and asks to see the book. He notices Doyle has been reading Doyle tosses to him "Denneker's Meditations," and the book opens to the marked passage already quoted. Thus what Jarrett receives as an explanation for the other world experienced is the same as that which readers of Biece's short story receive. Psychological Shipwreck," too, experience, experience that Jarrett experiences. in "Denneker's It is worth noting that readers of "A Meditations," albeit vicariously, the same So there is no reason that the explanation which explains for Jarrett his experience of the other world, should not provide the same for readers of "A Psychological Shipwreck." The narrative technique of "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" is like that of "A Psychological Shipwreck," a mixture of third person limited and 33 first person points of view. The story opens with a completely objective paragraph which reads like a legal account, and then it follows Williamson as he makes his way into the pasture in front of his plantation mansion. In the process, he meets a neighbor on the pike who, having forgotten to relay to him information, directs his coachman to drive back, and: as the vehicle turned Williamson was seen by all three, walking leisurely across the pasture. At that moment one of the coach horses stumbled and came near falling. It had no more than fairly recovered itself when James Wren cried, "Why, father, what has become of Mr. Williamson?" (163) The next paragraph uses the first person narrative to relay Armour Wren's account of Williamson's disappearance. Wren's testimony concludes, and the third person limited narrator returns to summarize James Wren's account as a corroboration of his father's testimony. The narrator refers to James as the only other eyewitness and then qualifies himself with "(if that is the proper term)" (163). This aside and the objective statement "James Wren had declared at first that he saw the disappearance, but there is nothing of this in his testimony given in court" (163-64) yield the most profound insight into the nature of this tale, that it seeks to undermine the authority we assign to the premise that seeing is believing, even more than it seeks to relate Williamson's disappearance. And, as Bierce himself aptly pointed out, this is because there is nothing seen to believe; what must be believed is that which remains unseen, the fact that Williamson is no longer, at least in the worlds belonging to his wife and to the Wrens. .......... 34 These tales and the criticism raised about and even against them reveal Ambrose Bierce's stories, excluding his didactic tales which seek to two points: uphold a moral teaching, for in consistently present the world as inexplicable, his stories the world constantly fluctuates and is malevolent in its elusiveness. the malevolent nature While critics recognize of the worlds Bierce they do not perceive the changing nature of those worlds. attempt to interpret his stories according constructs, Instead, they that the world is to their perceptions static. The problem articulated with by Logan, such interpretations of Bierce's short Powers, Crane, Grenander, stories as those and others is that they are postulated within the confines of the distinctly Western thought that time is linear and defines the nature of human existence in the world. must therefore submit their interpretations of narrative to Such critics a monolithic understanding of time outside the written text instead of considering that the world is a product of words and that time is, in turn, defined by this product of words. In other words, since the world is in flux, time may be fluid. As Ricoeur explains, those "writing on time . . . usually overlook the contribution of narrative to a critique of the concept of time. They either look to cosmology and physics to supply the meaning of time or they try to specify the inner experience of time without Time" 170). any reference on the sensual dream and activity" ("Narrative Thus, in interpreting narrative, Western critics have relied upon an absolute reality and the experience theories, to narrative experience Crane's postulate of sensations. or hallucination that Peyton Powers and Logan rely for the formulation of their Farquhar has imposed a temporary reality relies on the idea of sensation, for Crane assumes that even after ry- *#Wpww 35 Farquhar dies, the character is still "sensing" These (desiring) in the heart. critics have perpetuated the centrality of the spoken word in Western They have retained a philosophy contributing to a distrust of the written text. "belief in some ultimate 'word', presence, essence, truth or reality," that which "will act as the foundation of all our thought, language and experience . . . God, the Idea, the World Spirit, the Self" have all been nominees for this role (Eagleton 131). Western metaphysics has used each candidate in an attempt to identify the nature of being in language. But Eagleton says the ambition is too lofty since it requires that the suggestion itself be beyond that system, and no candidate ever has been nor ever will be, for there is no singular idea which is not a part of an unresolvable together with elements (131). struggle for meaning in language, woven of other ideas and residue of previous ruminations The problem is that this attempt to gain meaning uses what Eagleton calls social ideologies to select interpretations and promote them to "privileged positions," which literary critics use as the central tenet to which all other meanings must submit (131). "Sometimes," explains Eagleton, "such meanings . are seen as the origin of others, the source from which they flow; but this . . is a curious way of thinking, because for this meaning ever to have been possible other signs must have already existed" (131). Taking for granted that "narrative occurs within of instants," . . . a linear succession as Ricoeur states the case ("Narrative Time" 170), leads modern literary critics to a limited understanding of many of Bierce's short stories and allows them only to conclude that his work is merely a "gulf separating appearance from reality" (Woodruff 76). I suggest that time in Bierce's short stories cannot be understood clearly by critics and readers who do not consider 36 that time may be other than the conventionally linear defined existence. Blind acceptance of linear time allows for the definition of existence in nonprogressive time fragments, frozen time or fluid time, for without a linear time frame, there would be no standard by which to make it non-linear. readers, we treat time as linear when analyzing a text. As If we can disassemble the whole of the text and place the various constituent elements into some sort of categorical structure, we feel the story is acceptable. We understand it. But all we are actually doing is constructing a formulation to eventually tear it down again; then we can look back at the energy we have expended and believe we have accomplished a great task. We are reminded of Derrida's deconstructionism and what appears to be its call for ultimate nothingness. We have But we have not even achieved an acknowledgment of nothingness. only returned to a text comprised of constituent elements, because, according to Boman, "time is for us an abstraction since we distinguish time from the events that occur in time" (139). Boman explains that, in contrast to the way we perceive time, the Israelites make no distinction between time and the events which occur in time. Instead, "for them time is determined by its content. of the occurrence; it is the stream of events" (Boman 139). Wiggins' suggestion concerning "An Occurrence Time is the notion In such light at Owl Creek Bridge," that "the detailed description must be revaluated not as objective reality, but as the vividness of a psychological state-the truth that the mind makes its own reality" (25), can thus provide an even broader application than he intended. We need to concern ourselves not only with a variety of psychological states but also with a variety of worlds and the fluid nature of time as it changes -- w- 37 from world to world. much literature, Thus, we might arrive at alternate interpretations to not only Bierce's. In a sense, the idea of a fluid time and a multitude of simultaneous worlds is not new. Jacob Neusner points out that Hebraic intertextuality, the study of the written word, the holy books, provides insight into the Hebraic identity of the past twenty centuries (The Way of Torah 2). It has not been applied in the Western world, however, having been sacrificed by Plato and post-Platonic thinkers for the sake of an entirely different way of thinking, as we shall see in chapter 3. CHAPTER III BACKTRACKING: TWO LANGUAGES, TWO HERITAGES In Genesis we are told that God created the heavens and earth. heaven and earth we term the "world." The Then God said, "Let there be light" (1:3), after which he saw that the light was good and separated the light from Thus, we call the He called the light "day" and the darkness "night." the dark. light "day" and the darkness "night" and term their passing the passing of But attempts to understand time and the world have led to a great many "time." practical and theoretical debates. If on Tuesday I Consider the practical level. were to promise to revitalize our long-neglected friendship by visiting you the next day, you would anticipate my arrival at your home within the next 24 to 36 hours. My arriving Friday with the explanation that as far as I am concerned I had arrived on the designated "the next day," would be unacceptable. On the theoretical We operate according to schedules, categories more evident. and delineations. Concepts level, the elusive natures of time and the world are and definitions, But such constructs may be merely society's own creations. of time are constructed and then deconstructed for clarification. Avoiding or ignoring the total construct, as when I chose to construct my own chronology and put in my appearance after the 24- to 36-hour time allotted by convention, results in chaos. constructs. We live according to our society's own Having defined time as a linear progression the world, we operate accordingly with great conviction. 38 of instants through When contrary ideas 39 concerning the nature of time arise, we raise our eyebrows and perhaps theoretically accordance entertain We, nevertheless, the idea. continue with our initial construct defined by society in to operate and the turning of the planets. The underlying uncertainty Ambrose Bierce presents which is a quality of life is precisely what in his short stories with "keen, darting fragments" (Starrett 38) to force his readers to realize that such fragments make up their Bierce tears down readers' constructs of the world and time to own existence. undermine the absolute, monolithic Woodruff identifies consciousness. most significant positions they enjoy in readers' Bierce's attacks on such constructs as his device: the great writer works with materials that have no tangible or finite existence, nothing but the products of his own creative imagination . . . . They are mysteriously insubstantial "spirits of dream," "existences not of earth," "the shadow and the portent." (93) The success of Bierce's work relies upon his awareness that the imagination is independent of the everyday physical world. Many of us in the Western hemisphere fail to acknowledge "materials that have no tangible or finite existence." That is, we distrust the products of our own imagination. So we pretend that time and the world are ipso facto and not merely a creative imagination's products. This distrust results from Plato's initiation of the Greek Enlightenment when "the original unity of word and thing, 4). speech and thought, discourse and truth [was] disrupted" (Handelman No longer do we perceive words to have an essence of their own. developed a system of signs to relate the physical We have world to the metaphysical 40 beyond. "Unless it can have no semiotics confronts this relationship, relevance to the world of practical affairs with its confident assumptions about 'reality,' and it cannot account for the role of semiotic systems in that world" The nature of this relationship between semiosis and (Hodge and Kress 23). the world has raised concerning questions the natures and the world, and their relationships to one another. of language, thought According to Hodge and Kress, Saussure succeeded in establishing "the sign . . . in a realm between [the] two material planes" of the signifier, which refers, and the signified, Saussure's work confirms Plato's theory of language which is referred to (24). as identifying signs (Hodge and Kress 24-25). While not merely semioticians, Ricoeur and Heidegger have developed philosophies attempting to identify the nature of time and narrative. And Boman has identified in Hebraic thought a similar understanding of time. "Narrative Time" (1980), Paul Ricoeur states that "anti-narrativist In writers in the field of historiography and . . . structuralists in the field of literary criticism" place too much emphasis on "nomological models" and "paradigmatic codes" (171). This emphasis "results in a trend that reduces the narrative component to the anecdotic surface of the story" (171) based on the assumption that time is always laid out progressively and as a punctiliar chronology. Riceour protests that the dualism between narrative human experience conceived by some philosophers function and is a misrepresentation time (170). Says Ricoeur, "I agree with Heidegger that the ordinary re- presentation of time as a linear series of 'nows' hides the true constitution time . . ." (171). of Boman, too, believes the linear concept of time is inaccurate "since the points on any single line are coexistent" tfbsppTb of 9- i-----,.ll.---"-..,-,-,l (142). Boman suggests: 41 "Since the points on any single line are coexistent, it is completely Both Ricoeur and Boman inappropriate to illustrate time as a line" (142). prefer to define time in terms of a nonprogressive to the Hebrews' round dances and accompanying Boman refers experience. rotation as an example of the This rhythm which for them is "the great reality" of the world and time (134). idea of rhythmic time, however, is very different from Westerners' of time. understanding Semiotics has by no means succeeded in resolving this issue concerning the relationship between language, or a system of signs, and the world or time, although it has succeeded in raising significant questions literary theory, especially in its study of narratives. as Prince explains it, not only narratology, a narrative, but also paraphrase getting at" ("Pragmatics" 529). and "what the narrator is Authorial intent can be understood to be and can provide an excuse for the assumption that there exists a content Smith For example, structuralist attempts to summarize attempts to specify synonymous with meaning, however, ideal message. about these issues in outside the communication is the which Such a perception promotes the dualism which Herrnstein questions. Any attempt to interpret a given message requires that both interlocutors engage in the same system of communication, semiotic structure. writing using the same Chris Hutchison states this principle in terms of the act: The writer is pretending that, or acting as though, the rules constitutive of making assertions, have been complied with. giving descriptions, and so on, That is, he is pretending that he commits 42 himself to the truth of the expressed proposition, that there is evidence for the truth of the proposition, and that he is able to supply (7) such evidence, and that he believes the proposition to be true. These principles have been articulated by H. Paul Grice in "Logic and Conversation" (45-58). as the definitive Nevertheless, for maximum format many writers deliberately complied. without constitutive rules flout these principles to asserts and with which readers have unknowingly Because stories are in the form of a written text, readers have very little to say about the communication trust it. communication Clearly, Bierce deliberately achieve a desired effect upon readers. describes effective construct; they either trust it or do not If they do not, they probably will not read it. indication of a belief in what the writer presents. Reading a text is an Althought it is doubtful that Bierce commits himself "to the truth of the expressed proposition," readers believe the writer has made such a commitment because they believe he is attempting to communicate maximally and efficiently. not attempt to define truth or provide However, Bierce does He "evidence" to substantiate truth. merely questions what is commonly accepted as truth without providing answer to the question. readers. an Many times what Bierce presents is not acceptable to All too often they find they have invested in what they had perceived to be the setting up of a truth, or at least a possible truth, only to discover at the end of the story that even the author undermines that "truth" he had set up. Indeed, the success of many of Bierce's at the end that the foregoing structure stories relies upon the revelation is fractured communication. Readers trust Bierce until the end, and then they feel cheated and quite often refuse to read him again since they do not trust him anymore. 43 Hutchison states: "The writer uses words with their normal meanings, Hutchison's but their connection with the world is only pretended" (8). statement implies that there is a world outside of words to which words must normally connect, an implication again based on the However, monolith of an absolute world. in the next arbitrarily defined Hutchison does qualify his statement paragraph: If the pretence applies to the rules for the making of an assertion, then the set of conventions that the writer of fiction invokes requires that his readers with him in imagining collude that the world is such that, or that there is a possible world such that, it meets necessary for the sentences all the conditions sincere, non-defective assertions. he utters to constitute (8) However, Bierce does not so much assume that he has presented a possible world as much as he assumes he has indicated that what appears to be the world we live in is not necessarily so. His careful attention to the techniques of realism appear to provide readers with the objective, coherent world to But by the time the narrative concludes, it is which they already ascribe. easily recognized that he has not presented any such world. "the capable writer gives [fiction] not a moment's Bierce wrote that attention, except to make what is related seem probable in the reading-seem true," for "nothing is so improbable as what is true" ("Works" 10:247). Wiggins suggests that Bierce "does not seek . . . to convince his readers that such goings-on are true" (34). He is right; Bierce only makes such goings on seem real but in doing so does not insist they are real. that Davidson agrees: one cannot distinguish "The narrative between perceived and method itself implies imagined events" (16), and 44 "the world in Bierce's stories is a projected subjectivity" (84). She points out that in Bierce's essay on the short story he "discredits the idea that literature should be grounded in the mundane and the explicable" difficult for readers only because the readers Bierce's work is (115). have placed the narratives their own context of the world without considering the validity them in a different context, one contrary to the typical Western in of placing context. Instinctively they have sought the explicable and the logical, and sought it along a linear temporality. They have attempted to define the stories in terms of a logical proof and a hiercharchy of predicates, one based on another. Readers believe Aristotle's claim in his Metaphysica, "To say what is is and what is not is not is the true definition of truth and falsehood conversely" (1011.626f). To this point, I have been focusing on the problems inherent studies of semiotics and narrative. in the My goal has been to raise questions concerning the validity of what we take for granted. Now I wish to review the impact of Greek philosophy on the development of Western thought concerning language in an effort to identify the root of the problems inherent in the studies of semiotics and narrative. I will highlight Western thought by comparing it to Hebraic thought, a system of thought which has remained unaffected by Plato's theory that what we experience in the world is but a shadow of reality. What the Hebrews term "the world" is different from what we call the world, and their understanding of time is just as unique as ours. Handelman simply is (4). "JIWAVAKOWAORM explains that western thought has determined that what In his Cratylus Plato suggests that words, or names, are signs is, 45 merely for the forms of things, In since real things cannot be apprehended. doing so he raises the question of the accuracy of names and determines that Plato names contain no truth; they are merely tools used to signify meaning. was more concerned with whether or not the represented name properly the form of the object than he was with apprehending the essence of the word, for he did not conceive of the word as containing its own truth. Understanding is outside language and occupies the "intelligible sphere, so that ever since in all discussion on language, the concept of the image (eikon) has been replaced by that of sign (semeia)- which is not just a terminological an epoch-making 374). decision about thought change, but expresses language" concerning Thus, words do not signify but only name true being. then this . . . ," linear hierarchical Instead, truth is To recognize truth, thought to be apprehended in logic outside of language. one need only use reason to construct (Gadamer a syllogistic proof. Thinking "If this, the correct formula of predicates, will reveal a progressive and relationship. Aside from what the word stands for, there exists no value in the word. Eventually Christian doctrine reflected the search for truth in logic (Handelman 100). Handelman explains that Philo, "the first to wed philosophy and Scripture" (93), made "logos something identical with the essence of God. From Plato he took the idea that all things are created by logos (i.e., a reason) and a divine knowledge which comes from God, thus making logos equivalent to the divine mind, and a first principle, (100). Thus, something or instrument of creation" although the first chapter of John states that "In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God" (1:1) and "All things came into being by Him, and apart from Him nothing came into being 46 that has come into being" (1:3), Christians tend to interpret another name for God, not as the essence of God. "Word" as simply God and word are now So develops the belief that language must be transcended, divorced. and, as Handelman points out, Socrates is led to hypothesize, "How real existence is to be discovered is, I suspect, beyond you and me-we must rest content with the admission that the knowledge of things is not to be derived from names" (5). Handelman concludes that while for the Hebrews there is nothing outside the sign, no metaphysical realm, Western thought is based on of metaphor, which relies on a distinction between Aristotle's theory "sensible" or "literal" and the "nonsensible" or "figurative" (16). the Indeed, Handelman says that the Platonic transfer of the soul from the visible to the invisible world is the basis for the entire ontological tradition of Western metaphysics and results in movement from the literal to the figurative instead of movement from the nonsensible to the sensible (16). unlike Western thought, has remained Eastern thought, uninfluenced by these Greek ideas. Rabbinic thought holds that the relations between various levels of meaning are more immanent aspects of one another than elements in a hierarchically ordered progression (Handelman 28-29). Yahweh, the Hebrew God, does not simply exist in stasis but spoke His being, and in His utterance the Hebrews hear and experience His Being (Handelman 17). The text, the divine word, was the means for the provision of the relationship, not the visualizing of a sign. Thus, "the realm of language retains its physis, its concreteness, and is (Handelman preserved" Because Handelman -, -t Christian 20). thought developed says it is "predominantly I MAW- lexical on the Greek foundation, and metaphorical, whereas the 47 Rabbinic mode [is] predominantly propositional While (55). and metonymical" the literal and the metaphorical exist in both traditions, they are used differently within the two traditions. In Greco-Christian thought, metaphor depends on a resemblance resulting in a transfer of one word or idea to another word or idea (Handelman 16). identification, and cancellation" This results in "substitution, election, (Handelman 55); thus, however differences, slight, between the first and second word or idea are effaced. Containing no essence of its own because it contained only words without essence, the written composition ceased to provide any definition of meaning. Ultimately, Christians rejected the relevance of what Handelman calls "verbal pattern" (32) to replace the value of the written text with the revelation word become flesh (John 1:14). of Christ, the The apostle Paul converted from Judaism to Christianity to preach the ultimate fulfillment of all words in Christ. But the Jews repudiated his message that Jesus was Messiah (Acts 13:46), and the news divided the Greeks (Acts 14:2). "For the Jews," Paul writes, "demand signs and the Greeks seek wisdom, but we preach Christ crucified, a stumbling block to Jews and folly to Gentiles" (I Cor. 1:22-23). And so, as Handelman points out, to convince both Jews and Greeks of the truth of the new creed, Paul used language to create truths that would reach both (84): To the Jews I became as a Jew, in order to win Jews; to those under the law I became as one under the law-though not being myself under the law-that I might win those under the law. To those outside the law [Greeks] I became as one outside the law-that I might win those outside the law . . . . 9:20-22) I have become all things to all men . . . . (I Cor. 48 Because Paul believed that the power of language was in its essence, he believed the proclamation of his creed would mean one thing to Hebrews and another to Greeks. Paul's letter to the Greeks at Colossae declares Jesus as Christ, the Messiah "the image of the invisible God, the first-born of all creation" (Col 1.15). Boman says Paul's statement can be interpreted in Greek thought to mean "that Christ is the becoming visible on earth of the invisible God" (121). But Boman points out that while the Hebrews did not accept Jesus as Christ, the Messiah, the verse can have meaning for them, too, in the sense that their Messiah is "the aggregate qualities" of God (Boman 121). remains the same although, as regards form, the interpretations "The sense are opposites" (Boman 121). As both Boman and Handelman explain, the world is objective for the Greeks, a given quantity easily apprehended sight. with the senses, particularly Only what is seen is of concern to Greeks, and they communicate nothing else (Boman 113). Post-Platonic Greeks tell no stories and do not narrate verbosely (Handelman 33). They avoid impressions and concentrate merely on what can be apprehended through sight (Boman 113). paraphrases Plato: "Perception is of decisive significance Boman for philosophy, all our concepts, including that of time, are given through sight" (115). for For Plato, god and the divine can been seen; Boman says Plato "tried above all to see the eternal and the invisible" (119). The Hebraic world is not so objective. The Hebrews' language differs radically from the Greeks'. Boman explains, "The Israelite-oriental In fact, conception of the word is formally the opposite of the Greek conception . . . " in the sense that it effects power (58). That is, for the Hebrews, the word is true being and is not merely an element 49 This is evident, as Boman notes (58), in the book of Jeremiah in "'My word, is it not like a fire,! A hammer that shatters the Hebraic scriptures: Boman points out that it is impossible for the Hebrews to rocks?"' (23:29). identify a distinction between the word and the voice of Yahweh, "for word signifies the power- though sense-laden utterances of God while the 'voice' represents above all God's working through the powers of nature. . " (Boman 58). "It [is] a mighty and dynamic force . . . of a system of signs to represent being. For the Hebrews . . . 'voice' signifies the sound of the speech [only], but 'word' means the utterance or what is said itself" (Boman 60). The Hebrews understand that the utterance is singular, separate from the voice. Because it is divorced from the act of speaking, the utterance is not related to sound. perception, but utterance and word are essentially Sound is auditory synonymous. This idea that the essence of being is inherent in the word allows the Hebrews to attach to the word the power of evocation. Psalm 33:9 reads, "For he spoke, and it came to be; he commanded and it stood forth." typical for the Hebrews since "it is characteristic of the Hebrews that their The Greek word merely is words effect . . . ." (Boman 69). initiate or activate (Boman 69). The scripture is and cannot therefore While the Greek logos only represents and boasts no creative energy, the Hebrew dabhar defines God and the Hebrews by action experienced by dabhar. "The action of the Hebrew noun is active, dynamic, visible, and palpable . . . while the action of the Ideas is like the effect of a magnet or of the sun, passive and impalpable but still real enough" (Boman 72). intersection Boman uses the following diagram to illustrate between mental life" (68): two entirely different ways "the point of of conceiving of the highest 50 drive forward gather, arrange speak, reckon, speak think Word Reason Deed From Thorlief Boman's Hebrew Thought Compared with Greek. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1960, p. 68. The above diagram communication, illustrates that word (dabhar, logos), central to all is perceived differently by the Greeks and the Hebrews. Starting at the top left and descending diagonally, we see energy displayed in speech and resulting in a deed. language operates. This is the typical Hebraic perception of how From the top right descending diagonally, we follow the course of word in speech through a series of stages that never leave the intellectual realm. This is the Greek perception of how language operates. There is no translation of the spoken or written word into the physical realm. In other words, there is no as the Greeks are concerned. active creative power inherent in language, as far Boman explains that the Hebrew word shem 51 means "name" but can be understood to mean Yahweh's appearance difference between the two is not great for the Hebrews. For them, sh em means the sum total of Yahweh's qualities and activities. "When men see God's since the acts, they see in them God so far as he is knowable to men-, his essence and his qualities . . . . In the name of the covenant-God his person is met face to face and his action is experienced" (Boman 106). In the Hebrew mind, to refer to God's acts is to refer to God. always the act of one mind . . . " (Boman 69). Testament religion "Dabhar is Indeed, "The great men of Old are depicted not because of their piety or their heroism but because God has acted in them or has spoken to them by acting, or like Ezra because he is reading God's word . . . the invisible being of his God is made visible in his acts through which he also speaks" (Boman 113). perception is metonymic. Such a Metonymy is defined as the use of the name of one thing for that of another associated with or suggested by it; the word metonymy comes from the Greek term me tonymia, a change of name (Webster's New Universal Unabridged Dictionary, deluxe Second edition, 1983). Today metonymy is allowed to do duty for the definition of synecdoche as well (Webster's New Int'l. Dictionary, Second edition, 1934). Metonymy is a pervasive principle in Hebraic thought. inherent within their art. It is even found Boman points out that while the pagan paints or sculpts the form of his god, the Hebrew paints or sculpts "the symbol of God's word: the Torah shrine and lamp or else the action of his God and so the sacred history. He does not employ God's image . . . " in his artwork (113). Greeks sought beauty in the representation of stasis, the Hebrews activity of impressions left on the senses to construct beauty. While the relied on the Plato defined art 52 as a mirror, and the Greek artists were naturalists impressions of nature. and realists reflecting their But for the Israelites "the beautiful needed to have no graceful, harmonious form. They found the highest beauty in the formless" (Boman concerned 89) and representations. were more with impressions and sensations than Says Boman, "The Israelite poets are impressionists; repeat only their impressions," not the logic or reason of form (87). they But this is not to say that that which is visible has no meaning for the Israelites. On the contrary, perhaps they attach even more value to physical objects than the Greeks do, for they perceive "comprehensible each material thing as having inherently content" (Boman 90). Thus, the significance of the physical object is not its form nor its mimetic property but rather its essence. of Solomon 5:13 we read: a In Song "His cheeks are like a bed of balsam,/ Banks of sweet- scented herbs;/ His lips are lilies,/ Dripping with liquid myrrh." out that we tend to subordinate "sense-impressions," Boman points and "there is obviously in that judgement a disparagement which is connected with the fact that for us they do stand on the second level. sense-impressions For the Israelites, however, the secondary are basic and decisive, and for this reason they should properly be called primary" (Boman 87). The images in Song of Solomon attributed to the face of a lover are replaced by others within the scripture as well. "As one image . . . can be applied to various parts of the body, so the same part of the body can be represented by two or three groups of images; hence the breasts (Boman are called towers (8.10), fawns (7.4), and date-clusters (7.8)" 83). The ability to represent various parts of the lover's body with one image raises an interesting point. It is easy to assume that what is displayed in Song 53 of Solomon is metaphor and simile. Indeed, Boman says "So natural was it for the Hebrews to think and speak in metaphors and similes that the exegetes forget it occasionally and substitute the direct meaning for the image" (91). But, like Handelman, Boman stresses the predominance of metonymy in Hebrew thinking and devotes much energy in his book to discussing the "universal concept" of the Israelite's thinking (70). "Hebrews always see the general," he says and proceeds to explain that "the particular individual is only a manifestation of the regnant type . . . nor is the abstract separated from the concrete" (70-71). Thus, it is difficult to describe the foregoing descriptions as metaphorical. characteristic If each of the previous images is merely one of the lover's body and can be transferred to represent yet another part of the lover's body, the idea does not exist that one image substitutes one part of the body. Even so, one must remember that representation is not physical as much as essential. The fact that the lover's lips are lilies and drip with myrrh does not merely comment on the nature of the lover's lips but comments on the nature of the lover as well. While representation is a part of Hebrew thinking, substitution is not. This point clearly differentiates Greek from Hebrew thought. rely on mimesis and representation; This property is distinctly Greek. they Metaphor or substitution are not a part of Hebrew thought. Metonymy, the use of a word or phrase to refer not to itself but to something associated with it, is characteristically Hebrew and affords an explanation of the foregoing passage from Song of Solomon. It is not so much that the lips of the singer's lover are like lilies as much as it is that that part of lilies which she appreciates, their beauty, is also a part of her lover. While we employ words to visualize, the Israelites employ I 54 words to express their impressions, neglecting the "photographic appearance" of the object (Boman 74). But because Jewish divinity is not located in being but in language, for God is the word (John 1:1), contiguity, juxtaposition and association provide the foundation for the Rabbinic idea that thing and word are never distinct and the resemblance metaphor, never effaces difference. Handelman explains that the is replaced by the "how much more so," the metonymical, of likeness dependent upon possibility, an if (53). only possible. Possibility is, the a relation always remains It cannot become a certainty because the relationship between word and idea is not one of metaphorical substitution. never cancelled (Handelman 54). Aristotle's hierarchy; there Thus, the literal is There are no categorical statements as in are no proofs precluding further discussion; there is no absolute truth outside of the word and its never ending possibilities. Conclusions are application, revision, always relative and subject to further interpretation, and extension (Handelman and multiple meanings exist simultaneously, 39). Various interpretations resulting from this what if, propositional mode of thought. These distinctions between the manner in which Westerners and Hebrews perceive the nature of language affect the roles time plays in the two cultures. It stands to reason that, within the Western tradition of hierarchical, predicative thought, time would be conceived of as linear and progressive, a series of events. And, naturally, within the Hebraic tradition of shifting ambiguous thought, time would be conceived of as fluid. Boman calls it "the stream of events" (139), but perhaps the image of the sea with its vast depths and rhythmic returns is a better likeness. The impact that this distinction has 55 on the study of narratives, particularly Bierce's, which utilize "keen, darting fragments" (Starrett 38) and not logical constructs, warrants a deeper study of the two perceptions of time. H. G. Ruthrof agrees with Herrnstein Smith that an understanding of the totality of the narrative text is critical to deriving meaning from the narrative itself. He states, "To be able to determine the story's authorial narrative situation, we must first consider the spatial and temporal locus of the point of view from which the presented world is seen" (47). Gerald Prince echoes this idea when he stresses the significance of the order of presentation in any study of a narrative ("Narrative Analysis" reveal is the importance we attach to space. themselves existing within an encapsulated 182). What such statements For Westerners, who perceive space which holds together, identifies, and categorizes everything, space is, in part, a definition of time (Boman 137). But, for the Hebrews, space provides a definition for existence without any regard to the nature of time, for space has never commenced and will never end. Because universality dominates the Israelites' thinking and an individual is only one psychical content contributes to a "collective consciousness" element of the whole, each individual's experiences and (Boman 70-71). This consciousness can be understood to be spatial, for such a consciousness, like space, never commenced and will never end, comprising the entire life of the people like a container which stores the people's whole life from childhood on, as well as the realities which they and those before them experienced (Boman 137). Handelman echoes Boman: "Past, present, and future are simultaneously bound together in . . . an indivisible whole" (36). such, events within a whole are also seen as wholes themselves. Boman As 56 explains that this unity of events of a linear progression: cannot be severed or even analyzed in terms "It is essentially inadmissible to break up or analyse this unity into a series of segments or rapidly consecutive points of time" (Boman 138). Here we see again that points do not constitute being. Instead, the rhythm of the life cycle, like the Hebrews' round dances and accompanying (Boman 134). successive rotation, never ends and is "the great reality" While their repercussions deeds, the events themselves of the world can be mitigated or augmented by are without variation and become essential elements of the people's identity (Boman 138). Boman goes on to say: "It is clear what meaning God's consciousnessness must have had for the Hebrews; the life of a man encompasses a small part of the history of existence, the life of a people a greater part, the life of humanity a still greater part, but the life of God encompasses everything" (139). Hebrews necessarily perceive Thus, as Boman points out, the God's consciousness as universal, too, a world itself in which all events are immutable and eternal (139). So, even while the Hebrews live in time, "time distinctions play a very trifling role for them" (Boman 138). The distinction between Hebrew and Greek senses of time is that one is "clear and exact" and one "unclear and inconsistent" (Boman 142). The European sense of time is a confused mixture of images (thus not only expressions) that we involuntarily make of time, as, for example, when we say: The future lies before us, the past lies behind us. should be clear to everyone, however, that time neither lies, nor is, but goes, comes, and becomes. (Boman 142) It stands, 57 Hebrew verb tenses do not and cannot reflect time as our tenses can do not work within our framework future). of three time-spheres (past, since they present, and While Westerners visualize themselves astride the straight line "time," the Hebrews do not. Westerners direct their gaze forward to the future and turn to peer over their shoulders to the past to define verb tenses by means of any one of a series of points dispersed along this time line (Boman 145). But this time line is not used in Semitic verb tenses, for their verb tenses only communicate the status of action, whether it has been completed, engaged in, or will be completed (Boman 144). is being Since the shortest time in Hebrew is a rhythm, a beat, and "not a point [on a line], nor a distance, nor a duration," lines have no place in Hebraic thought (Boman Because their spatial images have not become 136). entrenched in time, Hebrew images and expressions for time are "simple, clear, and without inner contradictions" (Boman 142). place of duree, duration, Hebrew thought. independent Temps can be translated by the word time, but in Boman prefers the term "occurrence" to explain But he explains that by "occurrence" he does not mean an event. Instead, he thinks of occurrence as "everything that can occur or be accomplished in time, [and leaves] all concrete content out of account, [to] have left the notion of pure occurrence" (144). Boman points out that from the Western viewpoint such an understanding of time is easily considered "timeless because from our view point it lacks the 'spatializing' of our 'time'" (144). Aristotle defined line or a linear line. "objective, physical, time as progressive movement along either a circular As Boman explains, the circular line is used to represent astronomical and measurable time" while the linear line 58 is used to represent "the grammatical time of past, present, and future in which are laid those actions we express in temporal terms" (125-126). critical here is that both representations time according to the metaphor of a line. presentation and spatial 'Western ontology and temporal because reveal Westerners' locus such an ontology in narrative is inherent of in rests upon Aristotle's legacy, is debatable since the Hebrews effectively yet do not believe that spatial perception This emphasis on order of emphasis upon logic and the hierarchy that supports it. a legacy What is and temporal concerns the But the value of such construct narratives are and relevant to narrative. For the Jews, the "text is not . . . a material thing located in a single space and circumscribed by a quantifiable time" (Handelman 37). Because of its creative powers, the original holy Torah, God's word, boasts no bounds (Handelman 39). The physical text is only the embodiment or enclothing of this metaphysical original holy Torah (Handelman 38). "The Torah is not seen as a speculation about the world, but part of its very essence" (Handelman 38). The all- embracing unity of the Torah is the "underlying structure of reality" and "all aspects of existence can be seen as ramifications of and connected to the Torah" (Handelman (Boman 139). consequences abiding facts Handelman's ideas echo Boman when he says, "The of events can be altered, but the events themselves can never be altered" (126). Boman 39); events are indestructible historically Nothing is allowed to be "irrelevant" or outside its scope. states this principle even more succinctly when he explains that dabhar means not only "word" but also "deed" (as thing): ". . . 'word' is in itself not only sound and breath but a reality. accomplishment, Since the word is connected that dabhar could be translated 'effective with its word' (Tatwort); 59 our term 'word' is thus a poor translation for the Hebrew dabhar, because for us 'word' never includes the deed within it" (Boman 66). It is critical to note that the idea of dabhar as thing is not merely that of substance or being; it is more the essence of the world (Handelman 3). The power of the Hebrew word defines the nature of the man who utters it; it is so powerful as to be perceived as the "highest and noblest function of a man" and "identical with his action . . . the deed is the consequence of the basic meaning inhering in dabhar" while not separating (Boman 65). Nevertheless, Boman goes on to say that word from deed, the Israelites still experience the failure of promising words, "not in the fact that the man produced only words deeds, but in the fact that he brought forth a counterfeit and no word, an empty word, or a lying word which did not possess the inner strength and truth for accomplishment or accomplished something evil" (65-66). While Greek language developed definite verb-forms to identify past, present, and future along a linear chronology, Hebrew did not. The Israelite sees more in words than the images called forth by a mimetic language. He sees God, a living essential matter, whose consciousness makes up the world and simultaneously creates the world. This basic difference between perceptions of language has had a profound impact upon the method of textual interpretation. Traditional Western interpretation has conceived of the text as an artifact requiring a peeling away to gain meaning and an absolute hidden by the words comprising the text. textual inherent interpretation within the relies upon words the comprising In contrast, the Hebraic concept of understanding the truth text, and that truth textual is an essence interpretation is 60 not a peeling away but a progressive unfolding of the various meanings constituted entirely by the words of the text. CHAPTER IV AMBROSE BIERCE AND TRADITIONAL HEBRAIC INTERTEXTUALITY One of the main objectives in applying any type of analysis to literature is to gain insight into how we understand or react to a piece of literature in the manner we do. Our perceptions of language perceptions of a piece of literature. cannot help influencing our While Bierce's short stories have received less attention than they merit, that which they have received is due in great part to the stories' language. so would successful manipulation of readers' preconceptions about It stands to reason if our perceptions of language were to change, our perceptions of Bierce's writings. As has already been pointed out, both the nature of time and the nature of narrative are critical elements of Ambrose Bierce's writing and affect readers' interpretations of the world in those stories. evaluate In this chapter, I shall each of the five stories in this study according to, first, the nature of time; second, the nature of language; fourth, the nature of discourse. alternate realities represented third, the nature of narrative; and, These observations will allow us to formulate in the short stories and integrate them with what the Hebrews identify as readers' texts to create a much larger, more fluid text not achievable within the confines of traditional literary critical theory. But first, I will address Bierce's concept of the function of language in order to clarify how he uses words and manipulates the language of his stories to create for readers move beyond an unusual their reading preconceptions experience regarding 61 which language. requires them to 62 Ambrose Bierce advocated: without them" ("Works" 10:59). are simultaneously contrary and inherent to others', reductive such "We think in words. Thus, the terms we use to express our concepts within our thoughts. as Jakobson's self-regulating We cannot think entity Such a view of language is that language is contention characterized by interrelatedness governed by laws of structural integration (Davidson 9). out, "To reduce an act of communication a complete and As Davidson points to its essential elements as Roman Jakobson does . . . would have no meaning for Bierce" (9). She explains that Bierce is more concerned with the polysemous nature of words and the ambiguity of any communication. The themes in Bierce's upon and words which formulaically hierarchically stories are not built represent truth. Remember, he is very much interested in relating the impossible, and this is why he declares, "'Fiction has nothing to say to probability"' 31). the (qtd. in Wiggins If words can only represent, there is nothing with which to communicate impossible. Handelman explains that traditionally the Hebrews perceived any event as a coherent whole instead of consisting of a series of independent factors which, when combined, create a constituency. intertextuality." concept. together "Again, melody This idea is termed "Hebraic is a most accurate In melody, past, present, and future are in rhythmic alternation representation of this simultaneously bound and an indivisible whole. Modern literature has many parallels to this type of time consciousness, most obviously in the stream-of-conciousness stories unaware employ readers this technique" (Handelman stream-of-consciousness along within a character's 36). Many technique thoughts and and of Bierce's often invite carry the short 63 perception of the story as an indivisible whole. Bierce readies us for his use of this technique in the first section of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" when he states, "As these thoughts, which have here to be set down in words, were flashed into the doomed man's brain rather than evolved from it the captain nodded to the sergeant" (11). Readers are informed of the fact that they are presently to begin to follow the thoughts of the "doomed man" and that what appears to be movement from present to past and back again is really the activity of Farquhar's mind and all in the present. Although the Hebrews conceived of the text as an element of the universe, they conceived of the text as making up the world as well. The Jewish Torah, the text, the word, is the "underlying structure of reality; all aspects of existence can be seen as ramifications of and connected to the Torah" (Handelman 39). said that stream-of-consciousness Thus, it could be in the short story echoes the Hebraic idea that the words which make up a text can also make up a character's reality, as well as a reader's reality insofar as a reader is carried along by that character's thoughts. To embrace such a view while interpreting the structure of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" allows readers to consider Peyton Farquhar's literary experience interpretation outside and invites the traditional a completely Western different metaphysics of reading from those reached by Logan, Power, and Crane. To understand the process of removing oneself from this traditional mode of interpretation, consider Ricoeur's claim that "the art of storytelling is not so much a way of reflecting on time as a way of taking it for granted" ("Narrative Time" 175). To deconstruct the story, or to discover the signification of a text "by the careful teasing out of warring forces of 64 signification within the text itself' (Johnson in Dissemination xiv), one must take for granted the structure of time in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" instead of reflecting on it. the narrative Initial preoccupation is linear or nonlinear is secondary with whether chronology in to whether the narrative can be understood in the Hebraic sense of intertextuality, for if this is the case, the entire consideration of time is irrelevant since time is to be taken for granted. What becomes more important is an ontological question, whether the death of Peyton Farquhar actually occurs. Like time in Bierce's stories, several narrative techniques can be analyzed from the Rabbinic perspective to explain their function in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." The significance Bierce attributes to words and his anti-Aristotelian view that words are more than signs is akin to the Rabbinic concept that interpretation is from sense to sense, not from sensible (i.e., the signifier) to the nonsensible (i.e., the signified). no opposing poles to move between. progressive interpretation. Handelman points out that, in "From Work to Text," upon the reader for its perfection (50). is also "inadvertently text as variegated and reliant She goes on to say that Barthes' Rabbinic sensibility" (50). "the theory of the text can coincide only with the activity This principle functions on various levels. same words parallels the character's usage constituent of another text, the readers'. Barthes states that of writing" (81). The way Peyton Farquhar uses words creates his world and becomes a text in itself. independent of Farquhar's. There are Instead, the movement is into the text, a Roland Barthes defines the post-structuralist definition the The way readers use the and in the process becomes a However, this text can be said to be We must believe it when we are told that Farquhar 65 "was now in full possession of his physical senses" and that "they were, indeed, preternaturally keen and alert," that "something in the awful disturbance of his organic system had so exalted and refined them that they made record of things never before perceived" his text. (14). Such was Farquhar's experience; this is Our experience is, to a great extent, his experience, at least until we reach the end of the story and obtain more words which enlarge ours. When added to our text, these new words at the end of the story, "Peyton Farquhar was dead . . . " (18), contribute to another possibility, a what might be. Bierce's conviction Logan's that words are beyond simple signifiers would substantiate postulate that Bierce knew what he was doing, that the author deliberately puts "Biercean metonymy [to] work" in the story (106) and that the story "explores or exploits epistemological issues and the logic upon which this epistemology rests" (102). This metonymy, something referred to by means of a related thing, is thus made quite evident; Farquhar's interpretations of the words he uses and our interpretation experience is complete compose the whole text. Farquhar's reality for him, but for readers Farquhar's reality is simply a metonymic element of our reality. Each interpretation is an association for the entire verbal exchange, but only for us. For Peyton Farquhar, his words and their experience comprise the entirety of his text. Thus, metonymy is well represented. There is therefore no distortion of an absolute reality in the story as many critics argue, but merely a variety of interpretations of the story, each valid, understandable, and simultaneous. Closely aligned with the principle of metonymy, the principle of juxtaposition is central to Rabbinic thought and is also a part of Ambrose Bierce's narrative technique. Juxtaposition is the position of being side by 66 side or close together. The strength of juxtaposition "rests on the powers of two confronted objects, both of which lead in spite of their differing positions to equal consequences" (Kunst 986). Handelman defines juxtaposition "as a display of something which is and is not, or existing on the boundary of the same and the different" (53). For example, in the first sentence of the third section of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," we are told that as Peyton Farquhar fell from the bridge, he "was as one already dead" (13). And yet we read in the next sentence, "From this state he was awakened . . . " (13). Farquhar "was as one already dead" could be read as a simile. line could also be read as a the citation of a juxtaposition. cannot awaken, Farquhar is dead and alive. Since a dead man cannot distinguish Peyton Farquhar's reality is not an exclusive collection of "is's" along a linear chronology. He does not experience first this, then another this, so that what came before the first is not now. is not, only a juxtaposition. There is no is and Readers must identify Farquhar's experience as the character's reality but then juxtapose that identification readers' texts. However, the Or at least he is experiencing both so close together that readers, and probably Farquhar, between the two. That with the rest of This juxtaposition results in an interpretation that allows for a multitude of possibilities and thus a corresponding shift of interpretation concerning what is and what occurs. This might be, the variety of possibilities in continuing interpretation, is the series of coexisting predicates polar opposites Aristotle could not reconcile. which stand as independent predicates retaining out, thus generating their independence and further interpretation. Instead of and equal entities, the Hebrews still not Boman cancelling explains each that this other see 67 phenomenon results from the allows everyone to become Hebraic concept "contemporaneous of contemporaneity, which with a well-remembered occurrence of his past while he is reliving it once more in his memory without forgetting at that moment the year or the epoch in which it took place and the significance it eventually (143). acquired for the remainder of his life" Just as Rabbinic thinking presents us with a process and not a product, so does Farquharian thinking; not seen as independent general and particular, categories. In Rabbinic inside and outside, interpretation create an element of the contiguous whole, another if search for truth. they are mesh to to consider in the Davidson argues that Farquhar's escape never occurs. She postulates that Bierce is more interested with one's perceptual processes at a critical juncture. Bierce's curiosity lies in how "inherited superstitions, past conditionings and subliminal impulses-as much as any external stimulidetermine a character's responses to what they naively choose external reality," implying that Bierce's characters "real" reality. to regard as are out of touch with "Fooled into death," she says, "that character can only try, unsuccessfully, to fool himself out again" (13). attempt to escape death was successful. But the fact remains that the This is one of the if s that Davidson fails to consider-that because Farquhar never knew he died, he did not die. This is the simplest and yet simultaneously most profound might be to consider, the possibility that words actually create reality. postulated that "the existential now preoccupation, retaining" which is a ("Narrative Time" is determined 'making-present,' 173). Ricoeur has by the present of inseparable from awaiting and I suspect that only with a marriage of this z- 68 vivifying power of the word and this if of traditional Rabbinic thought can Bierce's reader resolve Farquhar's death, or escape. The Hebrews perceive creation as an ongoing process. Thus, progressive interpretation is a critical idea in Rabbinic thought. Torah itself, with each verse, letter, and so on, is understood to be the creation process, so each seemingly insignificant element of Torah contains a multitude of meanings and references. Torah is creation Torah thus includes and ever-changing, interpretation, so is interpretation and because and meaning. Clearly, text is understood to be more than just the written composition. Like Barthes, the Hebrews understand text to include the existence of everything in and around it. And since the process of word usage and the concept of things and existence bound; the are intimately signifier-signified interconnected, relationship word and thing are inextricably is inappropriate since the word the actual characterization of the "spirit" of the thing (Boman 60-61). must understand is One this nature of the world and time in Bierce's "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." Peyton Farquhar does not use his language to create a metaphor for a moment of static physical reality; instead, he uses it as a metonymy for a fluid physical reality. The relation between his language and his reality is not substitutive metaphor but contiguous metonymy. Derrida posits, "It remains, then, for us to speak, to make our voices resonate throughout the corridors in order to make up for the break up of presence" (Speech xxviii), or the absence of Being. metonymically constructs The intertextuality to interpenetrate W- his reality, and of the Rabbinic the world of readers' Thus, Peyton Farquhar's word usage he escapes. theory experiences. of interpretation allows Handelman points texts out that 69 for the Jews in the text, not just readers' experiences for interpretation principles but even interpretation were disclosed is included at Sinai with the text. As such, the application of these principles yields not additions to the text, but innate characteristics of the text. is deduced by common human Moreover, Handelman states reasoning is given the same authority and status as that which is derived from the divinely given hermeneutic Readers adhering to such principles readers that Farquhar escapes his death by creating travel until Farquhar is struck They can also an alternate This interpretation is drawn directly with Farquhar (41). as that which is derived from the divinely given hermeneutic principles assigned to all text. redefining ontology. principles" can assign to Peyton Farquhar's reasoning the same divinity and authority determine that "whatever reality, or from the text since "a stunning blow upon the back of the neck" (17) and "a blinding white light blazes all about him" (17). Because this interpretation has been deduced by common human reasoning, it must be viewed as another latent aspect of the text. According to Hebraic intertextuality, each minuscule element of the Hebraic text, even those which appear insignificant, is awarded a position of privilege so that within the Rabbinic text, rigid temporal and spatial distinctions collapse. Thus, the division of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" into three sections, as if three texts, displays intertextuality, too. The structure of the story itself displays metonymy and a multitude of associations. All begins with Peyton Farquhar's mental activity, his interpretation of reality, his use of words and the world he creates with them, just as all begins with Torah-the finality conceives word's vivifying power. Western of each element of a narrative thought's assumption independent of what of 70 precedes and follows at any given moment. The idea that each portion of the text is a discrete unit firmly established in its chronological position is absent in Rabbinic interpretation and could be absent in an analysis of "An Occurrence units are at Owl Creek Bridge." so closely interwoven Contextual reading is fundamental, and contemporaneous considered divorced from any other. that none can and all ever be Bierce's dividing the story serves not to identify for readers the chronology of events, but only the sum of the activity of Farquhar's consciousness in its nonlinear ontogeny. The Torah's constant movement from one domain to another lacks clear demarcation and requires readers to approach Rabbinic in order to reap from it its yield of might bes. thought from within For example, consider that the voice of the omniscient narrator makes statements like, "touched to gold by the early sun, the brooding mists under the banks" and threads itself with Farquhar's consciousness of a "new disturbance" thrust of a knife" (11). that "hurt his ears like the While the narrator is present during the entire discourse, it is critical to recognize that the identity of the narrator changes, creating a fluid shift never Farquhar's experience. separated from readers' experiences nor from The shifting back and forth is so fluid that it is not until the conclusion of the story that we realize that while we were assuming that the activity we were following has been relayed to us by the omniscient narrator, Farquhar has been the narrator. These shifts in discourse often leave readers behind in a wake of confusion. For example, These movements in the fourth paragraph of the first section, we read: left the condemned the sergeant man and standing on the two ends of the same plank . . . This plank had been held in 71 place by the weight of the captain, it was now held by that of the sergeant. At a signal from the former the latter would step aside, the plank would tilt and the condemned man go down between the two ties. The arrangment commended itself to his judgment as simple and effective. He His face had not been covered nor his eyes bandaged. looked a moment at his "unsteadfast footing," then let his gaze wander to the swirling water of the stream racing madly beneath his feet. A piece of dancing driftwood caught his attention and his eyes followed it down the stream. stream! (10-11; How slowly it appeared to move! emphasis What a sluggish Linkin's) Linkin explains that in this passage we see a narrative transfer occur. Previously readers have perceived the narrator as merely recording data" (Linkin 140). paragraph a "camera Initially, "the linguistic structure of this seems to conform to the military narrator's idiolect" readers to determine even a pattern of speech (Linkin 140). readers obtain a new "location" with Bierce's personal pronouns and confusing introduction referents (Linkin find themselves inside Farquhar's thought process. 140). and allows Soon, however, of ambiguous Eventually readers As Linkin points out, "In retrospect we easily pinpoint exactly where the shift in consciousness occurs, but as we read we seem to ease imperceptibly into the consciousness of the condemned man" (140-141). Readers are forced to wander between the different worlds of the two narrators without being able to identify consistently who is who when. Floyd Merrell argues in "Metaphor and Metonymy: A Key to Narrative Structure" that "the mind-and by extrapolation literature, a product of the 72 mind-is world" an active rather than a passive (1). agent in interrelationship Merrell asserts that the next logical assumption is that artistic creation does not entail the mind's merely copying reality. "'invents' with the hitherto unknown realities and thus 'transforms Rather, the mind the world,' sense that it constantly penetrates the physical world to reorganize reinterpret it" (1). voice upon Employing free indirect discourse, Farquhar's experience to ensure in the and Bierce intrudes his that readers recognize that Farquhar's experience is one element of each reader's whole, but at the same time constructs the entirety of Farquhar's whole. Bierce did not punctuate the entire narrative that "Peyton Farquhar was dead" (18). This would not be evident if with his own omniscient remark Otherwise readers could not imagine that what they had just completed reading was only one element of a whole and that in the reality of the soldiers on Owl Creek Bridge Peyton Farquhar's body did hang. To understand this principle according to Handelman a meaning of metonymy "uncovered further, consider that through interpretation dispenses with the particular form in which it is clothed" (75). critical to consider and determine Farquhar's experience never Thus, it is in terms of how that experience is related to, or clothed for, readers, in this case the clothing being a mixture of an omniscient narrator's thoughts and Farquhar's thoughts. This can lead us only to assume that as far as Farquhar is concerned, his experience on Owl Creek Bridge is a valid one, metaphysical or otherwise, and that the experience of the others on the bridge is just as valid. of the experience intertextual 11. 1"'ll- 1 11 and , , , - "- is just as relevant includes all as another's perspectives. , I Farquhar's perception since the experience Remember, according to Im is Rabbinic 73 thought, the text always exceeds any interpretation hence does not provide an adequate completely fulfilled. which can be given it, and meaning that can be finalized or So, too, are readers unable at the finished reading of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" to provide an adequate meaning that can be finalized or completely fulfilled. another consideration, truth. They are left only with another might be, a continuing interpretation and are no closer to the Even though the omniscient narrator commands authority at the end of the story, readers have experienced an escape was not Peyton Farquhar, who was it? from death with someone. If it Having succumbed to that which is all silence and darkness, Peyton Farquhar ceases to speak and so ceases to be, believing until he no longer has the ability to believe that he has escaped death. Ironically, it is only in his dying that he succeeds in his escape. What readers of Peyton Farquhar's story assume to be objective reality turns out to be just as much the character's consciousness. Halpin Frayser's story, which readers assume to be a dream, turns out to be what is assumed objective reality. As usual, Bierce's manipulation of time startles readers and prevents them from resolving the tale. The tale is introduced with the epigraph from Hali, "a bogus mystic" (Davidson 103): For by death is wrought greater change than hath been shown. Whereas in general the spirit that removed cometh back upon occasion, and is sometimes seen of those in flesh (appearing in the form of the body it bore) yet it hath happened that the veritable body without the spirit hath walked. And it is attested of those encountering who have lived to speak thereon that a lich so raised up hath no natural affection, nor remembrance thereof, but only hate. Also, it is 74 known that some spirits which in life were benign become by death evil altogether.-Hali (395; italics Bierce's) The foregoing epitaph and a fourth section provide a frame for an otherwise identical structure to that found in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." In the first section, we are introduced to Halpin Frayser who awakes from a dreamless sleep in a forest to whisper a name, which we fail to appreciate at this point. "Catherine Larue," the irony of Subsequently we are provided an explanation as to why he finds himself asleep in a forest. and dreams this time. until a terrifying ends. He falls asleep again We travel with him through the forest in his dream ghostly apparition of his mother appears, and the section In section two we are provided with the character's background information, just as in section two of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." section three we return to the confrontation In with the ghostly apparition, "the thing so like, yet so unlike his mother" (401); again, the irony is not clear yet. Presumably we still follow Frayser's dream, for we leave section three with the statement "Halpin Frayser dreamed that he was dead" (402). In the fourth section we accompany a sheriff and his man at arms as they search through the woods for a madman recently spotted there. We learn the story of Catherine Larue and that the madman for whom the sheriff searches is her husband who murdered her. Ultimately they come upon a body, which we know to be Halpin Frayser, lying upon Catherine Larue's grave. sheriff remembers that "the murdered we understand the irony mother's grave woman's name that Halpin Frayser died unknowingly and the double irony that, apparition murdered him. had been Halpin When the Frayser" (408), on his in some form and fashion, that Frayser's story, which readers assume to be 75 a dream, turns out to be what is assumed objective reality, the inverse of their reading experience of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." of Halpin Frayser" Occurrence reverses the narrative circumstances at Owl Creek Bridge" to startle readers from resolving Thus, "The Death found in "An again and to prevent them the tale. Once more the concept of linear time fails readers in their attempt to determine a chronology of events. The first section of the story introduces Halpin Frayser and sets the scene for the activities to take place. second section of Peyton Farquhar's story, Halpin Frayser's Like the second section details his past and provides an explanation for the circumstance in which we find him. Readers begin their reading with, "In his youth Halpin Frayser had lived with his parents in Nashville, Tennessee" (398). the character's consciousness Having already entered via his dream, readers assume that they maintain that position as they move into his history in the second section. It is not at all unusual that the character should be spurred to think of his past at the sight of his dead mother. So, adhering to a concept of linear time, readers are inclined to assume this statement is a displacement from the chronological activity of events in the story. They fail to recognize the intertextuality of the story, that the tale encompasses the past and the future in the present. Nevertheless, the second section is another display of Bierce's stream-of- consciousness technique and can very well be understood to be in the present as much as any other element of the text. establishes His use of the past perfect tense what appears to be an ackowledgement of linear time. But this appearance disintegrates with the rest of the story as such tools as verb tense, 76 confusing referents, and ambiguous pronouns continue to undermine appearances. After awakening in the woods to utter the name, Catherine Larue, Frayser falls asleep again to dream, and "he thought he was walking along a dusty road" (396). But before the end of the paragraph, we read, "Soon he came to a parting of ways" (396), not "soon he thought he came to a parting of ways." By dropping such key phrases, Bierce makes it easy for readers to forget that they follow a dream. Indeed, it would appear that this is his objective, for at the end of the first section, Frayser determines not to submit to the evil around him, the blood and the "evil existences" which haunted his way, and begins to write a poem. When at the end of the story a detective and a deputy sheriff find Frayser dead, the victim clutches a poem, and readers are again forced to determine whether they were following a dream or not when they read, "He wrote with terrible rapidity . . . " (398). For a possible interpretation of the foregoing events, consider Ricoeur's contention that "It is our preoccupation, not the things of our concern, that determines the sense of time" ("Narrative Time" 173). He explains that what happens in time, while "not reducible to the representation of linear time," is nevertheless preoccupation subjected to such interpretation because the time of our was first measured and seasons ("Narrative Time" 172). by the natural environment, shifting light But he points out that the "day is not an abstract measure; it is a magnitude which corresponds to our concern and to the world ("Narrative Time" 173). The day measures the time of labor, that "in which it is time to do something" ("Narrative Time" 173). It is important to see the distinction in the meanings of the "now" which belongs to the time of WAWA wo mWNNWMNWANWWM -0-0-op-ow 77 preoccupation and the "now" which belongs to the abstract moment, which is a part of a series which defines the line of ordinary time. The existential now is determined by the present of preoccupation, which is a "making-present," retaining. It is because, inseparable from in preoccupation, awaiting concern itself into this making-present and to obliterate and tends to contract its dependency with regard to awaiting and retaining that the now isolated in this way can fall prey to the representation of the now as an isolated abstract instant. ("Narrative Time" 173) Thus, we see that time does not define experiences; experiences. rather, time is defined by Such a phenomenon in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" allows the would-be hero an escape from death. In "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" when Bierce writes, "As these thoughts, which have here to be set down in words, were flashed into the doomed man's brain rather than evolved from it the captain nodded to the sergeant" (11), he informs readers they are to follow Farquhar's stream of consciousness by following those words set down. But in "The Death of Halpin Frayser" the stream of consciousness is not introduced so blatantly. Readers have difficulty recognizing the phenomenon because of its subtlety. But by the time they read, "Soon he came to a parting of ways . . . " (396) during the recitation of the dream, readers recognize they are within Frayser's consciousness, for the physical character did not really come to a parting of ways. A third person narrator would have stated, "Soon he a parting of ways . . . ." an indivisible whole; thought he came to It is only at the end of the tale that we see the text as we see that Frayser's consciousness and experiences are 78 synonymous. We are reminded that the text is not a material thing located in a single space and circumscribed by a quantifiable time. Just as readers of Peyton Farquhar's story who want to discover all the text can offer might follow Riceour's suggestion and take for granted the structure of time instead of reflecting on it, so might readers of Halpin Frayser's story. This taking time for granted allows readers to concentrate on more important questions: What did Halpin Frayser experience? Did he experience a dream? Did he experience something beyond his dream? he experience both? While these questions are necessarily impossible to answer, several narrative techniques in this story can be analyzed Rabbinic viewpoint to gain a multitude of considerations can Or did from the about what the text offer. Identifying the nature of narrative techniques in Halpin Frayser's story is difficult until we recall Barthes' idea that "the theory of the text can coincide only with the activity of writing" (81). as writers too; readers actively participate written composition, literature. Barthes conceived of readers in creating the meaning of any an idea akin to Fish's, that readers themselves "make" The importance of a marriage of reading and writing a text was apparent in our analysis of "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" and also becomes apparent in an analysis of "The Death of Halpin Frayser." Halpin Frayser, awareness. "creatures experiences heightened sensory The trees are noxious, and "audible and startling whispers" of so obviously not of earth" fill his ears (397). Frayser's experience use like Peyton Farquhar, Readers must accept as valid and incorporate it into their own text. a character's words even while creating their own text Readers different from the 79 character's text, for the character's is a constituent of their own text. the context of Frayser's dream. Consider As with "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," readers fail to recognize until the end of "The Death of Halpin Frayser" that the assumed context is inappropriate, or at least questionable. a text even at a different level in Halpin Frayser's tale. provided with Frayser's But there exists Not only are readers words via stream-of-consciousness; not only do readers use those words to create their own text; they are suddenly provided with a written text within a written text, a poem Frayser writes. And to complicate initially the matter the second written text, as far as readers understand it, is not really written, but is merely part of a dream. But in the fourth section, the sheriff reads a poem "that sounds like Bayne" (408), and readers cannot help wondering how the poem was composed. It might be argued that the poem was written by Bayne and that Farquhar carried it with him, or knew it by heart, and reenacted its composition, attributing the original act to himself, within the context of his dream. However, Bayne clearly did not write the poem. collected works, and "that poem is not among them" (408). Jaralson owns Bayne's Had the poem been written by Bayne and inadvertently left out of the published collection, it would at least have been completed. prepare us. Bierce even provides foreshadowing to Although Halpin Frayser had never before written poetry and "could not have written correctly a line of verse to save himself no knowing when the dormant faculty might wake . . . " (399). question most likely seems to be, "Under what circumstances Frayser write that poem?" not "Who wrote the poem?" . . . , there was Thus, the did Halpin 80 In attempting to answer such a question, we find the importance of the Hebraic idea of progressive interpretation, continuing body. be. what ifs. a consideration of all those The poem was composed in a dream but found on a dead Frayser dreamed he was a poet, but readers are told he was not but might What if both statements are true? The poem is metonymic. The problem is that the whole to which the poem must be related is not obvious, for it appears both in Frayser's dream as well as in what appears to be the objective reality which follows it when Holker and Jaralson find the composition on the dead man's body. produces Both. Readers cannot reconcile all these elements of the text. the poem? Stream-of-consciousness, or actual manual What activity? The poem is metonymic, and readers must struggle to discover the whole with which the poem is associated. This principle of metonymy concerning the mysterious aligned with the principle of juxtaposition. poem is closely Recalling that the principle of juxtaposition may be interpreted as a display of something which is and simultaneously is not, we are reminded of Halpin Frayser's poem, or, more precisely, of Halpin Frayser as poet. While readers believe they follow Frayser's dream, Frayser announces, "I shall relate my wrongs, . . . -I, helpless mortal, a penitent, an unoffending poet" (397). a Then the omniscient narrator intrudes and tells us, "Halpin Frayser was a poet only as he was a penitent: in his dream" (397). narrator's statement But according all elements to Rabbinic Frayser's tlllll readers remove the omniscient text and deem modes of interpretation, of the text (time, self-contained 101,14,10% from Automatically, experience, it objective information. this is unacceptable sensation, being) cohere since and are within the text which is all that exists, and thus the text defines - - - - 0 wwammomm 81 the world. Thus, Halpin Frayser is a poet, even while he is not. paradoxical element of juxtaposition pervades the short story. This As early as the fourth sentence, we read: "He lived in St. Helena, but where he lives now is uncertain, for he is dead" (395). Just like Peyton Farquhar, then, Halpin Frayser is dead and alive; his being exists precisely on the boundary of the same and the different. Even the evil apparition displays juxtaposition, for it is a "thing so like, yet so unlike his mother" (401); it is a zombie, a dead body without a living soul. (402), he was dead. Indeed, while "Halpin Frayser dreamed that he was dead" How can one dead dream of death? only a juxtaposition. There is no is and is not, Just as with "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" readers need to identify Frayser's experience as the character's juxtapose that identification with the rest of readers' world. reality but then to texts to create another The elements juxtaposed in the tale of Halpin Frayser lie so close together that resolution is impossible. All things are valid, and no thing can be cancelled for the sake of another. We are required to consider all possible yields of the text, not as additions to but as innate characteristics of the text. And, just as with interpretations obtained through the use of ordained hermeneutic principles, all these possibilities are significant as well. Thus we assign to Halpin Frayser's reasoning the same preeminence that we assign to our own. The structure of the story displays the Hebraic notion of intertextuality, too. The failure of the four sections to appear in chronological order supports the concept that traditional, logical into "The Death of Halpin Frayser." Western thinking cannot provide insight Each portion of the text is not a discrete unit firmly established in its chronological position; all units are so closely 82 interwoven separation and simultaneously present that none can be considered from any other at any given moment. in We cannot simply say Halpin Frayser lies down; he sleeps; he awakens and speaks; he dreams; he dies. may appear to be the case, at least as long as we follow Halpin Frayser. when we follow Holker and Jaralson to the discovery suddenly this string of events is questionable. This But of the dead Frayser, What appears to be movement from present to past and back again is also the activity of Frayser's mind and all in the present. So what can we say? Inexplicability is the very success of the story, for that inexplicability yields numerous considerations. Nowhere does the text outside Frayser indicate that he does not actually walk while he dreams he walks. We only assume he has fallen asleep on his mother's grave and remains there for the entire dream. But his experiences on the "haunted way" he walks (396) blend with his dream and thereby diffuse the distinction between the two. Readers must recognize this Hebraic intertextuality in the story in order to understand that it is the essence of this story to be irresolvable. Otherwise, the fact that it cannot be explained logically will lead readers to determine that "the text . . . cannot sustain itself under the weight of its overload. The result is a sham of the whole process of interpretation" (Davidson 113). The fault for the sham lies in the interpretation, not in the story. The illogical nature of "The Death of Halpin Frayser" that can only be embraced intertextually is also a part of "The Man and the Snake" and is most evident in, again, Bierce's narrative techniques. concern in this story. Time is not so great a While the second section of the story interrupts the 83 linear progression of events, it does not, as in the previous stories, return to events of the past. presence in Rather it merely studies Harker Brayton and explains his Dr. Druring's house and the events take place in that house. describes the environment Here the concept within which of intertextuality is displayed not in a fusion of time but merely a fusion of readers' and Brayton's texts. But readers must not get caught up in the relative chronology of the story, for intertextuality remains the key to understanding the tale. Again, "It is our preoccupation, not the things of our concern, that determines the sense of time" ("Narrative Time" 173). As in Bierce's stream-of-consciousness other two stories, technique. this intertextuality In chapter two it was introduced with the noted that the key to the success of "The Man and the Snake" lies in Bierce's use of stream-ofconsciousness, for it allows readers they retain until they encounter story. to acquire Dr. Druring's Brayton's perceptions Even though the written text informs readers that perceptions, which at the end of the only Brayton's attention "disclosed . . . the coils of a large serpent" (143), readers do not question Brayton's attention and attribute to it more authority than it warrants. When the story ends, and Dr. Druring discovers a stuffed snake under the bed, it becomes evident that the text Harker Brayton compiles in the story is contrary to the text Dr. Druring compiles when he states that Brayton "died in a fit" (148). incorporate Dr. The texts that readers compile thus change accordingly to Druring's text. This change reflects the principle of metonymy in "The Man and the Snake." formulate Each text compiled is an association of the whole and is required to any hypothesis oamom, concerning what actually happened in the story, 84 for many things happen simultaneously. A snake with suns" "two dazzling (146) for eyes coils beneath a bed, and "its breath mingled with the atmosphere" (145) which Brayton himself breathes. But, too, Dr. Druring finds that Brayton "died in a fit" and discovers, not a live snake coiled beneath the bed, but a stuffed snake; "its eyes were two shoe buttons" (148). Neither of these two texts distorts an absolute reality, for no absolute reality exists represented. to be Both texts merely provide two interpretations, two preoccupations of a fluid ontology, both valid, both understandable simultaneous. It is likely that readers' interpretations provide and a third. Thus, the whole is the entire text which can be compiled, including all the what abouts applicable (what about the fact that Brayton saw a malignant snake under the bed and Dr. Druring saw a stuffed one?), and each sub-text is an association and performs metonymically. There is not one which can be substituted for the other, for readers can verify the validity of both Brayton's and Druring's texts, having experienced both. Aristotle's metaphorical structure of logic, with its "If this, then this" predicative hierarchy, is not the only way to explain "The Man and the Snake." We see in the story other elements of Hebraic intertextuality as well. In "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" juxtaposition was evident in the simultaneous life and death of Peyton Farquhar, who "was as one already dead" but who nevertheless awakens (13). In "The Man and the Snake" this same type of juxtaposition, simultaneous states of life and death, can be found in the treatment of the snake. "The snake's malignant head" (146) is stuffed; eyes were two shoe buttons" (148). malignant and stuffed and inanimate. "its two Thus, the snake is both animate and Again, we see the importance of an 85 interpretation possibilities that allows and concerning a subsequent what is. character's for consideration corresponding shift of interpretation Davidson's claim that "external stimuli . . . determine a responses to what they naively choose to regard as external reality" (13) is again arguable. themselves (145). of a multitude of what abouts or with Bierce tells us, "These thoughts shaped greater or less definition in Brayton's mind and begot action" The word's vivifying power precludes any choice Brayton may have about what Davidson terms external reality. Brayton's "existential now is determined by the present of preoccupation, which ("Narrative Time" 176). Davidson's. is a 'making-present"' Words define Brayton's reality as much as they define But Brayton did not have the opportunity to include Dr. Druring's words in his own text. Davidson did. This fusion of texts in "The Man and the Snake" is echoed in the narrative technique and shows once the text but is a textual constituent again that interpretation is not outside which intrudes upon readers' This fluidity which allows the all-embracing experience. Hebraic Torah to shift from sphere to sphere and issue to issue without clear demarcation is reflected in the narrative structure of Bierce's short story. An omniscient narrator relates the entirety of sections two and four, but sections one and three subtly employ free indirect discourse. Section one opens with, "Stretched at ease upon a sofa, in gown and slippers, Harker Brayton smiled as he read . . . " (142). The character continues to read until "A train of reflection followed-for Brayton was a man of thought-" (143). Then he sees the two points of light, which "shone with, it seemed to him, an added fire" (143). Finally, Brayton saw "almost directly under the footrail of the bed, the coils of a large serpent-the 86 points of light were its eyes!" (143). transition in narrative perspective. The preceding excerpts relay a subtle The first two statements clearly present an omniscient narrator since he refers to the character in third person. The last excerpt, however, just as clearly has Brayton exclaiming, "the points of light were its eyes!" (143); by the end of the story we realize this to be Brayton's editorial, for a stuffed snake has no light in its eyes. The actual transition occurs with the third statement, and the key phrase is one Bierce uses over and over again, "it seemed to him" (143). Bierce is not interested in writing fiction to represent reality; he is interested in making "what is related seem probable in the reading-seem true" (Wiggins 31). ambiguity Because of the of the phrase "it seemed to him," readers are unable to determine to which narrator the statement belongs. to an omniscient Initially it is reasonable to attribute it narrator because of the third person pronouns "him" and "he" in the sentence: "He thought, too, that they might have moved a trifle-" (143). The passage continues until we read the last statement, and here we realize that the identity of the narrator has become questionable. Just as in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge" and "The Death of Halpin Frayser" these shifts in discourse leave readers confused, and readers are forced to wander between the different worlds of the two narrators identify consistently who is who when. without being able to This ambiguity is in essence the tychism Peirce articulated and is essential to the nature of this story seen Hebraically or otherwise. Grenander produce points out that in order to be successful terror stories must fear, either by relating danger or by relating something thought to 87 be dangerous. She identifies Bierce's best tales of ironical terror as belonging to two groups: those in which the actual situation is harmful, with the protagonist conceiving it to be harmless and reacting accordingly; which the actual situation is harmless, and those in with the protagonist conceiving it to be harmful and reacting accordingly . . . . What the reader's grasp of events will be is controlled by the narration. Grenander's last statement is especially (94) critical, for it reveals her struggle with that nature of language which Peirce termed tychism, the uncertainty or indeterminacy of language. To resolve her struggle, Grenander decides that someone, in this case Harker Brayton, is guilty of misconception, perceptions of reality must align with each other. that according to Hebraic there is no identifiable contrary to readers. intertextuality absolute reality; no for all But it must be remembered character a character misconceives may merely since conceive The conceptions are merely different. What for Harker Brayton is true can very well be not true for readers. This irresolvability points out the pleasure of interpreting the story within the context of Hebraic intertextuality. "A Psychological Shipwreck" tells the story of William Jarrett, who has embarked on a voyage to America from England, and his out-of-body experience during the voyage. Metaphysically transferred from one ship to another without his knowledge, Jarrett encounters on the second ship, The Morrow, the fiancee of his travelling companion on the first ship, City of Prague. On the first ship Jarrett initiates a discussion with Miss Harford concerning a book she is reading, "Denneker's Meditations," until the ship 88 encounters bizarre atmospheric conditions and eventually Jarrett sinks. awakens aboard the City of Prague to discover that his body, at least, has remained there through the duration of the ship's passage. Doyle, his travelling companion, has also been reading He discovers "Denneker's Meditations" and only then learns that Doyle and Miss Harford have been engaged to be married. He never relates to Doyle his metaphysical experience, not even after The Morrow disappears at sea and Miss Harford is never heard from again. Quite unlike the foregoing tales, "A Psychological Shipwreck" is not made up of irreconcilable texts, although there is more than one text within the story. As usual, at the end of the story readers are required to incorporate more than one text into the whole. there Until halfway through the story, it appears William Jarrett, the first person narrator, informs exists only one text. us: In the summer of 1874 1 was in Liverpool, whither I had gone on business . . . . Having finished my business, and feeling the lassitude and exhaustion incident to its dispatch, I felt that a protracted sea voyage would be both agreeable and beneficial, so instead of embarking for my return on one of the many fine passenger steamers I booked for New York on the sailing vessel Morrow .... (494) Readers have no reason to question they later read the following passage this first person from narration, "Denneker's even when Meditations": To sundry it is given to be drawn away, and to be apart from the body for a season; for, as concerning rills which would flow 89 each other the weaker is borne across along by the stronger, so there be certain of kin whose paths intersecting, their souls do bear company, the while their bodies go fore-appointed ways, (495) unknowing. assume they have yet to encounter Jarrett's being drawn away Readers apart from his body for a season. and However, when, after Jarrett awakens to find he has been on the City of Prague since its departure from Liverpool three weeks previous, they understand that the tale began in the midst of the out-ofbody experience. beginning What prevented them from recognizing this fact was that Jarrett in the himself had been unable to recognize the fact and had even provided an explanation for his passage on the Morrow. Thus, we have the written text entitled "A Psychological Shipwreck" before readers, the written text entitled "Denneker's Meditations" before the readers, Doyle, and Miss Harford, and, initially, at least, Jarrett's text. Jarrett, Eventually, however, they all fuse to become one, and explicable at that, as we shall see. Here again we see at work the principle Grenander outlined, that This readers' perceptions of what they read are controlled by the narration. control is no less remarkable since the story does not call for reconciliation of irreconcilable texts. Indeed, the explanation of the events of two texts, readers' and Jarrett's, is provided quite candidly by the third text, the excerpt from "Denneker's Meditations." a reader nor Jarrett Nothing remains to be reconciled, for neither is privy to information the other does not have; text has become readers' text in this case. noteworthy Instead, what makes this tale is that it reverses the techniques to achieve, nevertheless, the same effect. Jarrett's Bierce uses in his previous tales A strange inexplicable event has 90 Graciously, Bierce occurred; how is it to be integrated into the readers' texts? has provided us with an answer to that question in the form of "Denneker's Meditations." :Davidson declares that Bierce's "stories of language and inconsistencies Shipwreck" is not one of them. delineate multiple levels between them" (14), but "A Psychological What is interesting here is that the same effect shifting narrative point of view typical of free indirect discourse concealed Here, the the multiplicity of texts within the story until the tale's end. is reversed, technique the Previously, is achieved through a new method, first person narration. for the narrative in "Denneker's Meditations" clarifies the narratives in the other texts composing "A Psychological Shipwreck." Particularly interesting is the role of time in "A Psychological Shipwreck." Unlike the previous stories, this tale has no divisions into Thus, we have no switching from past to present in terms of a linear sections. chronology. Bierce manipulates readers' conceptions of time to promote the coincidence which makes the story remarkable. What we have is a type of the Hebraic concept of contemporaneity that Boman articulates. he explains, allows everyone to become "contemporaneous Contemporaneity, with a well- remembered occurrence of his past while he is reliving it once more in his memory without forgetting at that moment the year or the epoch in which it took place and the significance it eventually life" (143). acquired for the remainder of his During the last half of the tale when Jarrett reorients himself aboard the City of Prague, he is, in a sense, reliving a well-remembered event of his past, living it once more in his memory without forgetting it occurred. Herein lies the mystery. linear chronology, they If readers continue to adhere to the concept of a will struggle to determine when, along the schemata, 91 did occur. the events recorded Doyle assures Jarrett that Jarrett has been And yet "right as a trivet all the time, and punctual at [his] meals" (496). Jarrett and Janette Harford have become (495). well acquainted aboard the Morrow On the other hand, an analysis of this event from the Hebraic point of view explains in terms of simultaneous the event experiences, one of which does not necessarily cancel out or substitute for the other. reveals juxtaposition functioning integrally in This same point also "A Psychological Shipwreck." While Jarret is aboard the City of Prague, he is also aboard the Morrow, Again, we are existing within the same and the different simultaneously. reminded of Riceour's postulate that the now is a "making-present" and that preoccupation is constructed ("Narrative by preoccupation, Time" 173). "A Psychological Shipwreck" is a beautiful example of the Hebraic concept interpretation of progressive inherent within intertextuality. Just as the Hebrews believe the text is more than the written composition, so too does William Jarrett. Not only faced with the printed and bound copy of "Denneker's Meditations," experienced the text. interpretation that he is also faced with the contemporaneity of having We are reminded of the principle within Hebraic textual grasped reality experiences with Bierce's previous replaces representation. Like our stories we actually experience with the character events which make up the tale we read. Physical reality remains fluid, and again we see that the relation between the character's language and his physical reality is not mimetic but metonymic. "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" works differently from "A Psychological Shipwreck." In both stories a strange, inexplicable event has occurred and readers wonder how it is to be integrated into their text. Only 92 two short pages, "The Difficulty of Crossing the Field" again utilizes Bierce's technique of variegated narrative, but the various texts do not reconcile. objective narrator begins the tale An with: One morning in July, 1854, a planter named Williamson, living six miles from Selma, Alabama, was sitting with his wife and a child on the veranda of his dwelling. lawn, perhaps Immeditately in front of the house was a fifty yards in extent between road, or, as it was called, the "pike." the house and public Beyond this road lay a close- cropped pasture of some ten acres, level and without a tree, rock, or any natural or artificial object on its surface. not even a domestic animal in the field. At the time there was In another field, beyond the pasture, a dozen slaves were at work under an overseer. The most remarkable objective nature. characteristic of this passage (162) is its undeniably It reads like a legal account without any omniscient or editorializing statements. We follow Williamson as he tosses away his cigar, rises to stride across the pike and greet the Wrens, his passing neighbors, and enters the pasture in front of his house, where he simply disappears. In the passing carriage, the neighbor's son asks, "'Why, father, what has become of Mr. Williamson?"' (163). The narrator intrudes: "It is not the purpose of this narrative to answer that question" (163) and then proceeds to introduce Mr. Wren's account of the event. Here the narrative point of view shifts, not subtly as in the previous stories but quite obviously; the entire account is quoted. Mr. Wren tells us, "My son's exclamation caused me to look toward the spot where I had seen the deceased [sic] an instant before, but he was not there, nor was he anywhere visible" (163) ([sic] in Bierce's text). After Mr. 93 Wren's testimony the limited narrator returns to inform us, might have been expected, was corroborated "This testimony, as in almost every particular by the only other eyewitness (if that is a proper term)-the lad James. . . . The boy James Wren had declared at first that he saw the disappearance, but there is nothing of this in his testimony given in court" (163-164). logical or otherwise, for Williamson's explanation, limited narrator tells us later, certainly effectively comments disappearance, and the "what has been here related is all that is known of the matter" for Williamson's disappearance, There is never an (164). By refusing to provide an explanation by stressing only what is known, Bierce on the limitations of human existence and lets readers know that any context may be merely constructed; it may not be absolute. No text seeks reconciliation with another in "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" because no character is privy to information another does not have. Because the story is so short, there is no time differentiation between narratives. We proceed with Williamson through a series of actions-and then he did this, and then he did this-until he disappears. testimonies concerning the disappearance, disappearance. which, of course, should follow the Time is an issue because we perceive of existence in time as akin to existence within space. he disappeared; Then we follow the Thus, we wonder where Williamson went when we are concerned with what space he subsequently occupies. However, the Hebraic concept of time, which does not consider time relative to space, helps explain the disappearance that for the Hebrews more appropriately. Boman explains "the abstract never separates from the concrete" (70-71). So, in a sense, Williamson has quite possibly merely transferred from one essence of the collective consciousness to another. The Hebraic predilection 94 toward here perceiving events by Williamson's that past, present, in terms disappearance, and future are of stream-of-consciousness bound represented the idea reflects for his disappearance simultaneously is together in rhythmic What the written text reveals initially alternation and in an indivisible whole. is Williamson's present; what it reveals subsequently is his past or future, Just like the written text, as far as the when he exists in that other essence. Hebrews might be concerned, Williamson's text is not a material thing located in a single space and circumscribed by a quantifiable time. Keeping such ideas in context is critical, and in "The Suitable Bierce puts forth his treatise Surroundings," a text. that context defines the nature of The main character, a writer, insists his reader read his ghost story at night in a house abandoned in a dark forest only by the light of a tallow, because readers must put themselves "into the frame of mind appropriate to the sentiment of the piece" they read (164). As writer of "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field," Bierce makes the same point that suitable surroundings play This supernatural an important role in defining his written material. experience cannot be explained naturally; it requires readers to put themselves in the appropriate frame of mind, in this case, Hebraic intertextuality. The narrative techniques Bierce uses in "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" indicate the advantage of interpreting the story within the concept of Readers are first struck by the formal legalese of the Hebraic intertextuality. third person narrator and environment are provided in which Williamson's with a detailed examination of the occurs, disappearance even to the that they know the distance between the house and the pike, fifty yards. mn - -- R. '401 extent But WOMAVAMMOWAVOMPOW 95 the of the events is distinct from inexplicable nature disturbing Herein lies the juxtaposition and well-marked environment. that familiar of Hebraic intertextuality, that display of something which is and simultaneously is not. Bierce spreads before readers of "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" a commonand objectivity, scene using techniques of realism, accurate description, place to create a mere panorama. But this realism serves only to highlight the supernatural and twist, reverse, and topple the "certainties" of the world. Suddenly, in the midst of this mundane scene a bizarre event occurs and the between requires reconciliation occurs. But this is not possible. comfortable; a Indeed, it does. supernatural event and the which it The surroundings are too familiar and too event should occur within a supernatural The world is never mundane and commonplace. uncertain, and always a mystery, the world is as supernatural disappearance. in environment context. Inexplicable, as Williamson's Bierce has been up to his old tricks and relied upon readers' assumptions about the world and their place in it to make the world seem real and familiar. No one in the story can provide an accurate assessment of what happened to Mr. Williamson. Neither can anyone outside the story, because all rely upon the same predicative questions concerning their world. hierarchy to formulate logic and answer And they base this logic on what they see. Bierce understands this method of relating to the world and subverts it. He questions the validity of the term "eyewitness" (163), points out that James Wren's testimony does not support his claim that he saw the disappearance (164), and indicates the event had occurred "before [Mrs. Williamson's] and rendered her mad and incompetent to testify (163). eyes" The disappearance 96 even occurred while "Williamson was seen by all three [the Wrens and their black boy Sam], walking leisurely across the pasture" (163). The field hands did not testify because "None . . . had seen him at all" (164), although those who did testify had not actually seen him either, so their testimonies proved inconclusive. Bierce even goes so far as to have Wren say that he looked "'where I had seen the deceased . . . before, but he was not . . . anywhere visible"' (163). The key word here is visible. Bierce does not write, "but he was He does not presume that Williamson no longer exists. not . . . anywhere." Bierce recognizes only that Williamson no longer exists as he has been known But, "The courts decided that Williamson was dead, and his to exist previously. estate was distributed according to law" (164). Logically speaking, the story is absurd. But this is Bierce, and knowing so helps us to consider and analyze the story appropriately, traditional idea that what we see is what we get. concerning Williamson's disappearance outside the Just as testimonies support the theory that we do not Even with a always get what we see, so does "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field." written text before them, readers do not read a story complete with introduction, the conflict, story is evaluated absurdity recedes. climax, resolution, and denouement. within the context of intertextuality, However, when the story's Since, according to Rabbinic thought, the text always exceeds any interpretation assigned to it, it does not provide an adequate meaning that can be finalized or completely fulfilled. Instead it becomes a vivid text with an incredible number of possible interpretations, bes, for the only boundaries of reality are our perceptions. what might Thus, in "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" there are no opposing poles to move between, 97 a progressive are required to move into the text to formulate and readers interpretation. this chapter, But the story is unlike the first three stories interpreted in which actually present readers of with various interpretations the world within their written texts, or even the fourth story, which actually interpretation explains the context. of the world necessary to place the story within Instead, "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field" distorts what readers might call absolute reality and undermines their traditional concept of how they see the world without providing an interpretation planter Williamson did live as you and I. However, he did not die. of that distortion. The But he no longer lives as you and I. Again we see the coexisting predicates Aristotle could not reconcile and that substitutive metaphor does not work in the story. Nor do we see in "The Difficulty of Crossing the Field" the metonymy which we saw at work in the other stories. Bierce merely ends the story at its call for the metonymic principle that would indubitably requires readers suggest simultaneous ontologies. This to formulate their own interpretations of what happened in the story and highlights the principle that that act of interpretation is a part of the continuous revelation of the text, a total and complete experience characterize exposing connective Readers themselves must the inner specific reality of the thing they read, and they can do so if they operate intertextually references, relations. and perceive a multitude of meanings and relevant to all time and place within every statement, letter of the text. realities and Merrell thus 'transforms penetrates the physical remarks that "the mind the world,' world to 'invents' word or hitherto unknown in the sense that it constantly reorganize and reinterpret it" (1). In Difficulty of Crossing a Field" we see again grasped reality instead of "The 98 representation; readers' minds must recognize to transform the world and reinterpret previously realities unknown it. The tales of Peyton Farquhar's death, Halpin Frayser's, and Harker Brayton's, and the tales of the disappearances of Janette Harford and the planter Williamson are more than the result of an intricate weaving of a tale by a master story-teller. They exemplify primary characteristics of Hebraic thought in direct opposition to those of Western literary critical theory. non-linear perception of time, the use of metonymy, The and the varied interpretations of a text due to the creative power of the word combine to create mystical tales readers cannot resolve. interpretation, while it provides Even the Rabbinic method of for the consideration of alternate insights into the story, leaves readers resigned to the power of the word, admitting that, as it provides the construct for our reality, the text remains superior. CHAPTER V BACKTRACKING AND PRESSING ONWARD: THE ESSENCE OF POSTMODERNISM AND HEBRAIC INTERTEXTUALITY Bierce wrote during the age of literary realism, but he refused to comply with the dictates of mainstream literary critics and allow his stories to reflect the ordinary "smiling aspects" of America as William Dean Howells suggested realistic literature should (Wiggins 44). He was not impressed with what Gambaccini quotes him as calling the "'measureless, meaningless, and unimaginative novels, destitute of plot, destitute of purpose, destitute of art"' of the traditionally esteemed Howells and Henry James (41). "For Bierce the universe was not made interested in realistic literature. sensible by (Davidson the certainties of much late-nineteenth-century science" Instead of probabilities, he was interested in possibilities 122). (Wiggins 44). Bierce was not So he played with language to become what Gambaccini calls "an American master" (41). Gambaccini explains: [Bierce was] a more colorful prose stylist than Crane and better at characterization than Poe. In his ability to make the reader share the terror felt by his protagonists, Bierce reminds us of Dostoyevski. His stories juxtapose unlikely elements in a manner not seen before or after him . . . . The joy of reading Bierce is in searching a little harder for truths and in following a story that doesn't have an obvious destination. dreamer. In Bierce's nightmares we dream in tandem with the (41-42) 99 100 Ambrose with tenuous Bierce's preoccupation at the possibilities expense of stable certainties resulted in his producing material which requires readers critical Gambaccini explains to develop that "[Bierce's] methods alternative tales, unlike Poe's, of interpretation. don't always progress from A to B; they may be less accessible" and cites the foregoing as the reason for Bierce's failure to be ranked among the premier American nineteenth century (42). writers of the and Bierce's readers cannot cling to assumptions preconceived ideas concerning the nature of the world and expect to resolve Gambaccini says, "[Bierce's] stories can be the conflicts presented in his tales. Time is out of sync, the reader's expectations for the plot aren't disconcerting. It is difficult to distinguish fulfilled, and almost nothing is foreshadowed. dreams from reality; it's even tough to tell who's dead and who isn't" (41). Bierce's nebulous short stories compare with the postmodern Bernard Malamud and the Latin American writers Julio writings of Cortazar and Jorge Luis Borges, who owe much of their creative technique to Bierce (Davidson 128). Gambaccini says that Bierce's influence on the Latin writers cannot be "overestimated" Bierce and such postmodern writers explore the nature (42). of reality and take advantage of the similar, the different, and the juxtaposed. As Davidson points out, such postmodern writers reshape the constructs of language and literature so that "the logician's either/or becomes (121). both/and, an open-ended refusal to dichotomize" postmodern writers undermine the foundation upon the writer's In doing so, which self-identity rests. Short stories like Cortazar's "Axolotls" and Borges' "The Secret Miracle" as well as novels like Malamud's The Tenants "confuse and confound such fundamental Western dichotomies as reason and superstition, reality and art, 101 even reader and writer. Mimesis, the foundation realism, is turned inside out" (Davidson 122). for late-nineteenth-century No longer is writing, or any form of art, considered to be a mirror held up to reflect the world. The mirror of Bierce's texts, Davidson says: is a mirror held up to consciousness-with all its conscious, subconscious, and unconscious tricks and turning . . . . postmodern literature] the reader necessarily [Thus, in participates in the creation of the fiction . . . to make the reader aware of his or her own limitations, and, by extension, the limitations of human understanding. (122-123) Davidson is thus led to conclude that Bierce was a "postmodernist fictionalizer" (1) who understood well life's duplicities. Barren, naked, and unadorned, than two or three thousand words. many of Bierce's stories run no more His precision in word choice allows him to communicate specific meaning and at the same time allows the text to operate at multiple levels and to challenge careless readers. levels is attested to by two paradoxically Bierce's style and form. accurate The stories' multiplicity of critical remarks concerning Starrett says, "The clarity and directness of his thought and expression, and the nervous strength and purity of his diction, are the most unmistakable characteristics of his manner" (34). But Wiggins argues that Bierce "speaks to a discriminating audience, in ambiguous and ironic tones" (47). Clarity and ambiguity? Yes, indeed. In the previous chapter I pointed out that the critical analysis of literature is an effort to determine and explain why we understand to a piece of literature the way we do. and react New Critics have called for strict 102 adherence to the idea that the text contains its own meaning and exists apart Post-structuralists have from any interpretation a reader might assign to it. maintained that the meaning of a sentence is always deferred since meaning is determined by what a sign is not, more than by what that sign actually signifies. referent Structuralists have advocated that the sign is independent and maintains a value only in its relationship of the with other signs. These shifts in perspective which we find so much a part of our efforts to explain the nature of language and literature indicate an inability to resolve contradictory ideas like those expressed by Starrett and Wiggins the meaning of a given piece of literature. continuing interpretation, interpretations, interpretations The even as however, contradictory submission Handelman interpretations, accepting to the explains process of with a multitude by of all text itself. unknowable, much like that of Bierce's and postmodern unknowable. Hebraic intertextuality's satisfactorally deals inherent within the Hebrews' concerning the incomprehensible, is authors' submission to the that the Rabbis allow interpretive to acquire religious authority and that they ultimately proclaim tradition the results of that tradition to be Torah, "thus beginning to invalidate the idea of revelation as a one-time, already established, complete communication" (Handelman 202). Written and oral Torah, two sources of authority, coexist and include within revelation "not just new legal ordinances, but [the Rabbis'] own discussions on all matters ethical, historical, and so forth. expansion of the concept What is extraordinary of the written Torah very attempts to understand it" (Handelman 202). (revelation) Scholem here is their to embrace their states: 103 The unfolding of the truths, statements and circumstances are given in or accompany revelations becomes that the function of the oral Torah, which creates in the process a new type of religious person . . . . The biblical scholar perceives revelation not as a unique and clearly delineated occurrence, phenomenon examined: of eternal unearthed and . new, commentary. that Revelation needs evident religious phenomenon it created. tradition, they bring forth something something rightly understood commands religious commentary dignity: in order to be and applied-and this is the far from selfdoctrine out of which grew both the of biblical exegesis and the Jewish tradition which (287) Handelman explains Hebrews to be "Turn it and turn it again, for everything is in it" . . . Out of the religious entirely fruitfulness but rather as a that commentary is thus significant for the "because it is now viewed as being implicit within the written Torah- in Derridean terms, 'always already there"' (202). She continues to say that commentaries yielded by a hermeneutic study of the Torah "attain the same status" as that assigned to the Torah itself, for it is accepted as a "latent" aspect of that Scripture which is revealed: "Exegesis and interpretation of Scripture now themselves become Scripture, and emanate, claim the Rabbis, from the same divine source as the written Torah" (Handelman 202). To understand interpretation as a latent aspect of a text and as contributing to the meaning material. ................... of that text is to Thus, the interpretation process generate further interpretable is self perpetuating and 104 neverending. The foundation for the continuous process of interpretation is Yahweh, for inherent in the name is a vivifying power which, as the source of all meaning, states: provides "infinite interpretation" (Handelman 205). Scholem " . . . the word of God carries infinite meaning, however it may be defined" and "God's word is infinitely interpretable; indeed, it is the object of interpretation par excellence" (295). replace the term "God's word" "its contemporary origin producing secular endless If, as Handelman points out, we were to in Scholem's lengthy foregoing equivalent, other text by Derrida or Barthes" (205). text, this description interpretations could statement with of a 'meaningless' have been written In stating that only as "prophets" or "mystics" can we receive a divine illumination, insight or revelation of truth (205), Handelman echoes Scholem's statement that " . . . the Written Torah is a purely mystical concept, understood only by prophets who can penetrate to this level. As for us, we can perceive revelation only as unfolding oral tradition" Only the interpretations continues: of tradition afford meaning to the name. "If the conception of revelation (295). Scholem as absolute and meaning-giving but in itself meaningless is correct, then it must also be true that revelation will come to unfold its infinite meaning . . . only in its constant relationship to history, the arena in which tradition unfolds" (296). Handelman explains that "this unfolding of tradition through the scholar's inquiries is a highly creative process wherein the fullness of the word can encompass contradictions: wherein, indeed, contradictions play a creative role" (206). Davidson claims that Bierce is "preeminently (Bierce would like this) the premodern precursor of postmodern stories the disorientation and ambiguity fiction" (134). of modem She finds in Bierce's life reflected in 105 contemporary literature. She states that postmodern "writers produce The reader is thereby invited to be an accomplice in perpetrating the text (128). . . . calculated incomplete narrations that tempt the reader to finish the fiction. The irresolvability of "The Death of Halpin Frayser" and the blurring of characters' and readers' examples of cognitions incomplete in "An Occurrence narrations requiring a at Owl Creek reader's Bridge" are contribution. Postmodern writers create a fusion of fiction and life and refuse to distinguish between what has traditionally falsehood and truth. complexities been identified as fantasy and reality, Such writers have not simply sought to express the and disillusionment of modem life by blurring fantasy and reality but instead have chosen to utilize form and presentation to communicate "Bierce, the ambiguities and uncertainties like many twentieth-century as well. experimental Davidson writes that writers, often employs genre as simply another human category that exists to be transgressed" (29). She identifies modernism in literature by what she calls "the disillusion of form, the contradictory self-reflexiveness perception and cogitation" (133-134). Malamud's The Tenants. of narration, the limitations of For example, consider Bernard The novel's want of large structure is evident in its lack of a beginning or an end. Readers read until page twenty when they are informed, "End of Novel," but discover more than a hundred pages are left until the last page of The Tenants. Such a postmodern strategy is also evident in the fragmented structure of many of Bierce's short stories, including "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," "The Death of Halpin Frayser," and "The Man and the Snake." Tenants We find postmodernism in the free indirect discourse of The and "Axolotls" and the stream-of-consciousness in Borges' "The Secret 106 Miracle," which abuses readers' perceptual refuses to yield a declarative statement. extensively and cognitive limitations and This same technique is used in "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge," Frayser," and "The Man and the Snake." "The Death of Halpin "A Psychological Shipwreck" reveals Bierce's ability to demand that the reader "be an accomplice in perpetrating the text . . . " (Davidson 128). preconceptions This short tale takes advantage of readers' regarding the role of reader in relation to the text by commencing with activity assumed to be taking place within the physical realm. Subsequently, readers grasp that the activity is psychic, but only as the character experience, grasps this in understanding; a sense, the activity thus the reader and the character simultaneously. "The Death of Halpin Frayser" exhibits all these elements which Davidson identifies as the tools of postmodern disorientation, modem society. fragmented the fragmentation, and the writers used to reflect the alienation of today's readers in Written in four sections, the story itself is physically and continually abuses conventional perceptions of time, disorienting readers and alienating them not just from Bierce and his characters but from themselves as well, forcing them to question their own roles in the modem world and their perceptions of those roles. The solutions which might appear to resolve the unending questions about who killed Halpin Frayser, what his dream meant, and who wrote the poem ultimately fail, and Frayser's dream does not serve to illuminate his character for the reader but only to cloud and blur any insight which might be gained: protagonist incestuous, murderous, or a victimized poet? Is the As Davidson "The joke lies in the fact that the reader must continually reject these explains, 107 apparent solutions because they do complexities elsewhere in the text. not adequately comprehend the More to the point, no one solution can contain the unsettled and unsettling universe evoked by the text" (113). Whether or not the story is a joke is debatable, but, as Davidson says, "Nothing resolves [the text]" (105). moral justification postmodern When she points out the "futility of looking for a for Halpin's writers: There fate" is no (106), she echoes contemporary resolution, no justification, no understanding of the world in which we find ourselves. The Hebraic theory of intertexuality, theory of language, recognizes words a vivifying power. interpretation for unlike the traditional Western man's cognitive limitations and assigns to As such, it is an effective and rewarding method of an increasing amount of postmodern characteristics like those found in Bierce's tales. literature displaying Such a methodology allows texts to interpenetrate the world of the reader's experience and yields a greater number of meanings response and Herrnstein variables, and references. Smith's theory based Hebraic intertexuality draws Like Fish's theory of reader on multiple interacting the reader incorporates the reader as a character. Hebraic intertextuality allows the reader's into the text and But unlike these other theories, interpretations to become a part of the text to the extent that the text ceases to merely represent something beyond the reader; instead it becomes a part of him and redefines even the context in which he finds himself living in the world. intertextuality his stories, is to embrace their Bierce, indeterminacy, for suddenly their "weird, the shadowy To embrace Hebraic disturbing elements effect" (Starrett become the stories' virtues and the reader's source of satisfaction. of 37), WORKS CITED Primary Sources Bierce, Ambrose. "An Occurrence at Owl Creek Bridge." of Ambrose Bierce. Ed. Clifton Fadiman. "The Death of Halpin Frayser." Ed. Clifton Fadiman. Clifton Fadiman. Citadel, 1946. Citadel, 1946. "A Psychological Shipwreck." Citadel, 1946. Ed. 142-148. The Collected Writings of Ambrose Bierce. Secaucus, NJ: Citadel, 1946. 494-498. "The Difficulty of Crossing a Field." The Stories & Fables of Ambrose Bierce. Owing Mills, MD: Ed. 9-18. 395-409. The Collected Writings of Ambrose lBierce. Secaucus, NJ: Ed. Clifton Fadiman. Secaucus, NJ: The Collected Writings of Ambrose Bierce. Secaucus, NJ: "The Man and the Snake." The Collected Writings Edward Wagenknecht. Stemmer House, 1977. 162-164. Secondary Sources American Literary Aristotle. Scholarship. New York: 1977. 241. Trans. by J. L. Ackrill. Categories & De Interpretatione. London: Oxford UP, 1963. Barthes, Roland. Ithaca: "From Work to Text." Cornell UP, 1979. Bierce, Ambrose. Textual Strategies. 73-81. . The Collected Works of Ambrose Bierce and Washington: Ed. Josue Harari. 12 vols. New York Neale, 1909-12. "The Suitable Surroundings." Ed. Clifton Fadiman. The Collected Writings o f Ambrose Bierce. Secaucus, NJ: Citadel, 1946. 161- 168. 108 WJM " ,, " --- H , q" ,, , , -1.1- - I- - - I . -- , OLIONAK40 109 Boman, Thorlieff. Hebrew Thought Compared with Greek. Westminster, 1954. Crane, John Kenny. "Crossing the Bar Twice: Bierce, Hemingway, and Golding." 1969. Philadelphia: Post-Mortem Consciousness in Studies in Short Fiction 4, (Summer), 361-376. Davidson, Cathy N. the Ineffable. The Experimental Fiction of Ambrose Bierce: Lincoln: Derrida, Jacques. Structuring U of Nebraska P, 1984. Speech and Phenomena. Evanston, II.: Northwestern UP, 1973. Eagleton, Terry. Literary Theory and Introduction. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1983. Fish, Stanley. Is There a Text in This Class? Communities. Gadamer, Cambridge: Hans-Georg. The Authority of Interpretive Harvard UP, 1980. Truth and Method. 1960; trans. New York: Seabury, 1975. Gambaccini, Peter. "The Real Old Gringo." Diversion October, 1989. 38, 41-42, 44. Grenander, M. E. Grice, H. Paul. Ambrose Bierce. New York: "Logic and Coversation." Syntax and Semantics: Ed. Peter Cole and Jerry L. Morgan. 3, 1975. Handelman, Susan. The Slayers of Moses: Twayne, 1971. Speech Acts. 41-58. The Emergence of Rabbinic Interpretation in Modern Literary Theory. Albany: State U of New York P, 1982. Hodge, Robert and Gunther Kress. Social Semiotics. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1988. 110 Hutchison, Chris. "The Act of Narration: Theories of Narrative Discourse." (1984): A Critical Survey of Some Speech-Act Journal of Literary Semantics 13.1 3-34. Johnson, Barbara. Introduction. Barbara Johnson. Dissemination. Chicago: By Jacques Derrida. U of Chicago P, 1981. "Juxtaposition." Webster's New International "Juxtaposition." Webster's New Universal Unabridged Dictionary. Kunst, Arnold. "An Overlooked Type of Inference." Oriental African Studies Linkin, Harriet Kramer. Bridge'." Logan, F. J. Trans. Dictionary. 1934 Ed. 1983 Ed. Bulletin of School of 10 (1942): 976-91. "Narrative Technique in 'An Occurrence at Owl Creek The Journal of Narrative Technique 18.2 (1988): 137-52. "The Wry Seriousness of Owl Creek Bridge." American Literary Realism 10.2 (1977): 101-12. Merrell, Floyd. "Metaphor and Metonymy: A Key to Narrative Structure." Language and Style: An International Journal Neusner, Jacob. The Way of Torah: Dickenson, An Introduction to Judaism. Belmont, CA: 1970. New American Standard Bible. Plato. 11.3. (1978): 146-163. The Dialogues of Plato. Nashville: Thomas Nelson, 1977. Trans. by B. Jowett. 30. 1871, Rpt. Oxford: Clarendon P, 1953. Powers, James G. Bridge?" Prince, Gerald. "Freud and Farquhar: Studies in Short Fiction An Occurence at Owl Creek 19.3 (1982): 278-81. "Narrative Analysis and Narratology." of Virginia P, (1982): New Literary History U 179-188. "Narrative Pragmatics, Message, and Point." Poetics 12 (1983): 527-36. 111 Ricoeur, Paul. "Narrative Time." The Rule of Metaphor: Meaning in Language. Ruthrof, H. G. 7.1 (1980): 169-90. Multi-Disciplinary Studies of the Creation of U of Toronto P, 1977. Toronto and Buffalo: "Narrative Language." Language and Style 5.6 (1974): 42-51. "Revelation and Tradition as Religious Categories in Scholem, Gershom. Judaism." Critigal Inquiry The Messianic Idea in Judaism New York: Schocken, 1971. 282-309. Smith, Barbara Herrnstein. Narrative Ed. W. J. T. Mitchell. Starrett, Vincent. Ambrose Toolan, Michael. Narrative: Routledge, "Narrative Versions, Narrative Theories." Bierce. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1980. Port Washington, NY: Q2n 209-232. Kennikat, 1920. A Critical Linguistic Introduction. New York: 1988. Wiggins, Robert A. Ambrose Bierce. Minneapolis: Wimsatt, William and Monroe Beardsley. U of Minnesota P, 1964. The Verbal Icon. Lexington: U of Kentucky P, 1954. Woodruff, Stuart C. The Short Stories of Ambrose Bierce: Pittsburgh: U of Pittsburgh P, 1964. A Study in Polarity.
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz