LEAVING POLITICS BIOS, ZľĎ, LIFE LAURENT DUBREUIL We live politics, which is not only the far horizon of shared existence, an inventory of techniques, a subject of discussion between scholars. We live it in our gestures, words, experiences, feelings, and attitudes. Life, politics are bound to each other; the evidence speaks to us from the entrenched camp of a university campus to a hermitage deep in the forest. But as to whether or how to articulate life and politics, no sooner is the question raised than we intuit their relation. And with this more questions arise: is it even accurate to make a difference between political practice and the course of life? Are these substances distinct? If so, do they converge at a single point in “public” or “private” space? There are no clear answers. In our times, a model of intrication is expressed more and more. Biopolitics has become the new catchword on the intellectual scene. Biopolitics would complicate yet again the relation between life and the City, for it seems to integrate bios LQWRWKH&LW\,WLVDQRSHUDWLRQRIIRUFHLQZKLFKVRPHWKLQJIURPOLIHÀQGVLWVHOI FRQÀVFDWHGVWDPSHGZLWKDGLVÀJXULQJVHDO7KHWRQHRISDWKRVLQP\SUHDPEOHEHIRUH the more philosophical words to which this article will also give voice, is intended to reproduce the strike force of certain audacious propositions, with their evocation of destruction. Here I am thinking especially of Giorgio Agamben, whose Homo Sacer series continues to provoke great controversy. Among the responses Agamben incites is the recent work of Roberto Esposito, the subject of this issue of Diacritics. I want to take this occasion to return to the relations between life and politics—in the strange light of our contemporary debates on the junction bio-politics. )DFLQJDÀHOGSRLVHGWREHFRPHDTXDVLVSHFLDOW\RIUHVHDUFK,ZLOOOLPLWP\VHOIWR an almost nothing, to the simple fringe, to these few employed, repeated, pooled words: ELRVSROLVYLWD]ĿďSomething other than a terminology or lexicography is in play. For the deliberations of Agamben or Esposito render an immediate and crucial importance to language in the elucidation of their categories. But what these authors make language say merits a supplementary examination. Their use of substantives, their solicitation of textual events, contain a philosophical program that informs their thoughts on biopolitics—beyond or other than what is recognized at times. In its epistemic reach, the present text is a critical inquiry into certain recourses to language, to idioms, and the way they contradictorily qualify present-day biopolitics. The theoretical problem takes a strange turn in the historical reconstitution given by Agamben, for whom the two Greek words bios and ]ĿďUHQGHUDQDFFRXQWRIWKLQJVE\QRZREVFXUHRUORVW$FRPSDUDEOHGLIÀFXOW\ arises from the confrontation of discourses assembled by Esposito. Both authors begin by analyzing the contemporary, both dress their works in a philology that cuts through history. This crossing of disciplines, and its value in the exposition of political philosophy, constitutes another face of my intended exploration. Situated by languages, placed among disciplines, biopolitics can be interrogated as well for the articulation it designates. Biopolitics appears to be revelatory of a political ambition more widespread than in the immediate exacerbation of biometrics or genographics. In order to clear a way for myself through textual territories, I will follow above all the impulsion of two words, and those they “engender”—bios and ]ĿďThese terms are Greek. In themselves alone they exercise a formidable effect in the work of Agamben. diacritics / summer 2006 diacritics 36.2: 83–98 83 While more discreet in Esposito’s, still they return. Shall we then conclude that Greek speaks in us, that politics is best expressed from its Hellenic origins? Not necessarily. But, UHTXLULQJQHLWKHUUHWXUQQRURULJLQFHUWDLQFRQÀJXUDWLRQVRIWKH*UHHNFRUSXVVHHPWRUHpeat themselves almost identically. Everything depends upon the almost, of course, which facilitates the transition from one text to another, in one sense or the other. My anxiety in regards to biopolitics is thus linked to the bios, to the ]Ŀďto the polis, to their proliferation in both Antiquity and the present—two eras from which may come, by anachronism, several supplementary readings, be they of the “canonical” Aristotle. Thus we must begin ZLWKWKHLQWURGXFWLRQRIWKHÀUVWHomo Sacer, wherein Agamben presents a semantic distribution he declares to be crucial. Bios Is =Ŀďand =ĿďIs Bios1 “The Greeks had no single term to express what we mean by the word ‘life.’ They used two terms [. . .]: ]Ŀďwhich expressed the simple fact of living common to all living beings (animals, men, or gods), and bios, which indicated the form or way of living proper to an individual or a group” [1/3]. These two sentences, which open Agamben’s Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, have since popularized a “Greek” distinction at the very heart of life, a distinction that would have been lost. According to Agamben, Greek suggests an opposition between the “simple, natural life” and a “particular way of OLIHµ>@´OLIHLQJHQHUDODQGWKHTXDOLÀHGZD\RIOLIHSURSHUWRPHQµ>@´SULYDWH OLIHDQGSROLWLFDOH[LVWHQFHµ>²@=ĿďWKHÀUVWWHUPZRXOGUHIHUXVEDFNWROLIH in nature, common to life in general, which the human becoming would have to convert LQWRTXDOLÀHGOLIHLQWRHX]ďQ(the good life3), VX]ďQ(living-with), in short, bios politikos. At best, ]Ŀďarises from oikos, a more circumscribed space than the one of the City. This conceptual structure would be paired with the operation of Greek semantics, $WKHQLDQ GHPRFUDF\ DQG FODVVLFDO SROLWLFDO UHÁHFWLRQ LQ SDUWLFXODU WKDW RI 3ODWR DQG Aristotle). Modernity has called into question the difference, the gap between ]Ŀďand bios. Historically speaking, “the decisive fact” consists in that “bios and ]Ŀďright and fact, enter into a zone of irreducible indistinction” [9/12] that founds totalitarian biopolitics in the West. Agamben’s analysis is notorious. I reference it so as to underline the extent to which the linguistic hypothesis remains in solidarity with the entire demonstrative movement of the trilogy Homo Sacer. The effective separation between mere life and political existence is conferred on us by the words of the Greeks. This point is by now widely accepted. On the web, the correlation between ]Ŀďand bios yields a large number of responses. The two Greek terms have become veritable signal-words, cited often without explicit reference to Homo Sacer. Their presence hallows an exemplary success in the diffusion of ideas that owes to Agamben. However, he merely popularized the terms, as is evidenced by his introductory references to Hannah Arendt and Michel Foucault. The second is invoked for his conclusion to The Will to Knowledge and the courses he led at the Collège de France on biopolitics. Arendt appears as one who restores the effaced difference. In The Human Condition we read in effect that bios is situated “in opposition to the simple ]ĿďµDQGSURYHVWKXVWREH´VSHFLÀFDOO\KXPDQOLIHµ>@4 6RPHHOHPHQWVRIWKLVÀUVWSDUWKDYHDOUHDG\EHHQSXEOLVKHGLQ)UHQFKXQGHUWKHWLWOH´'H la vie dans la vie: sur une étrange opposition entre ]Ŀďet bios” in Labyrinthe: Atelier interdisciplinaire 22 (2005): 47–52. The present version has been amended and revised. 3DJHUHIHUHQFHVZLOOOLVW(QJOLVKHGLWLRQÀUVWRULJLQDOVHFRQG 3. Cf. commentaries in Homo Sacer 2, 7/4, 10. 4. Arendt’s sentence is a bit ambiguous, so it is hard to determine whether she believes the GLVWLQFWLRQWREH´*UHHNµRU$ULVWRWHOLDQ 84 The interplay between ]Ŀď and bios was remarked upon much earlier by Greek speakers. The grammarians proposed two notable theories to explain the competition in terms. For some, the distinguo would be related to duration and continuity. Bios would be “the time of ]Ŀď,”5 a portion of it. Some other authors proposed the inverse repartition. The second explanation lies at the origin of Arendt’s words, as of Agamben’s and their followers’. For Ammon of Alexandria, “bios is appropriate to animals of reason [logikon ]ĿRQ], that is, to human beings only; ]Ŀďto human beings and animals without reason.”6 We must note as well that the philologist uses Aristotle’s distinctions without wondering whether the reasonable use preferred by the Stagirite is relevant for the entire Greek language. Let us add that other grammarians believed a contrario that bios had been the term reserved for nonrational animals. Obviously, each of the two constructions relies on more or less convincing examples. $UHQGWUHPDLQVHYDVLYHDVWRZK\VKHRSWVIRURQHMXVWLÀFDWLRQRYHUDQRWKHU,WLVQRW certain that she means to refer to one usage of Greek; she moreover cites Aristotle in support. Without doubt the distribution ELRV]Ŀďhas some consistency in the philosopher’s writings. But it would be overly hasty to believe, in regard even to Aristotle, that bios is ´VSHFLÀFDOO\KXPDQµRU´SROLWLFDOµ7DNHIRUH[DPSOHWKHSKUDVH´OLYLQJ>]ďQ] the life [bion] of a plant.” One reads as well that “the differences among animals []ĿRQ] are relative to their lives [bíous], their characteristics, and their organs.”8 Certainly in the two occurrences one will object that Aristotle did not intend to repeat, after ]ĿRQthe related word ]Ŀď; but to explain this approximation by way of a single stylistic concern is hardly convincing. It could be that the recourse to bios (for a plant) is due to the internal limitations of Greek, in which the verb ELRĿis “practically never used in the present tense” “in Attic Greek.”9 This would preclude the syntagm “to live [bioun] the life []ĿďQ] of a plant.” Here I have just transposed the solution onto an analogous problem proffered by Agamben, that is, the theoretically troubling expression ]ĿRQSROLWLNRQBut the rarity of certain forms of ELRĿremains to be proven; and in any case there exists another verb of the same “root,” ELRWHXĿ2QHÀQGVLWLQ$ULVWRWOH·VGHVFULSWLRQRIELUGVWKDWGRQRWÁ\ but “live [bioteuousin] near water”: bios and not ]ĿďIn fact, one could follow Agamben (more than one can Arendt) on the degree of TXDOLÀFDWLRQAristotle has perhaps the tendency to place bios more on the side of particular life (vegetable or aquatic existence in the city) and ]Ŀďon the general. One would have the play between a marked substantive and an unmarked one, linguistically speaking. But in no case can bios be reserved to either humans or political practice. Finally, Aristotle is not the entire Greek corpus. A useful truism to repeat. When he contrasts bios and ]Ŀď Aristotle inscribes himself within a discursive tradition. We will draw upon only one diplopic example. In the second chorus of Heracles, Euripides invents a moral postmortem in which the good people, having arrived at the end of their years, are offered a second chance, while the bad are to be punished by a death without return. Two verses convey the improbable gnome: “villainy ,DPXVLQJWKHFODULÀFDWLRQVSURYLGHGE\WKHThesaurus Graecae linguae at the end of the Bios DUWLFOH>VHH(VWLHQQH@7RDGGVRPHWKLQJWRWKHGLFWLRQDU\OHWXVVSHFLI\WKDWWKHK\SRWKHVLVLV SDUWLFXODUO\GHYHORSHGE\WKH*UHHNFRPPHQWDWRUVRI+LSSRFUDWHV&IScholia: Hippocratem and Galenum 2: 246, 248. All translations from classical languages are the author’s. 6. Ammonius Alexandrinus, 'HDGÀQLXPYRFDEXORUXPGLIIHUHQWLD§100. The same distribution is found in the Bios article of works of the same era, such as of Herennius Philo, De diversis YHUERUXPVLJQLÀFDWLRQLEXV 7. Aristotle, De generatione animalium [2.3.736b]. 8. Aristotle, Historia animalium [1.1.487a]. 9. Agamben, Homo Sacer 2/5. Agamben cites ELRĿ LQ LWV PLGGOH YRLFH DQG LQÀQLWLYH IRUP biounai. 10. Aristotle, Historia animalium [1.1.487a]. Ammonius gives a new distinction between ELRĿ and ELRWHXĿZKLFKLVQRPRUHUHOHYDQWWKDQWKHÀUVWRQH diacritics / summer 2006 85 would have only one life [bioton] in life [zoas].”11 Zoas is a delicate genitive to elucidate; he literally says, “one life’s life,” or “one life of life.” Translators have often chosen to see in it a single intensity and discard the doubling. I choose ambiguity; that is, one life would be of life, the life’s life, because in life. Bios is a portion, or the subcase, of ]Ŀď somewhat as with Aristotle. Let us hasten to cite another phrase, one that indicates the exact and dynamic inverse. Here is a bit from Plato, who, in the Timaeus, imagines a psychic migration proximate to Euripides’s chorus. He mentions a soul which “spent a lame OLIHWKURXJKRXWOLIHµ>F@³ÀQDOH[FKDQJHRIWHUPVLQZKLFKWKLVWLPHbios denotes life in general, and ]Ŀďa singular lifetime. If it is our intention to render coherent these disparate elements (and must we?), we should hardly know how to get beyond situating the most general tendencies and the most SDUWLFXODUNHHSLQJLQPLQGWKDWWKHUROHVDUHQRWGLVWULEXWHGLQDGYDQFH$VSHFLÀFtongue has its structures and its laws, but it is not an external or absolute datum: discourse can reinvent it in a singular manner, which is what Euripides, Plato, or Aristotle did. Agamben, who substantiates an Alexandrine conjecture undertaken by Arendt, is well within his rights to attach a conceptual content to ]Ŀďand inversely another one to bios. In so doing, he participates in the Socratic moment when the philosopher went to visit the everyday FLWL]HQVRI$WKHQVVRDVWRUHGHÀQHWRJHWKHUWKHODQJXDJHWKH\VSRNH6RWKHGLIÀFXOW\ comes not so much from the philosophical process than from its linguistic and historicoSROLWLFDOMXVWLÀFDWLRQ$JDPEHQVLPSOLÀHV$ULVWRWOH·VWH[WVDQGWKHQGLVVROYHVWKHPLQWR the grandiose entity of “the Greeks.” Embedded in the unfounded argument from authority is a network of unspoken motives, which we must expose, then denounce. Even while he anchors the entire “political existence” in language (logos12), Agamben remains deaf to the semantic phenomena in tongue. 6LJQLÀFDQFHFDQRFFXUZLWKLQDGLVFRXUVHLQZKLFK bios and ]Ŀďassume values that respond to one another, that complete or critique each other—far from the indexation of closed and rational meanings. 7KHGHFHSWLYHHTXLYDOHQFHEHWZHHQWKHFRQFHSWXDOFODULÀFDWLRQRIGHÀQLWLRQDQGWKH uses of utterance or discourse leads us to the lexical underpinning of political analysis. The alleged solidarity among words, City, and philosophy cannot but astound. The end of Homo Sacer reads like the workings of a character backstage: “today bios lies in ]Ŀď H[DFWO\ DV HVVHQFH LQ WKH +HLGHJJHULDQ GHÀQLWLRQ RI 'DVHLQ OLHV liegt) in existence” >@0RUHWKDQWKDW$JDPEHQMRLQV+HLGHJJHULQWKHDIÀUPDWLRQWKDW´WKH*UHHN tongue, and it alone, is logos” >+HLGHJJHU WUDQV PRGLÀHG@7R XQGHUVWDQG WKH SRlitical logos requires us to move in the direction of the philosophical Ursprache that is Greek. The idiom rings in unison with the real: two different words designate two different things (naked life, political life). Agamben apparently situates the dissolution at the HQGRI$QWLTXLW\ZKHUHDVIRU+HLGHJJHUWKHXSVHWGDWHVIURP6RFUDWHV$QRWKHUPRGLÀFDtion: in Freiburg, the Hellenic celebration includes praise of a language “in unison with being,” whereas in Venetia the modern blurring of the ancient duality is deplored. But in both cases history is a metaphysical process beginning with the loss of the Greek—and true—Urgrund. By inscribing his project ab ovo in the Greek tongue, Agamben runs the philological risks already noted. According to the protocols for proof in Homo Sacer, lexical counterexamples mar a large part of the support. In fact, the supposedly novel element of the modern era (this “irreducible indistinction” between bios and ]Ŀď) is authorized only by DQLPDJLQDU\UHLÀFDWLRQRIVD\linguaggio and lingua. Despite the status it appears to merit in the political logos, the idiom is accordingly, and exemplarily, reduced to a distribution of meanings stripped of their motility, of even their life—in all possible senses. The assertion here of a “sole” word for life might merit today an additional remark. To contend that a single substantive exists corresponds no more to indifference than the ex 86 11. Euripides, Hercules, v. 663–64. &IDQDO\VHVLQ$JDPEHQHomo Sacer 7/10–11. istence of parasynonyms may be confused with a “clear” or obvious distribution. Are we all in agreement on “what we mean by the word ‘life?’” [Homo Sacer 1/3, my emphasis]. Did Michel Henry, Gilles Deleuze, and Jacques Derrida, each contemporary and French, share the way in which they heard the term? The “single term” [Homo Sacer 1/3] is thus diffracted as well. It is troubling to note that Agamben hardly explains the current confusion regarding this lexical unicity, and for good reason; the chronology of biopolitical events would lose its contemporary character if allied, for example, with the emergence of the Latin vita and its successors. This is to say that Agamben has cause to protect the state of exception that inheres in a Greek experience, in which the adequation of language to situation would be KLVWRULFDOO\UHYHODWRU\ &RQFHSWDQG6LJQLÀFDWLRQ 7KHLPSDVVHVLQ$JDPEHQ·VWKRXJKWSURYLGHRFFDVLRQWRUHÁHFWXSRQWKHZD\VZHPDNH use of disciplines. The most troubling in Homo Sacer derives undoubtedly from the peculiar connection between philosophy and other disciplines—above all, philology and history. Here, “history” means more or less “beginning,” or origin. One returns to the Greeks so as to plunge into the causality of the past. I readily accept a correlation, a strong one, between Athens and a large number of countries in the present. But the idea of a lineage leading from Greco-Roman Antiquity to Europe and the United States is highly suspect. Agamben deplores the break in this line, the event that bypasses the (illusory) bipolarity of bios and ]Ŀďin favor of the false unity of life. Just after he insists on this break in the present day, he postulates the possibility of a direct heritage. Playing on these two planes, Agamben eludes simple temporal linearity—so widely criticized following Nietzsche— to reestablish it as a virtual countermodel: contemporary politics would have yet retained its glorious Hellenic distinction had it known to adhere more faithfully to Aristotle. The present accession to indistinction has effected a bifurcation LQWKHÀUVWWUDMHFWRU\ This discontinuity has rendered all the more palpable the prestige of origin, according to which all is judged. So it follows that history is precisely a fall out of the initial paradise. A similar image emerges from biblical accounts of the Creation whereby human mobility corresponds to the loss of Eden. Agamben thus convokes two major paradigms in his understanding of the unfolding of time: history is produced in its emergence from the origin, and it is also a linear narrative that has deviated. The rupture has to do with both a theology of the fall from grace and a poetics of the discontinued event. We can easily see that Agamben not only borrows from Foucault the term biopolitics but also appropriates the sense of history as a broken line. But Agamben recovers to some degree the Heideggerian side of Foucault.13 Historical and local fractures are the hypostasis of an originary ÀVVXUHLQWKHRULJLQ To the extent that it is discipline, the history Agamben practices also mimics FouFDXOW·VGHPRQVWUDWLRQV:HÀQGLQLWWKHVDPHWHQGHQF\WRZDUGHUXGLWLRQ$JDPEHQFRQÀUPVSKLORVRSK\·VQHHGWRGUDZKHQFHIRUWKIURPRWKHUGLVFRXUVHVRINQRZOHGJHDVGRHV Foucault. Erudition is transformed into an authoritative apparatus. From the moment that uncertainty (whether it be the lack of distinction typical to the era, or the relativity of science) threatens the solidity of theoretical discourse, authority is sought in the administration of proof. The protocol thus adopted copies philological and historical scholarship: accumulation of facts, enactment of a unitary rule, and liquidation of counterexamples GLVTXDOLÀHGDVHUURUVRILQWHUSUHWDWLRQRULQVLJQLÀFDQWDEHUUDWLRQV$JDPEHQ·VHUXGLWLRQ LVQRWVRPXFKIRUWKHSXUSRVHRI´UHVSHFWLQJVRXUFHVµDVWREULQJDVFLHQWLÀFDSSDUDWXVWR the philosophical core of his thesis. Foucault, with more endurance and more footnotes, &I)RXFDXOWDits et écrits ´+HLGHJJHUDWRXMRXUVpWpSRXUPRLOHSKLORVRSKHHVVHQWLHO>+HLGHJJHUKDVDOZD\VEHHQIRUPHWKHHVVHQWLDOSKLORVRSKHU@µ6HHDOVR diacritics / summer 2006 87 proceeds similarly. Agamben, less encumbered with formalities, has greater recourse to philological scholarship than to the breakdown, collection, and analysis of archives. In this he evinces another of Heidegger’s tendencies, whereby a thorough familiarity with classical languages in no way precludes the pronouncement of hazardous hypotheses. The valorization of Greek thus plays into an overall strategic approach. The number of readers capable of verifying case by case the arguments surrounding the Hellenic corpus is proportionally as slight as the risk of contesting any of these. Any divergent arguPHQW³LQFOXGLQJWKHRQH,KDYHMXVWSURSRVHG³ZLOOÀQGLWVHOISUH\WRHQRUPRXVGLIÀFXOties. For even had I multiplied the examples, a priori the objection as formulated is hardly more credible for non-Hellenists. Finally, as I have stressed, linguistic competence can lead to entirely other conclusions than my own; the Alexandrians were playing this game. In short, in the time of one reading, objection runs the risk of neutralization. “Responsible” scholars would not want to chance decision and would suspend their judgment. Agamben’s philology suggests disciplinary procedures, but it is foremost intended for WKHUHDGHUVZKRGRQRWSRVVHVVWKHPHDQVRIYHULÀFDWLRQ³HYHQPRUHVRVLQFHWKHFLWHG texts are commented upon rather evasively, the selection unduly chosen, and the grammatical conventions occulted. Agamben’s is a philology for show, in sum, which weakens in advance the possibility for debate. Everything becomes incontestable: the necessary dialogic and contradictory movement of human sciences is thus stopped. Interdisciplinarity takes on meaning only when interpretations show the tensions internal to knowledge, and when the elements harvested are given the possibility of an explanation. Agamben rushes his liminal argument through a few pages, curbs his examples as much as possible, and presents the philological argument in a monolithic manner. In addition to disallowing his public a rudimentary knowledge of the problems associated with language, he blocks the interdisciplinary practice he purports to perform. Norms WUHDWLQJSKLORORJLFDODQGKLVWRULFDOVFLHQWLÀFLW\DUHGHWDFKHGIURPWKHGLVFLSOLQHVDVGLVFXUVLYHDQGFROOHFWLYHHQVHPEOHV,QVWHDGRIDQLQWHUVHFWLRQEHWZHHQNQRZOHGJHVZHÀQG isolated practices whose legitimacy is as yet untested—this in order to better seat the auWKRU·VSKLORVRSKLFDOUHÁHFWLRQ7KHDUJXPHQWIURPDXWKRULW\WKDWKLVWRU\WKH´ÀUVWWLPHµ and the erudition of classical studies (the disjunction between bios and ]Ŀď) provide is required by a conceptual speech seeking external support but fearing any confrontation with another discourse. 5HYLVLWLQJ WKH ÀFWLRQDO RSSRVLWLRQ EHWZHHQ bios and ]Ŀď consequently helps us to qualify Agamben’s philosophical act. Ours is not a matter of reestablishing the truth, but rather one of divesting the crow of his peacock feathers, as in Aesop. Finally we must emphasize the repercussions of a thought riveted upon the origin and dedicated to its eventual rupture. The fact that ]ĿďKDVQHYHUXQLTXHO\VLJQLÀHGEDUHRUDQLPDOOLIHFDOOV into question, beyond all else, the fable of a biopolitical happening and, at the least, contests the account of its current practice. It would nonetheless be unfortunate to renounce the possibility of an encounter among discrete types of knowledge, and altogether too convenient to simply disqualify the concept of biopolitics for reasons of the usage that stressed anew its study. It becomes precisely all the more necessary to rethink the articulation between OLIHELRV]Ŀďand politics³ZKLFKLQYROYHVQROHVVWKDQFDUHIRUWH[WXDOVSHFLÀFLWLHVDQGFKDUWHGHYHQWV Situated along this vein is Roberto Esposito, whose book Bios deploys an altogether different thesis than Agamben’s. In responding, most often allusively, to the philosophical reinauguration of biopolitics expressed by his compatriot, Esposito displaces the problem in three salutary ways. First, Bios PRGLÀHVWKHKLVWRULFDOPDUNHUVRIWKHXVDJHRIWKH word biopolitics and uncovers its traces before Foucault. Esposito’s introductory mention RIWKHZRUNVRI0RUOH\5REHUWVLQRU$DURQ6WDURELQVNLLQ14 exceeds simple 14. See Esposito, Bios ² 1% RQ S 6WDURELQVNL·V ÀUVW QDPH LV PLVVSHOOHG DV ´$URRQµ 88 anecdotal precision. It allows for the collective construction of a category underneath that of the tutelary duo signaled by Agamben (Foucault and Arendt). This chronological UHFRQÀJXUDWLRQSUHFOXGHVWKHSULYLOHJLQJRIRQHW\SHRIJLYHQFRJQLWLYHÀOLDOUHODWLRQVKLS From there Esposito is more in line to return to the (post-)Foucauldian intricacy between biopolitics and biopower. Finally, the circuit through the canon of political theory favors an abandonment of the Johannic posture that Agamben so effortlessly adopts. There is in Bios neither apocalyptic visions15 nor faith in the primordial nature of logos, as respun in the in principio erat verbum (in the beginning was the word) of the evangelist. While Esposito’s approach assumes the false air of a classical history of philosophy, the work goes beyond the compilation of philosophical doctrines. The evocation of the SUHGHFHVVRUV WDNHV WKH IRUP RI D SURJUHVVLYHO\ FULWLFDO DQG UHÁHFWLYH UHFXSHUDWLRQ (Vposito renounces the objectivist projection of an exterior observer. He marks the sites of passage, the moments of contact between texts that can rely upon the same sort of analysis, all while endowing contrary values to the facts they describe. Esposito advances by way of underlining differences and relationships within those WH[WVFRQGXFLYHWRFRUUHODWLRQZLWKRXWSUHÀJXUHGVXEVXPSWLRQ7KHSUREOHPDWLFGLVSODFHPHQWVGHÀQHGHDUOLHUDQGWKHSUHFLVLRQRIWKLVPRGHRIH[SRVLWLRQOHQGKRSHWKDWbios and ]Ŀďmight be led back to a whole body of works rather than frozen into a linguistic RQWRORJ\:KHQLQWKHÀUVWFKDSWHU(VSRVLWRHYRNHVWKH´*UHHNOH[LFRQµKHVSHFLÀHV “in particular the one of Aristotle.”16 Afterwards, he limits himself to considering bios as ´TXDOLÀHGOLIHµ´IRUPRIOLIHµ>@GLVUHJDUGLQJWKHDGGLWLRQDOFRQVLGHUDWLRQRIDKXPDQity. Elsewhere he cites the two Greek words as having arisen from the “classical Aristotelian partition” [55]. Both times Aristotelian might refer as much to the tradition borne by Aristotle as to the Stagirite himself. And even though the philosopher did not make these substantives contrast in a unique and rigid manner, the fact remains that the Alexandrian grammarians I referenced above are very much the inheritors of the Lyceum’s teaching. In the care he takes to distinguish between the Greek tongue and Aristotelian practice, Esposito undoes the history-catastrophe that opens and closes Homo Sacer. In the remainder of Bios, the contrasted occurrences of bios and ]Ŀďrefer more often to their current use. It is because he critiques Arendt that Esposito designates, in the phenomenon of birth, a “maximal distance” between “]Ŀď” and “bios” [196], a frontal opposition (cf. “that opposes [bios] frontally to ]Ŀď” [196]). A bit later, he will qualify this “Arendtian caesura [. . .] between life and the condition of existence” as “already Heideggerian” [196]. On this point he challenges the idea of a “reduction of bios to ]Ŀď—or to ‘bare existence’” [153]. Quoted indirectly, Homo Sacer seems to describe a resurgence of the couple of Greek words. Because Esposito’s recourse to the ELRV]Ŀďbipolarity is systematically tied WRWKHWH[WVWKDWKDYHHODERUDWHGXSRQLWWKHSULYLOHJHKHOGE\WKH*UHHNODQJXDJHÀQGV itself evacuated. In all probability Esposito would rather be skeptical before the natural validity of such an opposition. Caution is less in the philological order than the philosophical. In the wake of Derrida, Esposito tries more than once to approach the discrepancy in differential terms. Thus does he discern in Nietzsche “the point of precipitation of a biopolitics of death and the horizon, hardly sketched, of a new politics of life” [114]—that LV´DIÀUPDWLYHELRSROLWLFVµ>@,QDQRWKHUZRUNCategorie dell’impolitico, Esposito states similarly that “the impolitical is not diverse from the political” [xx]. As to ]Ŀďand bios, (VSRVLWRPRGLÀHVWKHDUWLFXODWLRQKHIHLJQHGWRUHFRJQL]H+HFRUUHFWVIRUH[DPSOH Agamben’s version of Nazi biopolitics by writing: “one should speak of the spiritualization of ]Ŀďand of the biologization of the spirit” [Bios 153]. Throughout Esposito repeats the word “biologization,” in which bios comes to assume the place of ]Ŀďas mere life, or 7KHÀQDOZRUGVRIHomo Sacer DUH´ULVNLQJDQXQSUHFHGHQWHGELRSROLWLFDOFDWDVWURSKHµ >@´ULVFKLRGLXQDFDWDVWURIHELRSROLWLFDVHQ]DSUHFHGHQWLµ>@ 16. Bios $OOTXRWDWLRQVIURP(VSRVLWRKDYHEHHQWUDQVODWHGE\WKHDXWKRURIWKHDUWLFOH diacritics / summer 2006 89 simple animal life. Even the title, Bios, becomes a supplementary means by which to alter the distribution between bios and ]Ŀď 7KHUHÁHFWLRQWKXVUHFRYHUVVRPHWKLQJRIWKHVHPDQWLFLQÁHFWLRQDWZRUNLQ(XULSides or Plato. But Esposito succeeds only by occulting the very term ]ĿďThe work is entitled Bios, and not Bio-, ZKLFKZRXOGKDYHLPSOLHGDSURGXFWLYLW\RIWKHDIÀ[LQPRGern languages. The name of the book is, after all, Greek. In this way Esposito continues a series of references to Antiquity [see his Immunitas and Communitas]; and again he rejoins Agamben, whose trilogy Homo Sacer is scored with indexed concepts on ancient languages. Yet if a concept of life may be placed in bios, in the name of what can we avoid, or void, ]Ŀď? Tactician without a doubt, and markedly unlike his contemporary, Esposito prefers not to harp on a lexical disagreement. But does the induction of ]Ŀďin bios not reproduce the hierarchical dichotomy suggested by both Arendt and Agamben (human life > naked life"5DWKHUWKDQDIDFHWRIDFHRSSRVLWLRQZHÀQGKHQFHIRUWKDGLIIHUHQWLDOFKDUDFWHUL]Dtion; yet the sense of the value remains identical. Under the name of bios, DXQLÀFDWLRQ is in process that has nothing to do with Greek vocabulary. The rare references to the +HOOHQLFSKLORVRSKLFDOFRUSXVUHVSHFWWKHGRXEOHVLGHRIVLJQLÀFDWLRQWKHUHDUHbios and ]Ŀď), and limit the opposition to a (post-)Aristotelian operation. But the innumerable resurgences of bios throughout the text serve above all to dispense of ]ĿďFacing a Greek particularity in relation to the Roman and Anglo-Saxon languages, Agamben opted for a bipolar rationalization, whereas Esposito tends to erase the cumbersome supernumerary. Bios, from beginning to end, contains ]Ŀďas internal difference, which is as much as to say that Esposito’s subtle games between idioms are in the last analysis sustained by one V\QWKHWLFWHUP7KH*UHHNODQJXDJHLVH[KXPHGLQRUGHUWREHVDFULÀFHGDVHFRQGWLPH DQGRQWKHDOWDURIWKHFRQFHSW$JDLQZHPHHWWKHHQWLUHSUREOHPRIOLQJXDOVLJQLÀFDWLRQ We must strongly suspect the tacit relationship Esposito establishes between discourse and concept. The introduction of Bios situates the major stakes of the question, “not only what does it mean, but when was it born, the concept of biopolitics?” [xii]. The will RISKLORVRSKLFDOUHFRQVWUXFWLRQLQKLVWRULFDOGHFHQWHULQJLVREYLRXVKHUH7KHGLIÀFXOW\ arises in the enunciation of biopolitics as concept. For the last is immediately glossed as one “lexical vein” in “a line of discourse” [xii]. So, vocable or concept? The concern with lexical veins should lead to the title %LRVDQG=Ŀďor Bio-. Or the lexicon bears concepts in the latent state, most often incompletely formed—until the arrival of the philosopher, who at last polishes the words. The learned one would come at the end of the line, recuperating that which the speaker sensed only confusedly and discarding the dregs (]Ŀď for example). If contemporary philosophy has recognized the place of language and of la-langue in conceptual construction, then the relationship sketched by Esposito seems a bit brief. The odyssey of the concept within discourse replaces the odyssey of the Spirit in the real. Both ride a slope that skittishly evades points of aberrancy, in the event of which speech is transformed into a more or less imperfect actualization of concepts that the philosopher alone must consolidate. Esposito moves without warning from Nietzsche to Charles Richet, from Dracula to the Nazi treatises on racial hygiene. The comparison of the incomparable must be understood as decisive to research in the “human sciences” or “humanities.” And still we should be careful to specify the name of that in which one would attempt the angel’s leap. In Bios, all scruples as to method are effaced by the omnipresence of the concept. Then it becomes possible to move from literature to medicine to political organization, for these discourses share a lexicon, and therefore concepts. It is the therefore that I refuse. The KRPDJH(VSRVLWRJHQHURXVO\SD\V)RXFDXOWUHYHDOVRQHRIWKHJUHDWHVWGLIÀFXOWLHVRIWKH :KLOHWKH´FDWHJRU\µRIZKLFK(VSRVLWRVSHDNVRIWHQDSSHDUVWREHDORFDODFWXDOL]DWLRQ DQFKRUHGLQDGLVFRXUVHDQGDFRQWH[WLWGHULYHVÀQDOO\IURPWKHFRQFHSW·VLQFOXVLRQ6HHIRULQstance the relation between plural and singular in the title Categorie dell’impolitico. 90 author of The Order of Things (Les Mots et les choses). On the same subject of discursive collision among disciplines, we were saying that Agamben enhanced the effect of authorLW\DQGWKHSRPSRIVFLHQWLÀFLW\PDUNHGLQ)RXFDXOW,Q(VSRVLWRZHDUHFRQIURQWHGLQ plain sight with what an analysis of discourse can harbor. That which is enunciated is detached from its enunciation, from its project, from its place in discursive registers, from its potential performativity, and so on. To the extent that a law and a novel may encounter each other, so the gap between them requires as attentive an accounting. At the end of The Order of Things, Foucault distinguishes a trihedral of knowledge whence “the human VFLHQFHVDUHH[FOXGHGµ>@&RQVWLWXWLQJQHLWKHUDQHZGLPHQVLRQQRUDVXUIDFH WKH\EHORQJWRD´FORXG\GLVWULEXWLRQµ>@'HYLDWLQJVOLJKWO\,ZRXOGVD\WKDWWKH analysis of discourse displays its objects identically; it organizes them with no depth. An analogous method brings to the surface unexpected convergences and divergences that are at times revelatory. The strategy remains, however, a reductive one if it neglects in advance the macrodifference between a book of medicine, a samizdat, and a thesis. The resort to discourse makes tongues, language, and speech objectively disappear: in other terms, one simply eludes what makes discourse possible. In his return to a concept removed from the internal plurality supposedly inherent in episteme, Esposito distinguishes himself from Foucault. Reinhart Koselleck’s Begriffsgeschichte (“conceptual history”) is explicitly evoked in the recent preface to the new edition of Categorie dell’impolitico [vii]. The same move, in sum. Seized in time, discourse expresses the history of the concept. Thus texts are transformed into linguistic supports. This leads to the double postulation of a concept that would act upon the social—and of enunciation as transparent medium. Koselleck maintains that “it has been possible to form concepts that have liberated new realities.”18 Let us note it is the concept WKDWOLEHUDWHV$QDORJRXVO\WKHÀQDOVHJPHQWRIBios, carrying the title of “Philosophy of bios,” presents the future of biopolitics as conditioned “by the manner in which conWHPSRUDU\WKRXJKWwill follow its tracks” [215, my emphasis]. This conclusive thought restores power to the concept as such. ,WGHÀQLWLYHO\FODULÀHVDQ\KHVLWDWLRQUHJDUGLQJWKH “lexical vein”: the lexicon bears meaning only in function of the concept that commands it. Because the “living must be thought of in the unity of life” [214–15], because there is FRQFHSWXDOXQLW\(VSRVLWRKDVÀQDOO\QRWKLQJZKDWHYHUWRGRZLWKWKHZRUG]Ŀď Now I would like to propose that a single substantive is no more the guarantor of DXQLTXHVLJQLÀFDWLRQWKDQWZRWHUPVPD\LQGLFDWHDFRQVWDQWDQGSUHGHÀQHGDOORFDWLRQ RIPHDQLQJ$QGULJKWDZD\,·OOFRUUHFWWKDW$IWHUDOO(VSRVLWRLVQRWVHHNLQJVLJQLÀFDtion at all but the sense of the concept, patiently constructed by the history of usages he uncovers and by the history he is composing. If it is a question of reading texts, evidence DFFXPXODWHVLQH[KDXVWLEO\VRVLJQLÀFDWLRQGRHVQRWFRPHDERXWE\GLVFRQWLQXRXVZRUGV EXWE\WKHLUFRQÁDJUDWLRQ$VIRUWKHlife in tongue, it is not a pure concept, on occasions preformed or corrupt: it is at each moment reelaborated in enunciation. That one meaning can be settled and in common would be plausible (although such a settlement would EHPLQLPDODQGLQJHQHUDOPLVOHDGLQJLIQRWIRUWKHIDFWWKDWWKLVYHU\PHDQLQJÀQGVLWV value in the excess that enables it. To say “life”—if it is a question of saying it—undoes WKHGHÀQLWLYHHYHQWRWKHSRLQW³SDUWLFXODUO\LQOLWHUDWXUH³RIIUDFWXULQJFRQFHSWXDOLW\ When Euripides maintains life in life, he is already threatening the efforts of semantic investigation; he shows, moreover, that life differs from life, such that the living PDWHULDOLW\ of the idiom procures a signifying difference. Esposito is, in turn, precariously positioned, IRUKHKDVQHJOHFWHGWKHSURFHVVRIVLJQLÀFDWLRQ As regards methodology, textual reading is directed by and toward the philosophical—a telos for the book. Esposito seeks to reground this knowledge within a polytechnic perspective. The history of philosophy aligns itself with the history of law or of medicine; .RVHOOHFN ´6R]LDOJHVFKLFKWH XQG %HJULIIVJHVFKLFKWHµ 4XRWDWLRQ WUDQVODWHG E\ WKH author. diacritics / summer 2006 91 yet it would be less than accurate to see this as a particular privilege of the historical discipline. What is true for history is true for philology. Held to be crucial, they are yet UHFWLÀHGLQWKHPHDQLQJRIWKHFRQFHSW,QWKLV(VSRVLWRLQGHHGFRQYHUJHVZLWK$JDPEHQ Multidisciplinary scholarship yields to SKLORVRSK\ as early as the work’s subtitle. The venture reterritorializes a vast textual continent rather than assembling procedures, protocols. The Foucauldian archaeologist of discourses begets a dé-disciplinarisation that WDNHVSODFHWRWKHEHQHÀWRISKLORVRSK\³DQGZLWKDEVROXWHVLQFHULW\LQ(VSRVLWR1RRQH will consequently be astonished that historical studies are few in number, even in the pages consecrated to genocide [see 146 ff.]. The Begriffsgeschichte, or the “history of ideas” [Esposito, Categorie vii], will in any case be translated into the history of philosophy’s renewal, which responds, at a distance, to the wishes formulated by Gilles Deleuze as early as 1968: “the history of philosophy is the reproduction of philosophy itself” [xxi/4]. The historical reach of reproduction in general is kept in suspense, however, if we were to retain Deleuzian terminology. How does one move from one conception to the next? +RZWRUHÀQHWKHbios? Indicating several times a skepticism of the grand ruptures à la )RXFDXOWRUjOD$JDPEHQ(VSRVLWRTXDOLÀHVWKH´JHQHVLVµRIELRSROLWLFVDV´VSHFLÀcally modern” [Bios xiii] but declares “one of its roots” to be meanwhile “recognizable also in earlier eras” [xiii]. Does recognition imply a transhistorical ground? We return to the latency of the concept, which would remain nonetheless subsequent to Antiquity.19 We seem to have dived into biopolitics at the end of the nineteenth century, at a point of junction between politics and medicine. Nietzsche’s work reports contrasting virtualities: his is an “extraordinary seismograph” [xiv]. Temporal progression would then be neither a juxtaposition of ruptures nor a simple forward movement, but an accumulation of shock waves automatically swelling in size. This model would suppose a decline of the concept after the acme of Nazism (“in Nazism biopolitics experimented with WKHPRVWWHUULI\LQJ form RIKLVWRULFDOUHDOL]DWLRQµ>P\HPSKDVLV@7KHODVWSDUWRIWKHERRNGRHVQRW share this “optimistic” view. In the section on post-Nazism, it is more a question of “interUXSWLQJLQDGHÀQLWLYHPDQQHUWKLVWHUULEOHWKDQDWRSROLWLFDORUGHUµ>@E\LQÁHFWLQJXSRQ ELRSROLWLFVDUHYLWDOL]LQJDIÀUPDWLRQ+RSHZRXOGQRWKDYHVHQVHLIWKHVHLVPLFLPDJH were preserved. I conclude from this that the superlative achievement has unsettled the system of conceptual history. Or again, that Esposito approaches the sequence of thoughts and facts in a nonhomogeneous manner: inexorability, interruptions, deviations. Both hypothetical readings expose the site at which the philosophical concept defaults itself. In the very body of philosophy wherein it desires a place, Bios is led back to the constitutive GHÀFLHQF\RIWKHUDWLRQDOH[SRVLWLRQRIWKHFRQFHSW7KHV\VWHPLVOLWHUDOO\RYHUVKRWE\ WKHLQÀQLWHLWDLPVWRFRQWDLQ,DPQRWUHSURDFKLQJ(VSRVLWRDVKHGRHV$UHQGWIRUQRW KDYLQJ´WKRXJKWLQGHSWKµ>@,DPLQGLFDWLQJRQHÀVVXUHLQSKLORVRSK\$WWKHIDXOW OLQHQRRWKHULQVWLWXWLRQDOL]HGNQRZOHGJHZLOOKHOS(VSRVLWRÀOOLQWKHYRLGQRWHYHQWR straddle it; for he has deprived himself of the resources of the disciplines. History, absent, will not throw a bridge over the abyss that history reveals. (VSRVLWRVWXPEOHVDQHZRQWKHVLJQLÀFDWLRQRIWKHKLVWRULFDOWKLFNQHVVLQWKHYDVW body of texts he convokes. The same word can mean something else in reiteration, as different terms may intersect by dint of the alterity that enunciation confers. Texts, constituted in turn by phrases and words, are possibly bound by the same phenomenon. The biopolitical corpus proceeds—apart from or beyond the hermeneutical act of regrouping—from an invariant’s variation. In the reiteration of forms, themes, words, schemas, or statements, alterations may arise. Any history of discourse that would deprive itself of the teleological purport of the concept would take seriously the lingual nature of its “object.” Everything is always the same but can be different. This “history” tells of the heterogeneity of the homogenous—which is better than falling back upon heterogeneous 92 &ILQSDUWLFXODUWKHDQDO\VLVRI3ODWRBios 51. paradigms (shock waves, rupture) in the anxiety to cover the defect. To do another kind of history would require an account of each utterance in respect to the perfomativity of political and legal paroles, wherein acts are not indomitably detached from words. This entails a consideration of the site, the force, and the reach of a text beyond its layout on the discursive plane, without which one runs the risk of making “more terrible” the old incarnation of the Hegelian idea: the factual illustration of a treatise or the adventitious horizon of a booklike world. The condition of this methodical redimensioning would make it possible to perceive the conceptual weakness without, however, stopping there. The jusqu’auboutist interdisciplinarity verges on the indiscipline to the extent that it continues up to sites of fracture and so passes beyond the procedural limitation of knowing. It is not a question of constructing a patchwork with scraps of knowledge. Rather than falling back upon encyclopedism alone, open to wherever the wind may blow, the interdiscipline postulates at once RQWKHLQÀQLWHDQGH[KLELWVSRLQWVRIDUUHVWFROOLVLRQDFFLGHQWV%\UHIRUPLQJLQWKLVZD\ the rich hypotheses of Roberto Esposito, a history bordering on that of the tongue would HQVXHDQGIURPWKHFRQFHSWXDOÀVVXUHZRXOGGUDZWKHIRUFHWRFRQWLQXH&RQWLQXDWLRQ OHW XV QRW GHFHLYH RXUVHOYHV ZRXOG OHDG IDU DÀHOG IURP Bios and displace by several removes the problems already askew in Homo Sacer. This putative book remains to be written, and will perhaps always remain so. The Multiple Lives of Politics $WWKLVOHYHORIFULWLTXHWKHXUJHQF\VHHPVWRUHTXLUHVRPHWKLQJHQWLUHO\RWKHUWKDQDÀFtive work. Agamben had the merit of investigating the possible relations between politics DQGOLIH(VSRVLWRFORVHVWKHLQTXLU\ZLWKDQDSSHDOWRDYLWDOUHDIÀUPDWLRQEH\RQGDPRUtiferous biopolitics. For Agamben, the present day had been dominated by the renunciation of the Greek bipolarity between bios and ]ĿďFor Esposito, today’s world has been determined since the beginning of modern times: that is, since we emerged from the reign RI$QWLTXLW\:KDWWRPDNHRIWKLVGLYLGH",Q$JDPEHQLWÀWVWKHDSRFDO\SWLFUHSUHVHQWDWLRQ³EXWWKHVRFDOOHGSURRIRILWVUHDOLW\LVPLVVLQJ(VSRVLWR·VDSSURDFKFRUUHVSRQGVÀnally to a theoretical decoherence. Advancing by anachronism, I would hope to put aside the hypothesis of an absolute rupture, one that Bios, we recall, relativized in the span of a page. We will thus conclude with a supplementary collation between the Greek scene and our current one. Rather than remaining with the pure unicity of an isolated era (whether it be the Athenian City or our age of biometric desolation), I opt for a violent shift, which would make the biopolitics in all politics resurface. So let us read an Aristotle who is neither the holy origin nor the Father; and let us move from Politics to Nicomachean Ethics. ,QWKHODWWHUZHÀQGUHÁHFWLRQRQOLIHDQGWKH bonds between citizens. The initial assertions of Politics about the ]ĿRQSROLWLNRQthat is PDQ³WKRVHVWDWHPHQWVVRFUXFLDOIRUWKHHQWLUHGLVFXVVLRQUHYDPSHGE\$JDPEHQ³ÀQG there a pendant. We read in fact that “by his nature, man is a political thing,” and that “man is by nature a political thing” [8.9.1169b]. The attribute politikon is neutral, which the periphrase “political thing” means to indicate. Neutral: while in these same textual UHJLRQVGLVGDLQIRUWKHDQLPDOLVKHDUGWKHTXDOLÀFDWLRQRIPDQLQEthics is less engaged with his ravaging humanism than in Politics. Finally, politikon refers directly to the City, the polisDQGWKHÀUVWIRUPXODPD\EHSXWLQWKHVHWHUPV´E\QDWXUHPDQOLYHVLQD&LW\µ The anachronism I am hazarding here would not go so far as to confuse society and City, for polis includes also the organization of power that extends beyond collective hierarchies. 20. Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea 1.7.1097b. Man LVIRUWKHQRQJHQGHUHGFDWHJRU\RIanthropos. diacritics / summer 2006 93 If the living animal (]ĿRQ) is temporarily absent from these axioms, life surges forth—alive and well. I intentionally abbreviated the second sentence, which in its more integral version reads: “man is by nature a political thing and he lives with others” [my emphasis]. The VX]ďQis literally a living-with, but to pair it with the Heideggerian Mitsein would be misleading. In effect, VX]ďQin its other uses at the core of Ethics, designates a strong community that is marked particularly by friendship, or philia. It surely does not designate a relation of coexistence with the Other in general, and refers more to those affective or practical relations that rest upon activities in common. The VSHFLÀFLW\of VX]ďQ in regard to the citizenry entails this “and” (kai) that in turn relates it to the political. The human being is a member of the City and implied in an ensemble of particular associations. Let us add that sumbioun appears in Ethics on two occasions, and as a bonus the substantive sumbios. The word sumbioun is derived from the verb Agamben said was “rare in attic prose.” Twice Aristotle intentionally associates the composite terms ]ďQand bioun. In several successive lines, sumbioun and VX]ďQ designate in an identical manner the sharing of an existence between people;21 a parallel phenomenon is repeated further on.22 This can no longer surprise us. All the same, I wanted especially to note these shifts so DVWRHVWDEOLVKWKDWWKHSUHÀ[FKDQJHVQRWKLQJRIWKHOH[LFDORVFLOODWLRQ7KHLQWHUFKDQJHability is evidenced even when Aristotle makes a list of activities that friends can do in common: “some drink together, others play dice together, or together they do sport and WKH\KXQWRUWKH\SKLORVRSKL]Hµ>D@´7RJHWKHUµFRQYH\VWKHDFFXPXODWLRQRI SUHÀ[HGZRUGVLQsun, which are just as much subcases of VX]ďQcited at the head of this UXEULF>E@$WWKHHQGRIWKHVHULHVWKHSKLORVRSKHUV\QWKHVL]HVKLVGHVFULSWLRQ with the formula: “all devoting the days they spend together to what they precisely like in OLIHµ>D@Life is bios and directly echoes the beginning of this sentence, about the multiple and individual reasons for “living”—wherein “living” was written ]ďQ We had shown that Agamben’s explanations of the Greek language in general lacked validation in use. The function of Aristotle’s writing teaches us another thing, clearer still after reading Esposito. The Stagirite is not beneath conceptualization when he moves, indeed with insistence, from bioun to ]ďQduring the course of his text. On the contrary, KHFRQÀUPVWKHLGLRPDWLFRUJDQL]DWLRQDQGDUWLFXODWHVDWKRXJKWWKDWLVQRWULYHWHGWRWKH word but produced in the act of enunciation. Not only does a word not equal a concept; but a concept does not necessarily correspond to one word. The concept is not absolutely anterior to language, which would otherwise approximate it. After all, doesn’t Aristotle’s rupture with Platonism begin with his rejection of the theory of Ideas, as mentioned in the introduction to Ethics? I will go further, to risk even an irrevocable divorce with the Aristotelian project. From the moment that the concept is recognized as a construct, as a lingual production, WKHLGHD·VÀVVXUHLVDOUHDG\DQQRXQFHG:LWKVLJQLÀFDWLRQRFFXUULQJE\ZD\RIZRUGV between them, even beyond them, the principle of identity falls down—at least on the lingual level. A substantive can signify other than itself and the same thing as another. An exemption to internal noncontradiction is possible, which threatens to resound in the constitution of the concept at the places of its foreclosure. The implications of what I am sketching complete the critique of unitary rationality in Esposito: it is permitted, with or without proper authorization, by the rereading we were conducting of Aristotle. In any event, we have to face the necessity to retain not only bios. Life is expressed ELRV]Ŀď Another may read vita or life, accordingly: life is life here, and diverges there. But it is time to refuse the edict of the underlying concept. On occasion certain conceptions may dominate, as, perhaps, “biologization” in Nazism. In no case do they precede, however, 21. Cf. 4.5.1126a and 4.6.1126b. 22. Cf. 10.10.1171a and 10.11.1171a. 94 or even form, a unitary semantics. Finally, their majority position is evaluated according to minority options, ones they could not obliterate with a single blow. The accumulation of amicable activities occasions a second remark. No doubt $ULVWRWOHFRQVLGHUVWKHÀQDOsumphilosophein (“philosophize together”) as an occupation superior to the preceding ones (“drink together,” for example). The characterization of VX]ďQ³“putting words and thoughts in common”23—is eloquent in this regard. However, in the conclusion we cited of the two books consecrated to friendship, the author recognizes life to be intrinsically dependent on neither its form nor its content. To live together LPSOLHVWKHSRVVLEOHPXOWLSOLFLW\RIOLYLQJ,ZDQWWRUHFRQÀJXUHWKHDUJXPHQWLQWRDUHsponse to one scruple of Esposito’s. The current consensus on the existence of biopolitics seems often to be accompanied by a secret and profound disagreement on the subject of bios. In retrospect, besides my serious doubts concerning conceptual communities, I wonder whether the meaning of bio- in biopolitics need necessarily be standardized. If Nazism is one biopolitical apogee—or ELR]Ŀď-political apogee—did the controlled and annulled life not exceed medical parameters? All those activities listed by Aristotle were also deeply affected by the Third Reich. A certain death was also brought into these lives. Destruction in life, oriented through racial control, entails a ruin beyond the medical or the “biological.” Life is not only life. $ULVWRWOHDOORZVXVDÀQDOUHDVVHVVPHQWRIWKHFXUUHQWGHEDWH+HUH,KDYHLQVLVWHG the VX]ďQand sumbioun are distinct from politics. And nonetheless they depend on it. The HQWLUH ÀUVW SDUW RI Nicomachean Ethics maintains the “architectonic” and “sovereign” SODFH RI SROLWLFDO VFLHQFH LQVLGH NQRZOHGJH >D@ (WKLFV GHSHQGV XSRQ SROLWLFV The VX]ďQof friends is thus linked to the “living-well,” the HX]ďQthat is the objective of the City in Aristotle’s Politics and Nicomachean Ethics. The political perspective of Aristotelian ethics is renowned. The intention behind its particular, and culminating, case of friendship is without doubt. That is why the types of philiai are compared to those of government, why friendship is indispensable among citizens, and so on.24 In The Politics RI)ULHQGVKLSJacques Derrida fully developed this temptation to inscribe philia within politics, in Aristotle and beyond. And no sooner is this done than the movement is inverted, signing another severance between ethics and politics. Whereas governmental science is by rights superior to moral study, the acquisitions of the latter specify the content of the former. The place held by philia LQSROLWLFDODQDO\VLVFRUUHVSRQGVWRDVHFRQGLQÁXHQFHRIHWKLFVXSRQLWVQHFHVVDU\ condition. In the same respect, “living-together” is facilitated by “living-well”; it even contributes to it, but it does not belong solely to it. In the enumeration evoked earlier, it is obvious that Aristotle does not present as the purpose of the City a continual sharing of occupations, by all and for all. There is no Spartan call to uniformity; Plato’s disciple has no special admiration for Lacedemon and its Republic of similars (homoioi). Decidedly, “life-with” does not coincide with HX]ďQA life exists, which breaks ranks with politics and is not consigned to the naturalness of the household. From the superposition of politics upon ethics life surges forth. 7KLVDPELJXRXVV\VWHPHYLGHQFHVDGRXEOHFRQÀJXUDWLRQ%HJLQQLQJZLWKWKHQHFHVsity of living well, Aristotle makes ethical life depend upon political existence. Because of the primacy of the City-State, full human life exists only in the polis, through politics. The slightest action, the slightest thought, the slightest word, since they imply a collective space, are governed politically. Only the City may lend constituency to bios and ]Ŀď At the same time, the ethical VX]ďQremains in excess to this vital political ground. Life surpasses the frame that “authorizes” it. 23. Cf. 4.12.1126b and 9.9.1170b. &ILQLWVHQWLUHW\ diacritics / summer 2006 95 ,Q$ULVWRWOHWKHGLVWULEXWLRQRIIRUPVRIOLYHV>E@LVLQWHQGHGDVDQDQWLFLpatory response to this porte à faux. <HWLWRQO\DGGVDGLPHQVLRQWRWKHHGLÀFH)RULI political life (bios politikos) is one of three modes of existence (alongside the movement WRZDUGSOHDVXUHRUWKHRU\PDQ·VGHÀQLWLRQDVDOLYLQJSROLWLFDODQLPDODQGKLVQDWXUDO obligation to seek a life lived well within the City destabilize this new horizontal structure. Apart from the “political life”-form, each human life is already political, according to the phrase (]ĿRQ) politikon. Still in the light of our times, therefore, I propose to interpret the porte à faux in a different manner. Ethical or quotidian ELRV]Ŀďis constituted by and depends upon the polis; human life is E\QDWXUHpolitical; and the a-polis man is an “inferior”25 being. The totality of life, from its nature to its content, from its form to its quality, is coextensive with the political thing. However, friendly or ethical excess comes to contradict the grandeur of the political hold. I want to see in this—both against Aristotle and for him—the underpinnings of a double language. The Stagirite, imperturbable laudator of Athens, celebrates a total polis that governs all life, and all of life. Then with one unexpected gesture he designates an outside, a space where life exceeds life. Whereas he announces the political totality of OLIHKHGHQRXQFHVWKLVWRWDOLW\E\RSHQLQJDYLWDORXWVLGHÀHOG So I return to the grammar of the contemporary debate. It may be that the state of WHFKQRORJ\WKHLQÁXHQFHRIPHGLFLQHDQGWHFKQRFUDWLFHQJLQHHULQJSURGXFHDJRYHUQment of beings incommensurate with the totalizing endeavor I have just described. In the perspective of Bios, the fact that “politics is characterized as LQWULQVLFDOO\biopolitical” [xiii] may remain more modern than ancient. On the other hand, the second part of what creates biopolitics for Esposito (“life [. . .] LPPHGLDWHO\translatable into politics” [xiii]) is completely in place in Aristotle. We can understand Esposito’s resolve to give rise to a novelty, to mark a caesura. But if it is conceivable to follow him in his analysis of the mechanization and manipulation of the living, biopolitics today will never be more than a reinforced extension of the total relation between politics and life, as it was described by Aristotle. Politics adjusted the intensity of its control by cultivating an alliance with bio-; EXWLWV$ULVWRWHOLDQTXDOLÀFDWLRQKDVQRWEHHQUDGLFDOO\DOWHUHG(YHQZHUHZHWRH[WHQG and reform Esposito’s proofs in the directions I have sketched, biopolitics will only remotivate politics’ ambitions for life that Aristotle’s ethics tried to limit. The combination of ancient methods with new procedures (medicine or genetics, for instance) only conÀUPVWKHWKHRUHWLFDOVWDELOLW\RIWKHSROLWLFDOV\VWHPVDWLVÀHGZLWK´PRGHUQL]LQJµLWVRZQ reign. Agamben declares that “modernity does nothing other than declare its own faithfulness to the essential structure of the metaphysical tradition” [8/11]. The phrase designates an invariance, true; yet it does so, alas, in the name of logos and the lost origin, which doesn’t need to be reiterated. At the price of a certain impoverishment, Agamben’s statement nonetheless depicts better than Bios the possible solidarity between Aristotle and today. The obsession with the totalitarian (history or category) in contemporary theories also appears as a protective measure to obscure the variable persistence of biopolitical action in politics.26 25. Aristotle, Politica A.2.1253a. +HUHLVDUHPDUNWKDWGHVHUYHVPRUHWKDQDQRWHEXWZKLFKWKHHFRQRP\RIWKLVDUWLFOH SUHYHQWVPHIURPGHYHORSLQJ%\DQRWKHUURXWH-DFTXHV5DQFLqUHFRPHVXSRQDVLPLODULGHDZKHQ KHLGHQWLÀHVELRSROLWLFVDVRQHPRGDOLW\RIZKDWKHQDPHVWKHSROLFH%XWE\H[WROOLQJWKHFRXQWHUPRGHORISROLWLFDOVXEMHFWLYDWLRQLQDQ\FDVHDOZD\VULYHWHGRQWKHSROLFHLVQ·WKHRSHQLQJKLPVHOI to a rehabilitation or distribution of a good SROLWLFVWKHRQO\RQHZRUWK\RIWKHQDPHDQGbad (poOLFHRUGHU"$ERYHDOOZK\ZRXOGZHZDQWWRPDLQWDLQDVSDWLDOH[WHQVLRQRISROLWLFVWKDWHQGVXS HQYHORSLQJWKHHQWLUHW\RIOLIH³PLQXVWKHUROHRIWKHSROLFH",VWKHUHQRRWKHUWRWKHSROLWLFDORWKHU" On the distribution between police DQGSROLWLFVVHH5DQFLqUHDisagreement 28 ff. [La Mésentente: Politique et philosophie II@2QELRSROLWLFVDVDIRUPRISROLFHUHDGWKHLQWHUYLHZJUDQWHGE\ 5DQFLqUHLQWKHMRXUQDOMultitudes, ´%LRSROLWLTXHRXSROLWLTXH"µ 96 The current variation is also a means of exploring a (hi)story. In that case, the contribution of the Italian corpus to “biopolitics” holds above all to the retrospective revelation it favors. Our exaggerated rereading shows that Aristotle had expressed a coextension of politics and life—and suggested something beyond the polis.28 In other terms, the modern era has not “given birth” to the political tendency to absorb life. But many contemporary thinkers forget what even Aristotle had not omitted: the totalizing ambition RISROLWLFVVKRXOGEHFRQWUDGLFWHGE\DQDIÀUPDWLRQRIOLIHLWVHOInotwithstanding the political order that attempts to contain it. Michel Foucault stated that “man, over millennia, remained what he was for Aristotle: a living animal and with the additional capacity for a political existence; modern man is an animal whose politics places his existence as a living being in question.”29 Now Foucault and his critics allow us to understand in Aristotle a postulate very different from the one usually attributed to him. For in reading Politics with Nicomachean Ethics ZHÀQGWKHLGHDRIDQDWXUDOO\political man. Exaggerating only a little: he is ELRORJLFDOO\a citizen. Life is political for those who act within the City, who conform to the triad of existences. But, according to Aristotle, OLIHLVIXQGDPHQWDOO\SROLWLcal in any case. Hence Foucault’s “addition” is thoroughly inexact: Nicomachean Ethics FHUWLÀHVWKDWWKHOLIHRIPDQLVLQWULQVLFDOO\DGKHUHQWWRWKHpolis. The “question” of life is posed precisely “in politics,” as presented by Aristotle. Aristotle the anachronist, as we are reconstructing him, should guard us from the mystical return to the origin; for if there are bios and ]Ŀďin these regions, the contemSRUDU\EHQWWRZDUGRSSUHVVLRQPD\WDNHHTXDOUHFRXUVHLQWKHP0LJKWRQH\HWÀQGWKH DGHTXDWHWRROVWRLQYHQWDQHZUHVLVWDQFH",ZRXOGUDWKHUPDNHDQRWKHUÀQDOVXJJHVWLRQ In Nicomachean Ethics, it is barely articulated but irreducibly there: this life in excess of the political force that handles it. Against political totality, there might be the impossible SRVVLELOLW\RIDQRWKHUOLIHGHVSLWHDOO1RWWKHDIÀUPDWLYHELRSROLWLFVVRXJKWE\(VSRVLWR nor the Aristotelian dissymmetry of ways of life subordinated in every manner to the RUGHUVRIWKH&LW\,DPVSHDNLQJLQVWHDGRIWKHXWRSLDQDIÀUPDWLRQRIDOLIHWDNLQJOHDYH RISROLWLFV+HUHWKHIDPLOLDUQRWLRQRIUHWUHDWZLOOQRWVXIÀFHIRUWKHZRUGLPSOLHVDUHturn or spiraling back onto oneself. It would be vain to join “those who turn their backs to politics” [Rancière, Disagreement 32/55]: we must depart and look things squarely in WKHH\H1RORQJHUVXIÀFLHQWLVWKHKRUL]RQWDOTXRWDSULYDWHKHUHSXEOLFWKHUHKHUH,DP a citizen, there an autonomous individual). It will always be a matter of leaving politics: recognizing its necessity, its grandeur, its risks—and abandoning it. This movement cannot be completed once and for all but forever begun again. I recognize the political hold, ,GRQRWGHQ\LWDQG,GHVHUWLWLQWKHYLWDOFRQWUDGLFWLRQWKDWVLJQLÀHVVRPHWKLQJ2QH can hope to combat political tyranny by walking its terrain (the resistance of the exile in Hardt and Negri, Esposito’s renovated biopower, the true politics in Rancière); but some VXSSOHPHQWDU\refusal is needed. Stating that all livable life is political, or that we VKRXOGRQO\ÀJKWSROLWLFDOO\DJDLQVWWKHFRQWHPSRUDU\ELRRUGHUZRXOGEHWKHXOWLPDWH victory for the totalizing ambition of polis and police. I do not call anyone to inaction. On the contrary, let us redouble the political acts of our unassailable lives; se moquer de la politique c’est aussi faire de la politique. Let us begin by DIÀUPLQJlife outside of politics—even today. Politics is not of a concept, of an obscured essence. It is rather a collective, frail, ruined construct of events, words, deeds, thoughts, feelings, forces, powers, 27. The quotation marks are meant to refer to a title or to index a problem. 7KDWLVZK\WKHpolitikon DWWULEXWHLVKLJKO\VSHFLÀFLIRQHFRPSDUHVLWZLWKRWKHUSRVVLEOH ´KXPDQµIHDWXUHV7KHUHLVIRULQVWDQFHQRH[FHVVRIlogos in Aristotle, even suggested in a negaWLYHZD\ 29. History of Sexuality, Vol. I: An Introduction 143 [Histoire de la sexualité, vol. I: La volonté de savoir ´XQDQLPDOYLYDQWHWde plus FDSDEOHG·XQHH[LVWHQFHSROLWLTXHµP\HPSKDsis]. diacritics / summer 2006 97 NQRZOHGJHVDOZD\VROG³DOZD\VQHZ:HVRPHWLPHVÀJKWIRUEHWWHUSROLFLHVEXWSROLWLFV LVQRWDOO-XVWDVRXUZRUGVFROOLGHDQGWHOOXVVRPHWKLQJMXVWDVVLJQLÀFDQFHSDVVHVOH[LFDOPHDQLQJVZHRXJKWWRVSHDNRIWKHÀVVXUHVRIWKHSROLWLFDO)DUIURPWKHWRWDOL]LQJ tendency of any bio-politics, we should remember that our life is able to be more. Critical scholarship is a possible way of articulating these ideas. But only one way, among others, such as passionate friendship or poetry. In order not to die as a consequence of my measured, chiseled, programmed, that is, totally political life, ,VKRXOGDOVRVWULYHEH\RQG WKDWÀHOGUHVHUYHGIRUPHSeek not only political subjectivation against the police, nor the DIÀUPDWLRQRIDELRSRZHUDJDLQVWWKHGHDWKWKDWGHWHUPLQHVH[LVWHQFH6D\DQGVKRZthat there is life in life. Live politics and leave politics. 7UDQVODWHGE\&ODULVVD&(DJOHZLWKWKHDXWKRU WORKS CITED Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Trans. Daniel HellerRoazen. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998. Trans. of Homo Sacer, Vol. 1: Il Potere sovrano e la nuda vita. Turin: Einaudi, 1995. Ammonius Alexandrinus. 'H DGÀQLXP YRFDEXORUXP GLIIHUHQWLD Ed. Klaus Nickau. Leipzig: Teubner, 1966. Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1958. Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. New York: Columbia UP, 1994. Trans. of Différence et répétition. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1968. Derrida, Jacques. 7KH3ROLWLFVRI)ULHQGVKLSTrans. George Collins. New York: Verso, 7UDQVRIPolitiques de l’amitié. Paris: Galilée, 1994. Dubreuil, Laurent. “De la vie dans la vie: Sur une étrange opposition entre ]Ŀďet bios.” /DE\ULQWKH$WHOLHULQWHUGLVFLSOLQDLUH² Esposito, Roberto. %LRV%LRSROLWLFDHÀORVRÀD7XULQ(LQDXGL ________ . Categorie dell’impolitico. Milan: Il Mulino, 1999. ________ . Communitas: Origine e destino della comunità. Torino: Einaudi, 1998. ________ . Immunitas: Protezione e negazione della vita. 7RULQR(LQDXGL Estienne, Henri. 7KHVDXUXV*UDHFDHOLQJXDHParis: A. F. Didot, 1831–65. Foucault, Michel. Dits et écrits. Vol. 4. Paris: Gallimard, 1994. ________ . +LVWRU\ RI 6H[XDOLW\ 9RO ,$Q ,QWURGXFWLRQ Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: 5DQGRP+RXVH7UDQVRIHistoire de la sexualité, vol. I: La volonté de savoir. 3DULV*DOOLPDUG ________ . 7KH2UGHURI7KLQJV$Q$UFKDHRORJ\RIWKH+XPDQ6FLHQFHVNew York: RanGRP+RXVH7UDQVRILes mots et les choses: Une archéologie des sciences humaines. Paris: Gallimard, 1966. Koselleck, Reinhart. “Sozialgeschichte und Begriffsgeschichte.” Sozialgeschichte in Deutschland. Entwicklungen und Perspektiven im internationalen Zusammenhang. Vol. 1: 'LH 6R]LDOJHVFKLFKWH LQQHUKDOE GHU *HVFKLFKWVZLVVHQVFKDIW Ed. Wolfgang 6FKLHGHUDQG9RONHU6HOOLQ*|WWLQJHQ.OHLQH9DQGHQKRHFN5HLKH² Heidegger, Martin. :KDW,V3KLORVRSK\"Trans. William Kluback and Jean T. Wilde. New York: Twayne, 1958. Trans. of :DV LVW GDV³GLH 3KLORVRSKLH" Pfullingen: Neske, 1956. Philo, Herennius. 'HGLYHUVLVYHUERUXPVLJQLÀFDWLRQLEXVNaples: D’Auria, 1988. Rancière, Jacques. “Biopolitique ou politique?” Multitudes. http://multitudes.samizdat. net/Biopolitique-ou-politique.html. ________ . 'LVDJUHHPHQW 3ROLWLFV DQG 3KLORVRSK\ Trans. Julie Rose. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1999. Trans. of La Mésentente: Politique et philosophie. Paris: Galilée, 1995. 6FKROLD+LSSRFUDWHPDQG*DOHQXPVol. 2. Königsberg: Borntweger, 1834. 98
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz