© The Author 2014. Oxford University Press and New York University School of Law. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: [email protected] Book Reviews Haider Ala Hamoudi. Negotiating in Civil Conflict. Constitutional Construction and Imperfect Bargaining in Iraq. University of Chicago Press, 2013. 382 pages. $35. ISBN: 9780226068824. Zaid Al-Ali. The Struggle for Iraq’s Future. How Corruption, Incompetence and Sectarianism Have Undermined Democracy. Yale University Press, 2014. 304 pages. $35. ISBN: 9780300187267. Within the same year we have been treated to two terrific volumes on the political development of Iraq after the overthrow of Saddam Hussein, written by two Iraqis who, as legal advisors, have participated at different levels. Both works are exciting, well written and argued, and full of new information. They are especially valuable to me for their long views on this development, coming nearly a decade after I concluded my own study on Iraq more or less after the ratification of the Constitution in 2005.1 What is, however, astonishing is that the two books seem to depict two alternative universes. Zaid Al-Ali tells a story of almost continuous political crisis, caused not only by “corruption, incompetence and sectarianism” but also by the failure of the constitution making effort and the resulting constitution. For AlAli, the American war and occupation, and especially the disastrous conduct of the latter, 1 Andrew Arato, Constitution Making Under Occupation: The Politics of Imposed Revolution in Iraq (2009). They also very much complement al-Istrabadi’s 2010 study: Feisal alIstrabadi, Islam and the State in Iraq. The Post 2003 Constitutions, in Constitutionalism in Islamic Countries 607 (Rainer Grote & Tillman Roeder eds., 2012). I•CON (2014), Vol. 12 No. 3, 808–840 are at the root of a political and constitutional failure that the externally imposed Iraqi elites in charge did very little to rectify. In his presentation, the ethnic and sectarian divisions of Iraq were at best intermediary causes, not historically deep-seated, and they were greatly exacerbated by the occupation’s policies. Al-Ali’s narrative is well documented, paying equal attention to constitutional process, administrative decisions, party politics, economic policy, and local struggles, both during and after the formal American occupation. Haider Ala Hamoudi tells a very different story. Without denying the dysfunction of political and economic developments in Iraq, he presents the constitution as the one dimension in Iraq’s post occupation period that has succeeded to an extent. While he does regard the negotiations that have led to the constitutional outcome as “imperfect,” he sees a positive dimension here as well: namely the adoption of an incremental method of constitutional development, made possible by these very imperfections. In his depiction, the imperfect process and its legitimacy problems led to a “capacious” text allowing for subsequent incremental development. Hamoudi rarely disagrees with my own earlier critical reconstruction of the constitution making process in an “externally imposed revolution,”2 but he sees the very contradictions that I (among others) pointed to in the constitutional outcome in a positive light. He views the obviously imperfect constitution as merely incomplete, and indeed preferable to any non-contradictory product that could have been achieved in 2005, or to the breakdown of the process altogether. Interestingly, 2 Haider Hamoudi, Arab Spring, Libyan Liberation, and the Externally Imposed Democratic Revolution, 89(3) Denver U. L. Rev. 699 (2012). Book Reviews Hamoudi believes that the ethnic and ideological divisions of Iraq are far more ancient and fundamental than does Al-Ali, and he argues moreover that constitutional deferral has helped to reduce the intensity of the divisions between Sunni and Shi’a, as well as between the religious and the secular. How can we explain the divergence between these two sophisticated and scholarly authors? Most obviously it is a question of perspective. Though they are both legal scholars, Al-Ali’s analysis is above all political, while Hamoudi focuses mainly on the legal. Thus Al-Ali demonstrates how little the constitution helped to solve the fundamental political problems facing Iraqi society, whose ills have become worse over time. In particular, he shows the great gap between constitutional forms and actual political practice. Even where a previous problem is reduced in significance, like the danger of forming wealthy regions that would further impoverish the rest of the country, he points out that this too has been achieved in part by change of political influence (within the Shi’i elites) and in part by a refusal to enforce the constitution by the government (facing new demands made by Sunni majority provinces). For Hamoudi, this very outcome represents a partial convergence of Sunni and Shi’a perspectives, made possible by the fact that the constitution left the matter open. Leaving aside the different political judgments (and perhaps commitments?) of the two authors, this example shows that a truly complete analysis of constitutions must combine political and legal perspectives.3 One could thus argue that if the 2005 Constitution had definitively resolved the procedures for the establishment of regions in a clear, unambiguous legal text—in that particular moment— it would have most likely led to the immediate 3 Such a two-sided perspective (Zweiseitenlehre) was postulated by Georg Jellinek in his once famous Allgemeine Staatslehre (3d ed. 1920). It has been recently revived by Julian Arato here in I•CON. See Julian Arato, Constitutionality and Constitutionalism Beyond the State: Two Perspectives on the Material Constitution of the United Nations, 10 Int’l J. Const. L. 627 (2012). 809 formation of a Shi’a super-region and the breakup of Iraq that many predicted.4 But one could respond that, without the political development of both sides, the deferral of the question for later statutory regulation would not have helped and could have greatly worsened matters. The relevant statute in October 2006 only confirmed what the extreme regionalists wanted in the Constitution itself. The fact that the new statute was never used was a political matter, and cannot be seen as a mere function of a very short deferral of the decision in the constitutional text.5 This example, in any case, does not resolve the main divide between the two authors, namely whether it is theoretically possible for a constitutional project to succeed while the relevant political community is in almost constant crisis, and when state formation is constantly in doubt. In a recent discussion at NYU School of Law, Al-Ali’s answer was clearly negative, and at that time his own take on constitutional theory became very clear.6 According to him, in a country without a genuine past of constitutionalism, only a strictly codified, entrenched, and enforced basic law can be described as a workable constitution; and he argues that Iraq has no such effective constitution despite the existence of a formal 2005 document bearing the name. While Al-Ali does not explicitly deny the empirical possibility of “constitutions without con4 5 6 Peter Galbraith, The End of Iraq (2006). Put in the text, according to Hamoudi (at 80, 174), as a result of a phone-call from President Bush, that, as he recalls, I and many others have described as pathetic and inconsequential. His argument that the delay allowed the formation of a more nationalist opinion among the Shi’a is unconvincing given the shortness of time involved. In fact, the delay did not affect the legislation in the least, confirming the impression that the concession to the Sunni Iraqi Islamic Party was meaningless. Shi’a public opinion, however, was never “federalist” whether before, during, or after the negotiations. See alIstrabadi, supra note 1; Zaid Al-Ali, Constitutional Legitimacy in Iraq, in Constitutionalism in Islamic Countries, supra note 1, 635. See also Al-Ali, supra note 1, 635 at 635 810 I•CON 12 (2014), 808–840 stitutionalism,”7 he clearly rejects such an option from a normative point of view. And, of course, he has no difficulty at all in showing the almost constant divergence of Iraqi political realities from the formal constitution. Hamoudi’s idea of the constitution in general, and especially in a deeply divided society, is different. Strongly influenced by Hanna Lerner’s recent book,8 he believes that constitutions—especially successful ones in deeply divided societies, but not only there—are better understood as open ended frameworks, deferring and delaying fundamental decisions by their unresolved elements and ambiguities. Thus where, for Al-Ali, a textual constitutional contradiction can only be proof that the constitution cannot and is not even meant to be applied, to Hamoudi, on the contrary, ambivalence, ambiguities, and contradictions open up the chance for later construction in a positive direction. Unfortunately, the latter neglects to say why opening up cannot equally lead into authoritarian or destabilizing directions. And, indeed, according to Zaid Al-Ali executive authoritarianism has been the main contribution of the Iraqi Constitution so far. One would be tempted to describe one view as a civil lawyer’s picture of the constitution, and the other as a common law perspective. Yet the matter cannot end there. Even in classical civil law countries like Germany and France, everyone knows that constitutional principles and values are open to construction and subsequent development. At issue is not the open-endedness of constitutional texts as such, but the specific nature of deferral, in other words: what is deferred, how much, to whom and by whose authority. In one of Lerner’s two main cases, for example, the first Israeli Knesset deferred the drafting and enactment of the whole documentary constitution, by its own authority 7 8 Nathan Brown, Constitutions in a Nonconstitutional World (2002); Feisal al-Istrabadi, A Constitution without Constitutionalism: Reflections on Iraq’s Failed Constitutional Process, 87 Tex. L. Rev. 455 (2009). Hanna Lerner, Making Constitutions in Deeply Divided Societies (2011). and to other Knessets just like itself. Like Hamoudi after her she has stressed fundamental disagreements concerning the nature of the state as the reason, neglecting the obvious interests of the executive power (in that case, Ben Gurion) not to be bound or restricted by constitutional rules enforceable in court. It is that neglect, perhaps, that made the religious–secular divide appear then as fundamentally intractable as it later became. In any case, the result in Israel was a paper-thin constitution with at best extremely weak (and relatively recent) entrenchment, and with a structurally weak supreme court. The court did have a few successes, but their viability depended on the divisions of the Knesset produced by an ultra-proportional electoral law, as well as public opinion behind some important decisions. The so-called Basic Laws have always been extremely vulnerable to simple legislative reversal, as well as alteration of the jurisdiction of the judges by the legislature, as has been repeatedly proposed by the right. In India, Lerner’s other main case, constitution makers produced a massive, wellentrenched constitution, deferring only 22 clauses (according to Granville Austin’s count) out of 368 (now 448).9 Not only was a three-track amendment rule10 established with higher levels of entrenchment applying to most of the text, but the 1950 Constitution established a very strong table of rights and Granville Austin, The Indian Constitution. Cornerstone of a Nation 256 (1966). 10 Track 1: simple majority of parliament in the case of up to 22 clauses. Track 2: 2/3 majority of each chamber. Track 3: 2/3 majority of each chamber plus the majority of state legislatures. See Austin, supra note 9, at 255 et seq.; see also Sir Kenneth Wheare, Constitution Amendment: The Nature and Scope of the Amending Process (Loc Sabha Secretariat n.d.). The Basic Structure doctrine has now in effect added a fourth track, which implicitly suggests that certain types of fundamental change are constitutional only if they are made by reversion to the original constituent power. Reference to the original constituent power is now common among constitutional judges as distant geographically as India and Turkey, Germany, and Colombia. 9 Book Reviews expressly provided for constitutional review by the Supreme Court. These provisions were not left for later legislative construction. The gap between the two supposedly incremental models, those of Israel and India, is quite significant. On first appearance, Iraq belongs to the same category as India, since a detailed and entrenched constitution was indeed produced in 2005, and formally at least strong constitutional review was indeed provided for (Hamoudi at 81–82).11 But we should take care not to be taken in by superficial appearances. Hamoudi mentions several devices by which things can be deferred, and notes that all of them have been amply used in Iraq. Of these, constitutional principles open to future construction are unobjectionable, and I doubt whether Al-Ali would wish to do without them. Contradictions and ambiguities are another, more problematic matter, as are even more explicit deferrals to future legislative majorities. Together, these methods indicate the variety of agencies to whose later decisions present problems can be deferred: legislative majorities; the highest court with the power of constitutional review; or the amending power. As in the case of fundamental principles, we assume in most countries today that it is the job of constitutional or apex courts to construe and construct constitutional meaning that is left open. The centrality of this point was illustrated by the Egyptian Supreme Court before the fall of Mubarak, largely defanging the famous article 2 of the Sharia clause by construction.12 In Iraq, the problem was that the very existence of such a court, the Supreme Federal Court, was itself left in Prof. Istrabadi who shows this, correcting a small mistake on my part based on the incorrect English text, realizes that the gain is compromised by the decision to include Islamic law experts in the apex court. See al-Istrabadi, supra note 1, at 618ff; 620ff. 12 See the excellent presentation in Tamir Moustafa, The Struggle for Constitutional Power 107–110, 166–167 (2007). See also Clark Lombardi, Designing Islamic Constitutions, 11(3) Int’l J. Const. L. 615 (2013). 11 811 great doubt by the constitutionally unresolved requirements for creating it. To Hamoudi, this too was a creative opening, since article 130 of the Constitution left all previous rules and regulations in place, allowing the Court inherited from the Transitional Administrative Law (TAL) (the interim constitution) to preserve itself until the unlikely event that there could be sufficient agreement of parliament (twothirds) to create the new court under the new constitution (Hamoudi at 97, 188, and 259, n.90).13 But as described by both Al-Ali and Hamoudi, such an “inelegant” court, with its pre-constitutionally regulated internal composition increasingly in doubt (Hamoudi at 188–189; Al-Ali at 132–133), is not likely to be, and has not been in fact, in a position to play a strong independent role in the construction of open-ended and ambiguous principles.14 It “cannot occupy a new constitutional role very easily,” Hamoudi reluctantly admits, and then cites the leaders of the largest party Iraqiya challenging the legitimacy of the court.15 Thus the job of construction is left to the government, or at best the parliamentary majority that would rarely expect to be over-ruled by a court with weak legitimacy. Only in the case of the rare conflicts between Thus he corrects my mistaken prediction that a Supreme Court with constitutional review powers could not be formed at all (Hamoudi at 259, n.90). 14 If a new court is not formed, and it is not likely to be, the old one may become increasingly weaker with time. In his excellent article, Feisal alIstrabadi was more optimistic, pointing to a case where the Court overruled a lifting of immunity by parliament of one of its deputies. See al-Istrabadi, supra note 1, at 618–624. Highly critical of the new constitution’s concessions to the perspectives of the religious, including the appointment of fiqh experts to the apex court, alIstrabadi did not evaluate the consequences of the carry-over of the TAL’s Court into the post 2006 regime. 15 al-Istrabadi, supra note 1, at 188. He goes on to say: “the Federal Supreme Court is self-evidently vulnerable on both political and legal grounds, and would be almost surely unwilling to challenge Najaf on core areas of its concern” (id. at 189). 13 812 I•CON 12 (2014), 808–840 the executive and parliament could such a court play an independent role. Generally, in order to construct, or indeed to change, the constitution, the ordinary political process seems to suffice in Iraq. Though there is a formal amendment rule, in reality informal change, Verfassungswandel tends to entirely replace Verfassungsaenderung, with all the resulting legitimacy problems.16 Since informal change need not satisfy demanding legitimation requirements, in Bruce Ackerman’s terms, monism replaces dualism. Hamoudi seems to discount the likely outcome of this type of move tending to obliterate the difference between constitutional and normal politics, allowing incumbents to produce and change fundamental rules in a manner always favorable to their political interests. Such an empowering of future governments is, in any case, what happens when a constitution-making body defers to a future legislative assembly, in other words, when constitutional development is left to subsequent statutory enactment—as in Israel, with very ambiguous results for constitutionalism. This was the case in India only in relation to a few distinct areas of the constitution, and however understandable deferral was in the given context, even there the results were very mixed. While the opening to the legislative majority had good results in the area of the linguistic readjustment of provincial boundaries,17 the refusal to constitutionally craft a uniform personal code in the beginning has been not only harmful to the rights of Muslim Georg Jellinek, Verfassungsaenderung und Verfassungswandlung (1906). There have been no amendments to the Iraqi Constitution under either the formal rule, art. 126, or art. 142 that was supposedly to replace it temporarily. Whether art. 126 is still in effect, since the “amendments stipulated” in art. 142 (cl. 5) were never “decided upon,” is itself a question. No one seems to care very much. 17 Sujit Choudhry, Managing Linguistic Nationalism Through Constitutional Design: Lessons from South Asia, 7(4) Int’l J. Const. L. 577 (2009). See also Austin, supra note 9, at 257; Granville Austin, Working a Democratic Constitution: The Indian Experience 155–156 (1999). 16 women,18 but has arguably contributed significantly to the success of the Hindu Right. In the case of Iraq, Hamoudi stresses the one positive example of region formation, where no new regions were in fact formed and the integrity of the state was preserved, aside from its total lack of power in Kurdistan based on facts on the ground from before the 2003 war and occupation. Yet, does not Al-Ali have an important point when he argues that today the blocking of the formation of regions, though supported by the majority, implies disregarding both the constitution and the law, with deeply harmful effects for constitutionalism and the rule of law? (Al-Ali at 142–144). Had no constitution emerged in 2005, the fallback position would have been the TAL which allowed only the formation of small regions, and even that required participation by the central parliament. Had the project of amendments from 2006 to 2009 reformed the constitution, the result very likely would have been the same. Thus, today’s Sunni demands could be legally denied under the TAL, or under a constitutional reform, as against the Constitution of 2005 and its enabling legislation, that require a more nationalist government to accomplish its program through illegality. Empirically speaking, the result would be the same, but the normative consequences would be very different. Hamoudi invites us to focus on the empirical results of deferral, that were in any case highly contingent, and to disregard the normative consequences. Finally, we should not lose sight of the amending power established by special rules in almost all modern constitutions, including India and Iraq if not Israel. If there has to be deferral to legislation rather than interpretation, why not defer to the amending power that would have the virtue of not being easily controllable by incumbents especially in a multi-party setting? Hamoudi, who was involved in one failed amending process from 2006 to 2009, seems to have become allergic to that alternative. He claims that the amending process is too time-consuming and too Neera Chandhoke, Individual and Group rights. A View from India, in India’s Living Constitution 207 (Zoya Hasan et al. eds., 2005) 18 Book Reviews costly. But does not that claim depend on the structure of the amendment rule that could be difficult or easy, monolithic or plural, and can even be multi-tracked as in constitutions from India to Canada and South Africa? Iraq in 2005 in fact adopted a multi-leveled amendment rule (art. 126) that included three rules in one—the first, a quasi-eternity clause (regarding the powers of regions); the second banning amendments for two terms (regarding rights and fundamental principles); and a third requiring ratification by referenda. Such a rule indeed opens up the terrain for informal change by construction. It is true, the temporary rule Hamoudi and his colleagues operated under (art. 142)—the supposed concession to the Iraqi Islamic Party required to get the constitution itself ratified in 2005—was yet another entirely different rule. Its ratification requirements were even more difficult, since it retained the three province veto inherited from the TAL. Assuming the two-thirds parliamentary majority, that potential veto made the passing of any amendment on region formation extremely unlikely especially since parliament was allowed to pass and indeed already passed the relevant legislation on this question by simple majority. Why would that majority become part of the 2/3 needed to pass the amendment reversing a law that was then exactly the law it wanted? If the Shi’ite-Kurdish dominated government and legislature wanted to fulfill a promise made to the Sunni Iraqi Islamic Party, why did they pass legislation confirming the constitutional provision objected to by that party? 19 In the actual event, the parliament did not act on the amendment proposal that the new committee, the Constitutional Review Committee in fact very belatedly submitted in 2009. But the reason by then was not that it had the law that it wanted, but because the fundamental shift in Shi’a leadership from the Islamic Supreme Council of Iraq to the Da’wa, i.e., from those desiring a Shi’a super-region to Iraqi nationalists. The latter, supported by general Shi’a opinion, were not going to use either the constitutional provision or the enabling legislation to form their region (Hamoudi at 2–4). 19 813 This story of futility does not reveal much about the potentials of a differently constructed amendment rule and amendment process. In a new, supposedly capacious and incremental constitution, one could have produced a very different and more flexible multitrack amendment rule to deal with the issue,20 and not the bizarre, ambiguous structure allowing the use of simple legislative majority and an inflexible amendment rule for the solution of the very same question. In any case, Hamoudi’s explicit discounting of deferral to the amending power is based on the given rules in Iraq, and should not be presented as a general preference in new constitutions for deferral to the ordinary legislative process. Let us for the moment assume that a capacious constitution was produced, one open to construction, incremental development, knowing how much and what to defer and to whom. Does the way we first adopted such a constitution matter at all? Hamoudi, who considers the Iraqi method of constitution making imperfect because of Sunni exclusion, seems to answer in the negative. We know this because he has indicated that the Egyptian Constitution produced in 2012 under Mr. Morsi’s presidency, despite the disastrous and exclusionary process first initiated by the Supreme Command of the Armed Forces (SCAF), and later controlled by the Muslim Brotherhood’s assembly majorities (first in parliament, and then in the two “constituent” assemblies) was capacious enough to allow the settling of fundamental division over the question of Islam in the state (Hamoudi at 226–228). As we now all must realize, the character of the process in this case very much seems to have mattered, and was indeed used to delegitimate, and then annul and replace, the constitution associated, rightly or wrongly, with Brotherhood imposition. Would a more inclusive process have saved this new constitution—one involving negotiations concerning an interim constitution, and the rules for making the final one rather than their Andrew Arato, Multi-track Constitutionalism Beyond Carl Schmitt 18(3) Constellations 324 (2011). 20 814 I•CON 12 (2014), 808–840 imposition from above? We will never know for sure, but the Tunisian example seems to show that where there are negotiations concerning the initial rules of the democratic transition, the first electoral consequences are likely to be more inclusive, and the constitutional outcome more consensual.21 We should also pose to Al-Ali the question of whether or not process matters. His argument seems to have a deterministic cast, even if in the end he tries to say that there are now possible perspectives for future development in Iraq. It is not at all obvious on what he bases this sudden optimism. Equally important for comparative analysis is the question whether a better, much more inclusive process producing the TAL, and the rules for the election of the constitutional assembly could have made a difference in the pattern so far. Not only Tunisia, but also the contrast between Colombia and Venezuela indicates that it does matter how things unfold at the very beginning.22 But neither Tunisia nor Colombia were countries occupied by a foreign power, one that destabilized the state, and constructed initial political participation, as in the case of the Iraqi Governing Council whose incumbents managed to stay in the key political positions throughout the process of constitution making. The Alfred Stepan, Tunisia’s Transitions and the Twin Tolerations, 23(2) J. Democracy 89 (2012). He focuses on the inclusive 150 (or 155)-member Ben Achour Commission, established by co-option, which negotiated the interim rules in Tunisia for the election of the Constituent Assembly. Of course, there are too many other differences to reliably ascertain the reasons for the Tunisian–Egyptian difference, such as the respective strength of Salafi movements and the military, both much stronger in Egypt. But the electoral rule mattered, both its highly proportional nature, and the requirement for male–female alternation on all electoral lists, guaranteeing equal representation for women. 22 Renata Segura & Ana María Bejarano, ¡Ni una asamblea sin nosostros! Exclusion, Inclusion and the Politics of Constitution‐Making in the Andes, 11(2) Constellations 217 (2004) and David Landau, Constitution Making Gone Wrong, 64 Ala. L. Rev. 923 (2013). 21 United States and especially the Coalition Provisional Authority have indeed much to answer for during the process of making the interim constitution—even if both the process and the result also bear the marks of several other actors, the Shi’ite clergy and even more the leaders of the main Kurdish parties. Nevertheless, after the elections of 2005, under new management in Iraq, the American authorities did indeed recognize their mistake, and became for a moment the strongest partisans for the inclusion of Sunni Arab and Iraqi nationalists. Would it have mattered if they succeeded? Very possibly, but arguably they could not have succeeded because of the problem of sequencing. Had Sunni inclusion been tried before the making of the interim constitution, as Sergio de Mello recommended as early as 2003, it might have worked. Adding representatives of excluded groups when the relevant negotiating figures were all included by co-option would have kept all those present on the same level. After elections, even under very unfortunate rules that dramatically skewed representation to the detriment of provinces with civil war conditions, the situation was different. Now duly elected Shi’ite and Kurdish representatives had to share power with Sunni politicians who were co-opted on American insistence. That they were later excluded is not at all surprising, especially given the contradictions of the American position insisting on both Sunni inclusion and adherence to narrow time limits, as Al-Ali rightly points out and he is hardly the first to do so (Al-Ali at 86–87). That honor belongs to Sheikh Humam Hamoudi, the chair of the Constitutional Committee (and the expanded Commission) in 2005. Process arguably does matter, but so does sequence and the amount of time allotted to a process. Or, in other words, a multi-stage process, such as the one actually used in Iraq, could have helped, but only if used in an inclusive and fully pluralistic manner, if a proper sequence of multiple stages was maintained, and sufficient time was provided for all the stages. These two important books invite us to try to assess what has been learned from Iraq, and now it may be worthwhile to consider Iraq’s Book Reviews constitutional process together with those of more recent revolutions. Looking at Iraq and Egypt together, there are at the very least important negative lessons to be learnt. First, elections should not come too soon, and certainly not before a framework for truly competitive elections is fully and inclusively negotiated. In Egypt, there were no negotiations, and elections came too soon. In Iraq elections did come arguably at the right time, but without inclusive negotiations. As a result, in both countries, it turned out to be impossible to arrange more inclusion by cooptation, after elections did take place. Second, we learn in both countries that the making of a constitution should follow an adequate and therefore relatively long time frame. Third, more positively, a focus on time and sequence may cast in a different light the matter of supposedly uncompromisable and non-negotiable divisions that are said to require an incremental procedure and constitutional deferral. We should indeed ask whether Hamoudi is right that in a deeply divided society there are some matters in principle not open to compromise, and therefore only incremental constitution making, with a capacious constitutional text involving both ambiguity and deferral can succeed. But even if matters were absolutely closed to negotiation and compromise, why would deferral help? It could be that matters that appear initially intractable are not, or will not remain so, if actors are allowed to develop, internally and in their mutual relations. It may be that Al-Ali’s impulse is right—that given sufficient time during, rather than after the making of the final constitution, matters that appear uncompromisable, like the territorial structure of the state, as well as religion and state relations could also be successfully negotiated so that each side gets at least its second best. Paradoxically then, the idea of using time productively can speak for both positions. We can significantly extend the time for making the final constitution, argues Al-Ali, and use time effectively to make the compromises we may very well be capable of making.23 We will not know how much can in fact be com Such was even more explicitly the position of alIstrabadi, supra note 7, that is positively cited in this context by Al-Ali, supra note 5, at 660. 23 815 promised if sufficient time were available. Or we can make the final constitution relatively quickly, give it a very capacious structure, and use the time thereafter to incrementally improve it. That is the position of Haider Ala Hamoudi. But then why not bring the two positions together, and advocate a third one, namely, the model from Spain and South Africa, involving the making of two constitutions, an interim capacious one, achieved by a pluralistic, inclusive process of negotiation, and the other, a more complete one, by a freely elected but non sovereign constitutional assembly that is given sufficient but not unlimited time to do its job.24 Such an arrangement makes learning possible in between the two constitutions, rather than exclusively during or after the making of the final one. Not having an interim agreement means that we have to learn in the context of revolutionary provisionality, when power rather than law, fact rather than legal authority decides. The lesson that one learns under such a setting is to not take law, including constitutional law seriously. The function of genuinely nego- In Iraq, there was indeed a two-stage constitution-making process, but neither stage involved adequate inclusion of the relevant parties. Thus here, the multi-stage model would require the making of a third constitution, involving more inclusion and relative consensus or principled compromise. This is in effect the concluding argument of Zaid Al-Ali, converging with the perspective of al-Istrabadi. In my earlier view, the opportunity was there in the amending process Hamoudi participated in 2006–2009, and I still think that the failure of this was more significant than he allows. I do not have the text of the amendments agreed upon in committee that he unfortunately does not detail in any way. The blog Niqash/Legislation identified the key issues, even if regarding the amendment rule mistakenly. While the 2/3 three-province veto is not part of art. 126, it would have been very useful to amend this cumbersome article in any case. See Sarmad al-’Ubaydi, Intractable Positions on the Constitution, niqash/legislation (Sept. 23, 2009), http://www.niqash.org/ articles/?id=2015&lang=en. 24 816 I•CON 12 (2014), 808–840 tiated, rather than imposed and therefore legitimate interim constitutions, especially with strict rules for final constitution making, is to allow learning to take place under constitutional rules that block the way to renewed dictatorship. Putting the learning after the making of the final constitution on the other hand means to obliterate the line between constitutional and normal politics, to the detriment of constitutionalism and the advantage of incumbents whoever they may be. A final constitution, though it will inevitably be interpreted and constructed, must settle some fundamental matters if it is to be a constitution in the full formal sense, or a constitutionalist constitution in the material sense. One can defer matters and learn under a constitution only if some of the most important matters are settled. One cannot learn when there is no structure, with everything perpetually open. Yes, it may be necessary to leave some issues, beyond constitutional principles and values, open for future construction. Yet, the most important thing to be settled is the identity of those who will be able to construct all fundamental matters, including what is deferred. Informal change can never be fully excluded, nor should it be even if it should hold a hierarchically lower position than either constitutional review or constitutional amendment. Because of such a hierarchy of the modalities of change, the formal rule(s) of change and the entity charged with enforcing it against “unconstitutional law” remain the most important things to settle whatever else is left open to future interpretation and construction. Only then can one begin to speak of “constitutions with constitutionalism.” Andrew Arato New School for Social Research Email: [email protected] doi:10.1093/icon/mou034 Michael Herz & Peter Molnar, eds. The Content and Context of Hate Speech: Rethinking Regulation and Responses. Cambridge University Press, 2012. 544 pages. $47 (pbk). ISBN: 9780521138369. The title of the book under review, The Content and Context of Hate Speech: Rethinking Regulation and Responses, is well chosen for the collection of essays assembled by Michael Herz, Professor of Law at Cardozo Law School in New York, and Peter Molnar, Senior Research Fellow at Central European University in Budapest. To the extent that this can be done in a few words, it encapsulates an important part of the debate over what to do about hate speech. The essays reflect a broad consensus that hate speech is one of the afflictions of our era and that there is a need to counter it. The issue that divides the scholars who contributed to this volume is when it should be legally prohibited. In most of the world, the decisive factor is the content of hate speech. On the other hand, in the United States, the critical question is the context in which hate speech takes place. The American approach reflects a system of constitutional rights in which the core value is liberty and in which the rights set forth in the First Amendment, especially freedom of speech, are of central significance in embodying the concept of liberty. Americans prize freedom of speech as an essential aspect of who they are as human beings; as a necessary component of democracy; and also as the means to protect all other rights as it ensures that they may speak out when any right is threatened. There are few countries, if any, where the protection of freedom of speech is as extensive and as robust as in the United States. Although Americans generally agree that hate speech is loathsome, it is nevertheless legally protected in public discourse except when it involves incitement of lawless action in circumstances in which it is likely to produce such action.1 That is, incitement of 1 See Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969).
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz