ARTICLE Democracy and collective decision making Samuel Issacharoff* Around the world, traditional barriers to judicial engagement with the structure of democratic politics have fallen remarkably as courts increasingly entertain first-order questions about the structures of governance. This article explores judicial responses to a particularly vexing problem: who should be the polity that decides first-order political issues? The most famous such judicial encounter is that of the Canadian Supreme Court in a case involving whether Quebec had a right to secede based on a referendum of its own population. The discussion places the Canadian Court’s resolution of that issue in the context of how numerous courts around the world, including the United States Supreme Court, have addressed similar questions, though generally in cases not so freighted as the potential dissolution of the national federation. Concluding from a review of such cases that courts forced (or willing) to engage such issues are likely to find little mooring for their resolution in either legal doctrine or political theory, the article warns that courts should be wary of following their impulses to treat such first-order conflicts about the structure of political systems as familiar claims of individual rights, even if that is the posture in which the issues are litigated. Much of the literature on the legal regulation of voting turns on the issue of who holds the franchise and what institutional arrangements should control the selection of officeholders. Ultimately, democracy is the process of aggregating preferences revealed as votes. At some level, the majority should prevail and, at some correspondingly high level of abstraction, there must be set institutional arrangements that confer legitimacy on the manner in which the collective choice is adduced. Within this framework there are a huge number of moving parts, dealing with the basic rights of participation and moving outward to the complicated role of political parties, campaign finance, rules governing the aggregation of votes, and an expanding universe of strategic interactions between all of these. Taken together, these make up the * Reiss Professor of Constitutional Law, New York University School of Law. I benefited from comments on an early version of this paper at the Conference on Democracy and Rationality at Hebrew University in Jerusalem and at a faculty workshop at NYU School of Law. I am indebted to specific comments from Erin Delaney, Cynthia Estlund, Clayton Gillette, Roderick Hills, Richard Pildes, Jeremy Waldron, and Katrina Wyman. Ian Samuel and Josh Stillman provided critical research assistance on this project. Email: issacharoff@exchange. law.nyu.edu © The Author 2008. Oxford University Press and New York University School of Law. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] I•CON, Volume 6, Number 2, 2008, pp. 231–266 doi:10.1093/icon/mon003 Advance Access publication March 28, 2008 231 232 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 complicated law of democracy, as it both channels and informs the ability of the polity to reach decisions on governance within the bounds of political legitimacy. The question of political legitimacy provides an interesting divide in the theoretical and legal literature. There are two dominant approaches for assessing the success of a democracy in terms of basic political legitimacy. Democracy may be thought of as primarily forward looking, offering to the desires of the electorate the prospect of representation. Or it can be defined retrospectively, by its ability to enforce accountability through the capacity to hold governors to task for their actions, most critically by removing them from office for failure to discharge the public interest. The prospective view evinces a greater concern for minority access in the process of ensuring some representation for all sectors of society. The retrospective view is more concerned with the capacity of majorities to form and reform, compelling government to anticipate and respect shifting political sentiments. Both the prospective and retrospective views of democracy assume, as they must, the preexistence of a fixed polity against whose political aspirations the scope of democratic legitimacy can be measured. Not surprisingly, then, neither has a great deal to say about the first-order challenge of determining what is the polity. The question of defining the political constituency arises in two characteristic forms, each coming about in response to two different challenges. First, there are the claims of a subsection of the population to determine its own political affairs by redefining itself outside the broader political order, as with separatist claims for national independence or, at a lower level, with claims for municipal deannexations. Alternatively, there are challenges to political compromises that condition political participation on defined membership in subordinate constituencies. One characteristic form of this alternative is formal power sharing among specific groups in the society—defined in the political science literature as consociationalism1—in which the ability of any individual to participate is mediated through his or her membership in a designated subgroup of the population. By contrast, there can be a number of institutional arrangements—federalism is a key example—that assign participation rights to geographical regions and then funnel rights of participation through these arrangements. Each of these potential challenges pushes the boundaries of claims that are handled through the normal workings of democracy itself. It is difficult to resolve satisfactorily within the political process challenges to the integrity of that process. For example, a claimed right of secession by a minority population will hardly be ameliorated if rejected by the majoritarian will of the parliament that may subsume the minority. But when presented to a court, where 1 See generally AREND LIJPHART, DEMOCRACY IN PLURAL SOCIETIES: A COMPARATIVE EXPLORATION (Yale Univ. Press 1977); Charles E. Ehrlich, Democratic Alternatives to Ethnic Conflict: Consociationalism and Neo-Separatism, 26 BROOK. J. INT’L L. 447 (2000). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 233 such first-order claims increasingly end up, the difficulty of identifying controlling first principles emerges just the same. The legal rendition of such ultimate questions suffers from the same defect as the attempted political resolutions. Most legal questions are presented interstitially, something which has the salutary effect of limiting the disruptions caused by any particular ruling. However, every so often, questions arise that push further than what is comfortably handled within the confines of legal doctrine, even in the common law setting in which the scope of judicial inquiry is far-reaching. This article deals with some of the more difficult and perhaps unresolvable issues that emerge concerning the question of what is the proper composition of the polity for settling deeply contested issues, particularly as they are presented to courts, which are more and more willing—and, occasionally, specifically tasked—to engage such issues. All modern democracies channel an individual’s democratic right to participate in self-governance through complicated institutional arrangements. We have come a long way since the Athenian assembly of all citizens or even the New England town meeting that comfortably encompassed all franchise holders in direct governance without any intermediaries. What happens, then, when the fundamental institutional arrangements of a democracy are themselves challenged? What are the principles that emerge from either legal doctrines or even political theory that should guide the resolution of such claims? The discussion will begin with a series of cases in which autonomy rights are claimed by a subset of the population demanding the right to determine independently their own legal and social arrangements vis-à-vis the broader community. The most compelling and most famous of these cases addresses whether the people of Quebec had a right to secede from Canada, or to seek to do so, through a direct plebiscite of the Québécois.2 In Quebec and in each of the other examples, the judicial resolution is unsatisfying precisely because of the apparent lack of a controlling principle for determining what is the right level of aggregation for collective decision making. The second part of this article, then, places the difficulty of defining the polity, properly understood, in the broader context of the long-standing theoretical uncertainty about the nature of collective decision making. The literature on what happens when the people gather to express their will runs the gamut. On the one hand, we believe intuitively that two heads are better than one, and we can extrapolate from that to a much broader reservoir of knowledge when the many decide rather than the few. On the other hand, we know that mobs can act in destructive ways and to an extent that individuals acting alone could never achieve. And we suspect that as soon as a lot of uninformed or uninterested citizens come together, they are likely to be manipulated by the most selfinterested or the most unscrupulous among them. 2 Reference re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217. 234 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 Assuming the contradictory intuitions about collective wisdom are all, to some measure, true, and assuming that empirical proof regarding which surmise is likely to prevail is either hard to come by or likely to be inconclusive, our next step is to ask how democracies should respond to claims for collective autonomy in making fundamental decisions. The last part of this article suggests that, despite the increasing judicial confrontation with such first-order issues, there is not likely to be a satisfactory response. Rather, democracies have developed a series of temporizing institutional arrangements that avoid these ultimate issues, the particular forms of which are likely to be historically contingent. Rules governing decision making, such as separation of powers, federalism, and bicameralism, all combine to limit the presentation of ultimate issues regarding the legitimacy of the political order. Together, they speak to a need for caution in the exercise of judicial review and of the need for a set of limiting principles to guide courts in engaging first-order questions of the constitution of the body politic. 1. (Dis)aggregating the political community The most dramatic confrontations with the question of what is the proper definition of the polity emerge in challenges to the continued existence of a nation as an ongoing political entity. Such claims to a right of autonomy by national subgroups, often denominated a right of national self-determination, emerge with some regularity in international law. Most notably, in the immediate postcolonial period following World War II and, again, in the aftermath of the breakup of the Soviet Union, secessionist groups proclaimed a right of independence based on broadly stated claims to a democratic entitlement to selfdetermination.3 While long-standing grievances against political or economic subordination resonated widely, particularly against the notoriously oppressive ancien régimes, the claim of an inherent and inescapable democratic right to withdraw from national and constitutional arrangements ultimately could not be sustained. All nation-states require the ability to govern cross-temporally and to shift resources from one region to another to meet all sorts of needs. No nation could command its citizens’ loyalty if the beneficiaries of today could readily walk away should the tide of benefits and costs flow in another direction tomorrow. Yet, despite the inability to frame such a demand for autonomy in the sweeping and categorical language of inherent democratic rights, the question of enforced aggregation remains a troubling one for democracies. Characteristic of the problems addressed in this article is the demand for the judicial enforcement of a right to autonomy, usually taking the form of the claim of a democratic right by a subset of the population in determining its own destiny. While this is often posed, directly, as a right of democratic 3 See generally TONY JUDT, POSTWAR 701–713 (Penguin 2005); CHRISTOPHER HEWITT & TOM CHEETHAM, ENCYCLOPEDIA OF MODERN SEPARATIST MOVEMENTS (ABC-Clio, Inc. 2000). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 235 self-determination, I will also turn to some examples generally not conceived of in this way to help illustrate the issue. 1.1. Devolving power [A] community of a higher order should not interfere in the internal life of a community of a lower order, depriving the latter of its functions, but rather should support it in case of need and help to co-ordinate its activity with the activities of the rest of society, always with a view to the common good.4 The principle of subsidiarity, enshrined in Catholic doctrine by Pope Leo XIII in 1891 in the famous encyclical Rerum novarum, has emerged as a mainstay of European Community law, particularly as regards administrative regulation.5 The basic principle of subsidiarity in EU law is intended to limit the reach of Brussels by creating a presumption of local regulatory autonomy, or, at the very least, a presumption in favor of national regulation as opposed to EU commands. For its enthusiasts, “subsidiarity is celebrated as a check on the monopolistic tendencies of the modern state; it is a plea for localism and doing things at the lowest possible level.”6 In EU law, the concept of subsidiarity makes the most sense when applied to economic matters. In some areas, such as the application of domestic competition (antitrust) law to conduct that extends beyond national borders, local authority must yield to EC-wide enforcement in order to confront the perceived problem at the scale at which it presents itself. But even in its initial full articulation in Rerum novarum, the concept of subsidiarity was premised on the primacy of the direct relation between an individual and the fruits of his labor. The encyclical was intended as a rejoinder to the intellectual challenge of Marxism and collectivism. As formulated, subsidiarity admitted of governmental activity only interstitially to tax and to provide for collective security to the extent the individual alone or through family was unable to do so. At the level of politics, however, the limiting effects of subsidiarity, even if accepted as a controlling principle, apply poorly. Political viability on the domestic 4 UNITED STATES CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, CATECHISM OF THE CATHOLIC CHURCH, pt.3, §1, ch. 2, at 1883 n.7 (2d ed. 1994), available at http://www.usccb.org/catechism/text/pt3sect1chpt2. htm#7. 5 The Maastricht Treaty’s subsidiarity provision reads: In areas which do not fall within its exclusive competence, the Community shall take action, in accordance with the principle of subsidiarity, only if and in so far as the objectives of the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the member-States and can therefore, by reason of the scale or effects of the proposed action, be better achieved by the Community. Treaty Establishing the European Community art. 3b, Nov. 10, 1997, 1997 O.J. (C340) 3. See generally ANTONIO ESTELLA, THE EU PRINCIPLE OF SUBSIDIARITY AND ITS CRITIQUE 74–179 (Oxford Univ. Press 2002). Patrick McKinley Brennan, Harmonizing Plural Societies: The Case of Lasallians, Families, Schools— and the Poor, 45 J. CATH. LEGAL STUD. 131, 133 (2007). 6 236 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 front can coexist easily with transnational economic alliances. The benefits of the European market are available to small nations, albeit at some cost to the customary prerogatives of sovereignty, such as coining one’s own currency or imposing tariffs at the national borders. Integration into the common market of Europe allows even small states to engage readily with markets beyond their political control. At the level of defining a right of autonomy to establish the political and social mores of a society, something beyond viability must be the test. There are some historical examples of a constitutional commitment to rights of autonomy. The former Soviet Union granted a formal right of secession to the diverse Soviet republics, a right whose attempted invocation undoubtedly would have resulted in the deployment of Russian tanks as seen in Budapest in 1956 and Prague in 1968. More sincerely, the post-Soviet Czechoslovakian constitution granted formal autonomy rights to the Slovakian half of the country—a right that was ultimately acted upon in the formation of two separate countries. The question of empowering smaller constituencies is posed, however, in countries in which there is no precommitment to an autonomy right and in which viability does not seem a meaningful constraint.7 The question becomes one of whether or not the subordinate unit of governance holds a “trump” that may be exercised on contested matters of sufficient importance to put at risk the joint enterprise.8 This is exactly the situation in Canada with the demands for independence for Quebec. Here, there is no claim that Canada has ever recognized a right of separation,9 nor is there a meaningful question of the ability of Quebec to survive independently. There are, to be sure, questions about the willingness of the Québécois ultimately to wean themselves from the positive transfer payments from the Canadian union. But in the aftermath of NAFTA and the opening of North American markets generally, an independent Quebec would no doubt be politically and economically viable, if perhaps poorer. 7 More typically, some countries build in limited autonomy guarantees at the local level, without recognizing any right to withdraw from the national confederation. For example, article 28(2) of the German Grundgesetz, which guarantees, even against action by the Länder, that local governments have “the right to regulate all local affairs on their own responsibility, within the limits prescribed by law.” GRUNDGESETZ (GG) art. 28(2), available at http://www.bundestag.de/htdocs_e/ parliament/function/legal/germanbasiclaw.pdf (official English translation of 2000). 8 For an elaboration of the idea of retained political power in the context of local governance, see Clayton P. Gillette, The Exercise of Trumps by Decentralized Governments, 83 VA. L. REV. 1347 (1997). 9 Canada recognizes a complicated federal structure that reserves important powers to the provinces within the overall constitutional framework and specifies specific powers held by the federal government. See In re Initiative & Referendum Act (Manitoba), [1919] A.C. 935, 942 (Manitoba P.C.) (explaining that the basic constitutional premise was “not to weld the Provinces into one, nor to subordinate Provincial Governments to a central authority, but to establish a central government in which these Provinces should be represented, entrusted with exclusive authority only in affairs in which they had a common interest. Subject to this each Province was to retain its independence and autonomy and to be directly under the Crown as its head.”). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 237 1.1.1. The Quebec reference on secession In 1998, at the height of one of the periodic upsurges in separatist sentiment in Quebec, the Canadian Supreme Court was presented with a question as direct as it was bedeviling: “[W]e are asked to rule on the legality of unilateral secession ‘under the Constitution of Canada.’ ”10 The matter was admittedly one of first impression and, since the existence of Canada could well have been in the balance, the Court faced the daunting prospect of ruling on a matter of last impression. The Court quickly discovered that the constitutional structure of Canada did not explicate the exact source of popular consent to governance; rather, “[t]he representative and democratic nature of our political institutions was simply assumed.”11 Without a clear mandate on the central question of the democratic premises of the state, the Court had to acknowledge the compelling claim of Quebec, at least initially: “The argument that the Constitution may be legitimately circumvented by resort to a majority vote in a provincewide referendum is superficially persuasive, in large measure because it seems to appeal to some of the same principles that underlie the legitimacy of the Constitution itself, namely, democracy and self-government.”12 The general appeal to democracy could not resolve the question of separation without first resolving the problem that “there may be different and equally legitimate majorities in different provinces and territories and at the federal level.”13 There were no mediating principles in Canadian constitutional law or in general democratic principles that could resolve the apparent conflict should a majority of the Québécois opt for independence while a majority of the broader Canadian constituency (including the Québécois) voted to preserve the territorial integrity of Canada. Rather, Canadian politics had long subsumed a form of Québécois separate representation through the reigning Liberal Party requirement that the leadership of the party alternate between French and English speakers and the party’s practice of setting informal quotas for cabinet seats between the two groups.14 Not only does Canadian politics strongly recognize the need for regional representation but Quebec has greater representation in the Senate than do other provinces; moreover, one-third of the justices of the Supreme Court are from Quebec.15 In addition, given the strong concessions toward regionalism on matters such as language, and given that overall 10 Reference re Secession of Quebec, [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217. 11 Id. at 253. 12 Id. at 259. 13 Id. at 255. 14 Brendan O’Leary, Debating Consociational Politics: Normative and Explanatory Arguments, in FROM POWER SHARING TO DEMOCRACY: POST CONFLICT INSTITUTIONS IN ETHNICALLY DIVIDED SOCIETIES 3, 16 (Sid Noe ed., McGill-Queen’s Univ. Press 2004). 15 Twenty-two of the one hundred and five Canadian Senators represent Quebec and three of the nine sitting Canadian Supreme Court Justices are members of the Quebec Bar. 238 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 economic benefits flowed to rather than from Quebec, there were no readily credible claims of oppression of the sort that may have sustained independence demands in the Baltics under the Soviets or in the broader regions of Kurdistan, for example.16 A formalist resolution could have been crafted—perhaps by focusing narrowly on the mechanisms of constitutional amendment along the lines of what will be discussed, subsequently, in the South African treatment of its legislators’ ability to defect to the opposition party. The Canadian Court could have construed the dissolution of Canada as a form of constitutional amendment requiring the full mandates accompanying any constitutional alteration. The effect would have been not only to move the level of decision making to the national level but to trigger the supermajority requirements for constitutional change.17 That presumably would have answered the challenge presented in a particularly unsatisfactory way: a minority constituency feeling aggrieved and unable to achieve its aims at the majoritarian level of national politics could only have appealed to the supermajoritarian constraints of the larger body politic. Such a course may have resolved the constitutional question but not the broader question of democratic legitimacy. At the end of the day, the Canadian Court found a halfway measure that granted separatist claims the right to initiate a dialogue on dissolution of the country. In what is known as the “clear majority/clear question” requirement, the Court granted to a majority of the Québécois the right to initiate a process of political renegotiation whose outcome could be secession, although those terms remained unspecified: A referendum undoubtedly may provide a democratic method of ascertaining the views of the electorate on important political questions on a particular occasion. The democratic principle identified above would demand that considerable weight be given to a clear expression by the people of Quebec of their will to secede from Canada, even though a referendum, in itself and without more, has no direct legal effect, and could not in itself bring about unilateral secession.18 16 By and large, the international law consensus on the right of self-determination, to the extent there is one, is limited to situations of conquest or colonization. See Patrick Macklem, Militant Democracy, Legal Pluralism, and the Paradox of Self-Determination, 4 INT’L J. CONST. L. (I•CON) 488, 505 (2006). 17 Formal mechanisms of constitutional amendment are a relatively new process in Canada. Prior to the constitutional reorganization in 1982, amendments of the Canadian Constitution were formally made by the U.K. Parliament as amendments to the British North America Act. Such amendments were typically approved only upon request endorsed by concurrent majorities of the House of Commons and the Senate, generally after obtaining a substantial degree of provincial consent. See generally PETER W. HOGG, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF CANADA 61–76 (3d ed., Carswell 1992). 18 2 S.C.R. at 265. Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 239 The effect was to create a species of “Canadian secession clause,” to use Sujit Choudhry’s formulation,19 although one that was not judicially enforceable. The Supreme Court’s gambit of subgroup rights to dialogue over a process of dissolution was never put to the test. The last referendum in Quebec occurred in 1995 and lost by less than a percentage point. Even here, there was considerable debate over the outcome, since the referendum prevailed strongly among the francophone Québécois but was defeated by the overwhelming opposition of the anglophone minority in Quebec, many of whom were recent arrivals from other parts of Canada, together with those known as allophones, namely, recent immigrants to Canada whose native language is neither English nor French and who now represent over 10 percent of the population of Quebec. For the past decade, while the main secessionist force, the Parti Québécois, has been a constant presence in Canadian politics its political fortunes have dwindled. Although it has not been put to the test in a genuine effort at secession, the Canadian Court’s analysis is significant for another reason, one with greater pertinence for this article. The question referred for judicial review was whether there was a right in either Canadian constitutional law or, at a higher level of authority, in international law that mandated the ability of a regional majority to compel secession. Rather than turn to a rights claim abstracted from politics, the Court turned to the nature of Canadian political institutions, finding an inextricable link between democracy and federalism. Claims of right regarding the political process must necessarily be mediated through the institutional structures of governance. At the very heart of a constitutional framework is the ability to “provide for a division of political power that allocates political power amongst different levels of government.”20 In rejecting the narrow rights claim, therefore, the Court concluded that the ultimate principle of constitutional settlement “would be defeated if one of those democratically elected levels of government could usurp the powers of the other simply by exercising its legislative power to allocate additional political power to itself unilaterally.”21 1.1.2. Consociationalism and formal devolution Ultimately, the Canadian Supreme Court’s decision represents a hybrid resolution of the problem of secession. The Court recognized a right of regional consultation which in turn might, depending on the outcome of that consultation, 19 This formulation is from Sujit Choudhry, Popular Revolution or Popular Constitutionalism? Reflections on the Constitutional Politics of Quebec Secession, in THE LEAST EXAMINED BRANCH: THE ROLE OF LEGISLATURES IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL STATE 480, 487 (Richard W. Bauman & Tsvi Kahana eds., Cambridge Univ. Press 2006). 20 2 S.C.R. at para. 74. 21 Id. 240 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 trigger a more formal set of autonomous regional rights that exist independent of the wishes of the national polity. A more extreme version of such assignment of rights to substrata of the polity is found in consociational systems, political arrangements in which the central divisions of the society are reflected in separate formalized representation.22 The American use of geographic districts drawn to ensure minority representation may be thought of as a weak form of consociationalism, one that sparked significant constitutional controversy when implemented most aggressively in the 1990s.23 In those societies that tried to stabilize internal division through formal power sharing—examples include Lebanon, Cyprus, and Sierra Leone— there had to be a formal recognition of the divisions within the polity and of the rights of the subunits to make claims against both other groups and the nation as a whole. Moreover, such power-sharing arrangements were almost invariably accompanied by strong measures of effective autonomy for the different factions of the society, much like what might emerge in Iraq were some form of tripartite division of the territory and oil revenues to take hold. But the inescapable result of such arrangements is to assign each individual’s citizenship in the first instance to some subset of the population and to recognize, formally, that the capacity of the citizen to interact with the broader polity will be mediated through the corresponding institutional arrangements. An interesting example comes from Belgium where, in a series of constitutional reforms in 1970 and 1980, the country was divided into four languagebased regions, reflecting the country’s historic linguistic divisions.24 These reforms were intended to defuse long-standing communal tensions in Belgium, which had been exacerbated by the differential treatment afforded to the different linguistic groups by German occupation forces during World War II.25 The reforms directed that each municipality “shall belong to one of these” language-based alignments and that the voting in each region would be assigned 22 For the classic account of consociationalism and its defense as a mechanism for stabilizing deeply conflicted societies, see LIJPHART, supra note 1. 23 This is the Shaw line of cases, named after the first Supreme Court case to announce a distinct constitutional concern over the use of excessive racial considerations in drawing territorial districts. See Shaw v. Reno (Shaw I), 509 U.S. 630 (1993); Shaw v. Hunt (Shaw II), 517 U.S. 899 (1996); Hunt v. Cromartie (Cromartie I), 526 U.S. 541 (1999); Easley v. Cromartie (Cromartie II), 532 U.S. 234 (2001). 24 For an account of the complex institutional and political compromises reflected in Belgium’s elaborate consociational arrangement, see Wilfried Swenden, What—If Anything—Can the European Union Learn from Belgian Federalism and Vice Versa?, 15 REG’L & FED. STUD. 187 (2005). 25 See JUDT, supra note 3, at 710; Martin Conway, Justice in Postwar Belgium: Popular Passions and Political Realities, in THE POLITICS OF RETRIBUTION IN EUROPE: WORLD WAR II AND ITS AFTERMATH 133 (István Deák, Jan T. Gross & Tony Judt eds., Princeton Univ. Press 2000) (describing German preferential treatment and promotion of the Flemish and Dutch speaking populations of Belgium as opposed to the Francophone population). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 241 to those citizens who chose to affiliate with the dominant language group of the designated town or region.26 Unfortunately, to assign representation to one group for a designated region is to deny it to another group, and this prompted a major constitutional challenge, presented ultimately to the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) as Mathieu-Mohin and Clerfayt v. Belgium.27 For highly technical reasons, the practical effect of the language-group classification was that individuals who had declared themselves to belong to a languagegroup constituency different from the controlling bloc in a particular locality could be prevented from voting for local government officials. As a result, there were citizens who were unable to participate in elections for officials with power over such key matters as regional planning, public budgets, and zoning policies.28 The effect of this removal from electoral participation was most acute in the suburbs of Brussels, which were in the Flemish-designated north but heavily French in population. In such cases, a citizen who publicly declared herself affiliated with the French voting constituency—by holding national office or declaring herself a candidate for office, for example—would be prohibited from participating in local elections that were restricted to the Flemish voting bloc. Tip O’Neill’s famous aphorism that all politics is local notwithstanding, the practical consequence was that engagement in national politics as part of a French-language political party meant removal from participation in matters that dealt with day-to-day life. The fact that citizens of a municipality could not vote for local officials because of their language-group status demonstrates a more extreme version of the divisions presented in the demand of Quebec for separate voting rights with regard to its claim for secession. In the Belgian case, the division had already been codified in strict limitations on the ability to participate as an equal member of the polity. It was asserted that the franchise restrictions violated the guarantee in protocol no. 1, article 3, of the European Convention on Human Rights, providing for “the free expression of the opinion of the people in the choice of the legislature,”29 and, even more broadly, the right secured by the preamble to the convention of the maintenance of “an effective political democracy.”30 For the dissenting justices, those who would have struck down the language-based assignment of voting rights, the matter was easily handled as 26 See Mathieu-Mohin & Clerfayt v. Belgium, 10 Eur. H.R. Rep. 1, 8 (1988). 27 10 Eur. H.R. Rep. 1 (1988). 28 Id. at 2. 29 Protocol to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, Mar. 20, 1952, 213 U.N.T.S. 262, available at http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/ Treaties/Html/009.htm. 30 European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, Nov. 4, 1950, 213 U.N.T.S. 221, available at http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/005. htm. 242 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 a violation of individual rights of representation: “The practical consequence is that unless they vote for the Dutch-speaking candidates, the French-speaking voters in this district will not be represented on the Flemish Council.”31 A rather accessible rights claim presented itself, one made all the more compelling by the fact that—based on a significant divide in Belgian society—some members of a community were permitted unfettered voting rights on local matters while others could vote only by compromising their ability to affect the broader national parliament. More interesting for the purposes of this article, however, is the reasoning of the majority of the Court, which, in order to rule for Belgium, had to accept that country’s ability to define formally the voting rights of its citizens in a way that could be circumscribed by an individual’s language affinity. In this regard, the Belgian case resembles the Canadian dispute over Quebec’s claimed right of autonomy. In each case, a democratic principle could yield either a centralizing perspective, organized around a universalist rights claim, or it could yield a contextualized account of institutional structures that sought to limit the power of centralized decision making. As expressed by the majority of the ECtHR, “In any consideration of the electoral system in issue, its general context must not be forgotten.”32 The key holding of the ECtHR was to endorse as a legitimate democratic objective an institutional structure that tries to find a mediating equilibrium between popular sovereignty and the risk that a narrow majority could claim too much power. The Court’s analysis of the “general context” recognized that the unique Belgian voting rules were aimed at preventing the centralization of power and the ability of an emergent majority to expand its decision-making dominion: The 1980 Special Act, however, fits into a general institutional system of the Belgian State, based on the territoriality principle. . . . The aim is to defuse the language disputes in the country by establishing more stable and decentralised organisational structures.33 Certain features stand out in the ECtHR opinion that provide important signposts for judicial oversight. First, the Court is not flummoxed by the presentation of a perfectly plausible claim of an individual right of participation. Certainly, there is a compelling argument by Lucienne Mathieu-Mohin and Georges Clerfayt, in their individual capacities, that their inability to participate in local elections based on their language-group affiliation is troubling. But this is offset by a second consideration that the entire consociational structure “emerges 31 10 Eur. H.R. Rep. at 13 (Cremona, Bindschedler-Robert, Bernhardt, Spielmann & Valticos, JJ., dissenting). 32 Id. at para. 57. 33 Id. Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 243 from the debates in the democratic national Parliament”34 in which MathieuMohin and Clerfayt—as well as all other Belgian citizens—were able to participate on a free and equal basis. Third, the Court looks to “the massive majorities achieved in favour”35 of the proposed political accommodation as evidence that there is no perceived sense of oppression resulting from the operation of the unique voting arrangements. Put another way, the Court discounted two individuals’ specific claims of not being able to vote in municipal elections when set against the broad support the voting rules had across all sectors of the population. Finally, the fact that the voting rules were part of a recent, public negotiation gave them enhanced credibility. The voting rules are not the dead hand of the past entrenched against change but, rather, the product of recent political compromise directed at the unique frailties of Belgium’s historic divisions. The context-specific considerations would be blunted under the rights claim accepted by the dissent. Rights claims tend to invoke a higher authority in the form of national or international law, together with a strong dose of inherent and inviolable entitlements sounding in the traditions of natural law. While a rights claim is typically associated with the protection of individuals against the collective, the source of the law sustaining that claim may have two paradoxical and, in part, countervailing effects. First, the tendency toward higher authority is likely to empower broader constituencies at the expense of subgroups, defined either across ethnic or geographic divides. Second, precisely because context-sensitive local accommodations tend to be idiosyncratic, the homogenizing effect of a rights template threatens the political accommodations epitomized by Belgium. 1.1.3. Revisiting one person, one vote The Canadian and Belgian examples provide the conceptual counterpoint to the centralizing impulses that we turn to in the next section, with cases from the United States and South Africa. Whereas these latter cases, which look, first and foremost, to a rights claim, turn generally to high-level fundamental declarations as a mechanism for resolving a core question of what is the right level of democratic decision making, the former look to institutional structures that represent a guarantee of divided authority. As will become apparent, the judicial confrontation with difficult core questions of democratic legitimacy rarely finds a ready-made set of answers. Virtually all of the opinions under consideration could find countervailing arguments and sources of authority that could have compelled an alternative result. But the Canadian and Belgian opinions are particularly instructive because neither could find a controlling principle in either national law or higher levels of democratic theory to resolve the ultimate issue of who is the polity that should decide. 34 Id. 35 Id. 244 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 In contrast with the nuanced Canadian and Belgian decisions, U.S. case law has been dominated by a rights approach in which the rights issue is seen as a dichotomous variable, one that is either in play in full or not at all. The initial move belonged to Justice William Brennan, who famously chose to evade the political-question doctrine in Baker v. Carr by attacking the structural defects in American democracy through the template of equal protection law.36 According to Brennan, “judicial standards under the Equal Protection Clause are well developed and familiar,” and, by extension, required no particular refining for application in the political arena.37 The equal protection approach made some sense given the large disparities in voting power in the early apportionment cases.38 Less successful were subsequent applications in which, for example, minute differences in voting power among voters in different districts were used to try to cabin the effects of partisan gerrymandering. But even at the time of the initial reapportionment revolution, the mechanical application of the rights-infused, one-person–one-vote standard was troubling. A key case in point is Lucas v. The Forty-Fourth General Assembly of the State of Colorado,39 a case with remarkable parallels to Mathieu-Mohin and Clerfayt v. Belgium. At issue in Lucas was a very recent amendment to the Colorado constitution (1962, just two years before the Court’s decision) that passed with strong support across the state and altered the apportionment of the state legislature. The new plan divided the state into equipopulous districts for the lower house and provided for county-based representation for the upper chamber. The plan added additional senate districts in urbanized Denver but preserved representation for counties whose population could not keep up with urban growth. The express purpose was to ensure consideration of rural concerns at a time when this ranching and mining state for most of its history was undergoing significant urbanization. The Court confronted a voting arrangement that bore none of the indicia of oppression or historic indifference to the claims of distinct sectional interests. As the Court noted, the plan received majority support in every county in the state, including the urban counties,40 and, given its recent adoption, “the plan at issue did not result from prolonged legislative inaction.”41 For the U.S. 36 Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962). 37 Id. at 226. For critical accounts of this initial move, see Michael W. McConnell, The Redistricting Cases: Original Mistakes and Current Consequences, 24 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 103 (2000); Guy-Uriel E. Charles, Constitutional Pluralism and Democratic Pluralism: Reflections on the Interpretive Approach of Baker v. Carr, 80 N.C. L. REV. 1103 (2002). 38 See SAMUEL ISSACHAROFF, PAMELA S. KARLAN & RICHARD H. PILDES, THE LAW OF DEMOCRACY: LEGAL REGULAPOLITICAL PROCESS 175 (3d ed., Foundation 2007) (describing disparities in voting power of 23 to 1 in Baker and much higher in some of the accompanying cases of the period). TION OF THE 39 377 U.S. 713 (1964). 40 See id. at 758 (Stewart, J., dissenting). 41 Id. at 730. Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 245 Supreme Court, as for the dissenters on the ECtHR, political accommodations that evidenced no sectional animus or oppression simply did not matter. The categorical template was unyielding: A citizen’s constitutional rights can hardly be infringed simply because a majority of the people choose that it be. We hold that the fact that a challenged legislative apportionment plan was approved by the electorate is without federal constitutional significance, if the scheme adopted fails to satisfy the basic requirements of the Equal Protection Clause. . . .42 None of the signposts considered in Mathieu-Mohin were deemed of constitutional significance. Once measured against the one-person–one-vote yardstick, it did not matter that the apportionment measure was adopted recently, that it was subject to revision through the initiative process, that the lower chamber provided for perfect equipopulation distributions, and that there was no sign of malice toward or subordination of any discrete section of the population. Nor has the Court been receptive to the argument that lower-level accommodations could pass constitutional muster so long as there was accountability in a higher-level, democratically accountable legislature—again another argument accepted by the ECtHR in Mathieu-Mohin. In Kramer v. Union Free School District No. 15,43 for example, the Court struck down a New York State provision that restricted the franchise in community school-district elections to local taxpayers and parents of enrolled students. Coming at the height of the Court’s commitment to the expansion of the franchise, any restriction on the ballot triggered the withering strictures of strict scrutiny. The New York law was not the product of a local majority seeking to shut out a disfavored minority or some vestige of an antiquated voting rule. Rather, it was a recently adopted state law that sought to give greater control over school direction to the constituents most directly affected—the taxpayers who funded the schools and the parents who were the end users of their services. Instead, the question presented by Chief Justice Earl Warren was only whether an individual claim for participation could be found, and, if so, whether the presumptively fatal review under strict scrutiny could be withstood: [T]he deference usually given to the judgment of legislators does not extend to decisions concerning which resident citizens may participate in the election of legislators and other public officials. Those decisions must be carefully scrutinized by the Court to determine whether each resident citizen has, as far as is possible, an equal voice in the selections. Accordingly, when we are reviewing statutes which deny some residents the right to vote, the general presumption of constitutionality afforded state statutes 42 Id. at 736–737. 43 395 U.S. 621 (1969). 246 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 and the traditional approval given state classifications if the Court can conceive of a “rational basis” for the distinctions made are not applicable.44 There was little attention given to Justice Potter Stewart’s dissenting claim that the excluded potential voters had ample access to the statewide electoral processes that were ultimately responsible for the school-board-election system. In Justice Stewart’s words, “[t]here is simply no claim whatever here that the state government is not ‘structured so as to represent fairly all the people,’ including the appellant.”45 The dissent’s argument was taken up, some years later, by Justice Lewis Powell in a case involving limited franchise rights for the key water district of Arizona.46 The majority in Ball v. James, in keeping with the categorical approach taken in Kramer, found that “special purpose” districts were entirely apart from the obligation to enfranchise the citizenry and that, accordingly, the on/off switch of voting rights would remain disengaged.47 Justice Powell’s concurrence accepted the limitation on claimed voting rights but did so for reasons of institutional compromise and the ultimate accountability of the entire arrangement to the voters of the state: Our cases have recognized the necessity of permitting experimentation with political communities. . . . As this case illustrates, it may be difficult to decide when experimentation and political compromise have resulted in an impermissible delegation of those governmental powers that generally affect all of the people to a body with a selective electorate. But state legislatures, responsive to the interests of all the people, normally are better qualified to make this judgment than federal courts. . . . 48 In the years since Baker v. Carr and its accompanying cases, the doctrine of one-person, one-vote has hardened and subverted the prospects for sensible political compromises. To take but one example, the Court struck down a complicated political arrangement in New York that allowed for the creation of a specialized body to deal with taxing and zoning issues. The fatal defect in Board of Estimate v. Morris,49 according to the Court, was that the board included the borough presidents of the five New York boroughs, each of whom was elected 44 Id. at 627–628. 45 Id. at 639 (Stewart, J., dissenting). 46 Ball v. James, 451 U.S. 355 (1981). 47 Ball concerned a challenge to the Salt River Project Agricultural Improvement and Power Districtin Arizona, which controlled the water distribution to about half the population of the state, including the growing cities of the state, such as Phoenix. 48 Id. at 373. For a more mechanical application of formal voting rights law to strike down experimentation with parental engagement in local school administration, see Fumarolo v. Chicago Board of Education, 566 N.E.2d 1283 (Ill. 1990). 49 489 U.S. 688 (1989). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 247 by a different number of citizens. It did not matter that the board corresponded to the compromise that created the modern City of New York in 1898 and that it was contemporaneous with the founding concern of disproportionate political power for Brooklyn and Manhattan.50 Nor did it matter that the Board of Estimate may have been the protection needed to hold Staten Island within the broader municipal arrangement. Numerical disparities in per-individual voting strength for any elected body were sufficient to offend the Constitution. 1.2. Empowering the broader constituency At the other end of the spectrum from the willingness to tolerate institutional arrangements born of political compromise is the far more common impulse of courts to assume the propriety of centralized decision making, as is evident in American one-person–one-vote case law. This may seem a paradoxical claim in light of the greater attention to federalism concerns in the U.S., South Africa, and, given the commitment to subsidiarity, in European Community law. Yet, properly conceptualized, this is the effect of the emergence of rights jurisprudence in the post–World War II era. Rights claims enshrine certain entitlements for the citizenry vis-à-vis the body politic and move the claims up to a higher level of law generation, either at the national constitutional level or beyond in multinational organizations or in international law commitments to human rights. When enforced by courts, such rights claims impose some level of uniformity on all political subdivisions over which the court has authority. As a result, local accommodations are rendered suspect by the movement toward universalized responses to claims for individual rights of participation. The sweep of rights claims in democratic societies around the world has a corresponding effect on how courts conceptualize core questions of political organization. 1.2.1. Local majorities Let us begin with a rather famous case from the United States. In 1992, Colorado voters approved Amendment 2, a voter-initiated amendment to the Colorado constitution requiring that all matters regarding the legal protections of homosexuals be enacted at the statewide level. The effect was to disempower local constituencies that might want to pass antidiscrimination ordinances or give certain sexual-orientation minorities some measure of special legal solicitude. If we assume, not unreasonably, that the rights afforded homosexuals remain a fractious issue in American politics, then the question arises at what level of government decision-making should the authority to act lie? As litigated in the Colorado courts,51 the state asserted that Amendment 2 “serves to deter factionalism through ensuring that decisions regarding special 50 See Richard Briffault, Voting Rights, Home Rule, and Metropolitan Governance: The Secession of Staten Island as a Case Study in the Dilemmas of Local Self-Determination, 92 COLUM. L. REV. 775 (1992). 51 The discussion is taken from Evans v. Romer, 882 P.2d 1335 (Colo. 1994), aff’d, 517 U.S. 620 (1996). 248 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 protections for homosexuals and bisexuals are made at the highest level of government” and that, as a result, “the deeply divisive issue of homosexuality’s place in our society does not serve to fragment Colorado’s body politic.”52 According to the state, Amendment 2 furthers this end by eliminating “city-bycity and county-by-county battles over this issue.”53 The Colorado Supreme Court rejected the claimed state interest and found, instead, that Amendment 2 denied a “fundamental right to participate equally in the political process” by depriving one discrete group of the ability to find legislative support at the local level: “Amendment 2 alters the political process so that a targeted class is prohibited from obtaining legislative, executive, and judicial protection or redress from discrimination absent the consent of a majority of the electorate through the adoption of a constitutional amendment.”54 The Colorado Supreme Court found a controversial right of democratic appeal to a local, cognizable constituency to be a sufficiently grounded right that its denial to one group but not another would violate equal protection.55 While not as explosive as questions of a right to secede, this claimed right of electoral appeal prompted a blistering retort by Justice Antonin Scalia, dissenting in the Supreme Court’s review of the Colorado court in Romer v. Evans.56 For Justice Scalia, prohibiting local constituencies from regulating the morals of their citizens is not the exception but the norm in a constitutional democracy: [T]here is a much closer analogy, one that involves precisely the effort by the majority of citizens to preserve its view of sexual morality statewide, against the efforts of a geographically concentrated and politically powerful minority to undermine it. The Constitutions of the States of Arizona, Idaho, New Mexico, Oklahoma, and Utah to this day contain provisions stating that polygamy is “forever prohibited.”57 Despite Justice Scalia’s argument that no right of local autonomy could coexist with the basic precepts of constitutional law, his argument failed to carry the Court. Or so it would appear: While the majority struck down Amendment 2, it did so on the grounds that the Colorado law’s “sheer breadth is so discontinuous with the reasons offered for it that the amendment seems 52 Id. at 1348. 53 Id. 54 Id. at 1338–1339. 55 There is no particular political valence to debates over local versus higher-level control over decisions such as the rights of homosexuals. The same day I first presented this paper in Jerusalem there was a protest by local authorities claiming an autonomy right to ban a gay pride demonstration. Their claim was that the more conservative Jerusalem local government should have the ability to determine the level of support for gay rights in a manner distinct from the national consensus. 56 517 U.S. 620 (1996). 57 Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. at 648 (Scalia, J., dissenting). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 249 inexplicable by anything but animus toward the class it affects.”58 According to Justice Anthony Kennedy, the underlying animus toward homosexuals as a class violated the equal protection clause of the Constitution, though perhaps only for the perceived irrationality of the regulation. While Justice Kennedy struck down the law, his decision to root the prohibition in the Fourteenth Amendment actually conforms to and extends Justice Scalia’s core argument. Where Justice Scalia would have denied the claimed right of a local majority to defy the will of a statewide majority, Justice Kennedy repudiated the right of a statewide majority to exercise its will in the face of a national consensus to the contrary. In effect, this use of federal constitutional law is just the sort of deprivation of autonomy for a statewide majority that the Colorado Supreme Court ruled could not be imposed on a local majority. In other words, Justice Scalia may have carried the day only too well.59 A variant of the Colorado debate emerges from the question whether a political majority—as opposed to a geographically concentrated majority—should be entitled to the realization of its political preferences. The classic presentation of the issue in American case law came in Gordon v. Lance,60 a 1971 case from West Virginia dealing with a state requirement that all bond indebtedness receive 60 percent support, as opposed to the normal majority, to go into effect. The Court was willing to entertain a claim that, at some level of supermajority support, the effect would be to empower a holdout minority sufficiently as to threaten democratic governance. However, according to the Court, that possibility did not translate into a guarantee of majority preference as such: “any departure from strict majority rule gives disproportionate power to the minority. But there is nothing in the language of the Constitution, our history, or our cases that requires that a majority always prevail on every issue.”61 In the context of a bond issue, there is a particular logic to supermajority rules. Since public indebtedness shifts obligations cross-temporally, supermajoritarian restraints may be seen as a way of obligating temporary majorities to submerge their preferences into a broader constituency that includes (through the operation of the voting rule) a vicarious proxy for the future generations 58 517 U.S. at 631. 59 Ironically, one American court has seized on the capacity of local majorities to fashion new rules as grounds for affirming a local antihomosexual ordinance. At issue in Cincinnati was a local prohibition that deprived homosexuals of recourse to local antidiscrimination laws to claim affirmative action or any of the more expansive remedies associated with current equal protection law. The court ultimately upheld the challenged ordinance on the grounds that, since the prohibition did not operate at the statewide level, it could be overridden at the statewide level and hence did not foreclose claims for redress within the political process. Equality Found. of Greater Cincinnati, Inc. v. City of Cincinnati, 128 F.3d 289 (6th Cir. 1997). 60 403 U.S. 1 (1971). 61 Id. at 6. 250 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 that will bear a substantial part of the obligation. The outcome in Gordon v. Lance thus may be seen as conceptually linked to the decisions of both Justices Scalia and Kennedy in Romer. In each case, the ability to constitute a majority of a subset of the greater polity (defined either geographically or temporally) is insufficient to sustain an autonomy right absent agreement by the broader constituency. More problematic for democratic theory are cases in which a supermajority is required for any action at all. At some level, this is simply a recasting of the fundamental tension in democratic constitutionalism. All constitutions constrain temporary majorities, acting through the normal workings of the political process, from achieving their desired objectives. But as indicated in Justice Scalia’s invocation of anti-Mormon provisions in the constitutions of several Western states, such prohibitions on majority conduct may be as troubling as they are commonplace. An interesting example emerged recently in Utah when conservationists attempted to use initiative procedures to limit hunting of the restored cougar population in the state. The legislature responded preemptively by amending the state constitution (by an appropriate two-thirds majority of each chamber) to stipulate that any initiative regulating the “taking” of wildlife would require a two-thirds majority, as opposed to the normal simple majority. Proponents challenged this on the grounds that the selective imposition of a heightened threshold inhibited normal political activity, this time in violation of the First Amendment.62 The Tenth Circuit, in a thoughtful opinion by Judge Michael McConnell, could not find a mediating principle that would allow such a challenge without sweeping aside all efforts to raise the threshold of political decision making to high levels of popular approbation, even if in direct violation of the will of a direct majority of the affected population: Constitutions and rules of procedure routinely make legislation, and thus advocacy, on certain subjects more difficult by requiring a supermajority vote to enact bills on certain subjects. Those who propose, for example, to impeach an official, override a veto, expel a member of the legislature, or ratify a treaty might have to convince two-thirds of the members of one or both houses to vote accordingly. State constitutions attach supermajority requirements to a bewildering array of specific categories of legislation, including appropriations bills, tax levies, bonding bills, debts, land use regulations, the salaries and discipline of state officials, district formation and redistricting, and judicial administration.63 Accordingly, the Court concluded that, “if it violates the First Amendment to remove certain issues from the vicissitudes of ordinary democratic politics, 62 Initiative & Referendum Inst. v. Walker, 450 F.3d 1082 (10th Cir. 2006), cert. denied, 127 S.Ct. 1254 (2007). 63 450 F.3d at 1100–1101. Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 251 constitutions themselves are unconstitutional.”64 That became the crux of the problem: it is difficult to root any commitment to direct majoritarianism in any democracy operating under constitutional constraints. Inescapably, “Constitutions are about the restriction of government power.”65 Even a majority at the level of the entire polity cannot overcome that restraint. 1.2.2. Represented constituencies A variant on the theme of empowering the aggregate at the expense of the discrete may be found in the questions concerned with the protection of minority representation. All election systems run a risk of excess of majoritarianism if the capture of state institutions by an electoral majority is not tempered, most notably by constitutional constraints. Many countries confront minority-access issues in connection with matters such as thresholds for success in representation,66 particularly in nonproportional electoral systems relying on territorial units as the basis for representation.67 In most instances, the debates center on the requirements for attaining office for candidates preferred by minority constituencies. But merely ensuring the election of minority-preferred candidates does not end the tension between minority preferences and the global claims of the political process. Once in office, representatives of minority constituencies may be lured away from their role as promoters of sectional interests by claims for the need to represent the entirety of the polity. This is, of course, the claim that representatives must serve, above all, the “general good, resulting from the general reason of the whole,” as famously expressed by Edmund Burke in his “Speech to the Electors of Bristol.”68 Descending a bit from Burke’s broad invocation of the general good, the issue comes up, most often, in the more prosaic form of a governing coalition capturing a member of the opposition by offering avenues of personal advancement. At times, as only recently in Canada,69 the appeal to an individual legislator to forsake his party platform may serve to salvage a 64 Id. at 1100. 65 ANDRÁS SAJÓ, LIMITING GOVERNMENT 49 (Central European Univ. Press 1999). 66 See, e.g., Kieran Williams, Judicial Review of Electoral Thresholds in Germany, Russia, and the Czech Republic, 4 ELECTION L.J. 191, 192–195 (2005) (discussing the German Constitutional Court’s longstanding approval of electoral thresholds). 67 See, e.g., the Shaw line of cases, supra note 23. 68 EDMUND BURKE, THE WORKS OF THE RIGHT HONORABLE EDMUND BURKE 447 (George Bell & Sons 1902) (1801). The opposite claim is that representatives must act “in the interest of the represented, in a manner responsive to them.” HANNAH F. PITKIN, THE CONCEPT OF REPRESENTATION 209 (Univ. of Cal. Press 1967). 69 In 2005, the faltering Liberal government of Prime Minister Paul Joseph Martin received a brief reprieve from falling as the result of the defection of an opposition member from the even more weakened Conservative Party. See Conservative Stronach Joins Liberals, CBC NEWS, May 18, 2005, available at http://www.cbc.ca/canada/story/2005/05/17/stronach-liberals050517.html. My thanks to Colin Feasby for alerting me to the Canadian example. 252 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 governing coalition on the verge of collapse. More often, however, such entreaties come from a stronger majority seeking to cement its hold on power. The risk of majority capture of rogue representatives is expressly addressed in several countries, particularly in those that are most concerned with protecting minority representation against an overweening majoritarianism. Countries such as India, Namibia, and South Africa formalized such antidefection concerns through legal prohibitions on what is known as “floor walking.”70 In South Africa, the initial constitution required a member of parliament to resign if he or she attempted to switch parties. The provision was an explicit subject of negotiations in the transition from apartheid, reflecting fears that the likely parliamentary majority of the African National Congress could be used to woo minority legislators and overconcentrate political power.71 Once in office and once its political power was consolidated, however, the ANC used its legislative supermajority to repeal the antidefection provision. Under the new law, defection was permitted so long as the defecting group constituted at least 10 percent of its party’s legislative delegation. This did little to placate critics, since this would pose a very large hurdle to defections from the ANC but would leave defection an individual choice for any party member whose party had fewer than ten members of Parliament. The constitutional amendment prompted a second constitutional challenge, this time a claim that the amendment would violate the principles of party integrity and separation of powers inherent in the entire constitutional structure.72 The Court rejected the challenge, both on the procedural ground that the mechanisms of constitutional amendment had been adhered to but, more significantly, on a deeper theory that representation after the election is not a right that attaches to a subset of voters: The rights entrenched under section 19 [of the Constitution] are directed to elections, to voting and to participation in political activities. Between elections, however, voters have no control over the conduct of their representatives. They cannot dictate to them how they must vote in Parliament, 70 New Zealand similarly prohibited party switching by members of Parliament in the Electoral (Integrity) Amendment Act, 2001, but the prohibition was statutory and expired by design in 2005. See Mathew S. R. Palmer, Using Constitutional Realism to Identify the Complete Constitution: Lessons From an Unwritten Constitution, 54 AM. J. COMP. L. 587, 610 n.64 (2006). 71 The role of this constitutional provision is discussed in the landmark case in which the South African Constitutional Court reviewed the entire constitutional compact for conformity to the negotiated principles that ended apartheid. See In re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (4) SALR 744 (CC).at para 181 n.136 and accompanying text (considering whether the antidefection principle was unconstitutional). My account of the initial constitutional issues in South Africa may be found at Constitutionalizing Democracy in Fractured Societies, 82 TEX. L. REV. 1861 (2004). 72 United Democratic Movement v. The President of the Republic of South Africa 2003 (1) SA 495 (CC). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 253 nor do they have any legal right to insist that they conduct themselves or refrain from conducting themselves in a particular manner.73 The American and South African examples show the ease of moving the locus of political power up to higher levels of the polity, particularly in cases submitted for judicial review.74 The reasons for the ease of moving up the scale of political constituencies, though beyond the scope of this article, might be traced to the prevalence of rights claims in providing as an increasing staple in the diets of the world’s judiciary.75 Seemingly of necessity, rights claims move the source of the entitlement to higher levels of political command, either at the constitutional level, domestically, or at the transnational level, through appeals to European Community law, for example, or to international law directly.76 For international judiciaries, accustomed as they have become to rights claims that move the locus of legal authority further and further up the ladder of collectivization, the move to expanding definitions of the polity appears to come with little resistance. 2. The wisdom and passion of the multitudes The Rerum novarum encyclical provides one of the few overarching theories for the organization of political life through a specific unit of political organization. The papal approach was to establish the default at the level of the sanctity of the individual, of individual labor, and of the family, and to structure a strong presumption against higher levels of political authority that could interfere in those primary relations. It is hard, however, to recognize the modern organization of commercial and productive life in the encyclical’s encomium for the primacy of individualized and atomized labor. Even under European Community law, where the concept of subsidiarity is formally embraced, the devolution of power to the most immediate competent source of authority better explains the structure of economic regulation than it does political decision making. For 73 Id. at 49. 74 This robust constitutionalization is addressed critically in Richard H. Pildes, Foreword: The Constitutionalization of Democratic Politics, 118 HARV. L. REV. 28 (2004). 75 The attempt to protect the domain of politics is central to Jeremy Waldron’s critique of judicial review. For example, he argues that legislation best preserves the unique virtue of political contestation, given that “the community for which the law is made is essentially plural, and in its essence incapable of representation by a single voice.” JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 60 (Oxford Univ. Press 1999). Even with regard to the most contested rights issues, Waldron strongly argues for what he terms the dignity of legislation. For a critical overview of the role of rights claims in dampening the ardor of the masses on an international scale, see RAN HIRSCHL, TOWARDS JURISTOCRACY (Harvard Univ. Press 2005). 76 For an informed discussion of the informal pathways among peripatetic judges of Supreme and Constitutional courts and how these have contributed to the formation of an international “common law” of rights jurisprudence, see ANNE-MARIE SLAUGHTER, A NEW WORLD ORDER (Princeton Univ. Press 2004). 254 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 purposes of answering questions about the exercise of political authority, some greater principle of organization needs to come into play. As revealed by the cases discussed thus far, however, such greater principles are difficult to discern within the law as well. In American cases addressing the structure of the political process, such difficulties are exposed when one side or other, usually the dissent, accuses the other of resorting to questions of political theory as opposed to law in reaching a desired outcome.77 Daniel Ortiz colorfully refers to this as the “Got Theory?” challenge to disputed claims.78 Even were courts to admit openly their willingness to be guided by political theory, however, the result would be no more certain. Political theory, it turns out, follows the same basic divide as the judicial decisions. Under long-standing and well-considered principles, it is possible to understand collectivization of decision making at broader levels of the polity as an invitation to wisdom or oppression, as empowering reason or passion, as a source of stability or factional strife. 2.1. Centralization and state authority There is no question that the broad sweep of history has expanded the size of the units of governance. Simply as a matter of military necessity, as recognized by strategic thinkers from Thucydides to Machiavelli and beyond, the need to organize for collective self-defense required centralized state authority and the ability to tax for the general welfare. That, in turn, required increasing not only the size of the governing unit but an increased democratic commitment to vest consultative powers in the citizenry and its representatives. For political theorists, the challenge of democratic governance became one of harnessing the collective wisdom of the populace. Aristotle in The Politics famously argued that the power of democracy was not limited to the expansion of the claims that may be made on the citizens; that power included, as well, the wisdom that can be harnessed from an expanded polity. The principle that the multitude ought to be supreme rather than the few best is one that is maintained, and, though not free from difficulty, yet seems to contain an element of truth. For the many, of whom each individual is but an ordinary person, when they meet together may very likely be better than the few good, if regarded not individually but collectively, just as a feast to See, e.g., Holder v. Hall, 512 U.S. 874, 893 (1994) (Thomas, J., concurring) (“[O]nly a resort to political theory … can enable a court to determine which electoral systems provide the ‘fairest’ levels of representation…”); Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 620 (1964) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (denouncing the majority for ruling “on the basis of political judgments which they are incompetent to make”); Lucas v. Forty-Fourth Gen. Assembly of State of Colo., 377 U.S. 713, 747-48 (1964) (Stewart, J., dissenting) (criticizing the majority for measuring the “demands of the Constitution … not by what it says, but by their own notions of wise political theory”); Colegrove v. Green, 328 U.S. 549, 552 (1946) (Frankfurter, J., plurality opinion) (dismissing challenge to Illinois’s districting scheme because the issue was of a “peculiarly political nature and therefore not meet for judicial determination”). 77 78 Daniel R. Ortiz, Got Theory?, 153 U. PA. L. REV. 459 (2004). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 255 which many contribute is better than a dinner provided out of a single purse. For each individual among the many has a share of virtue and prudence, and when they meet together, they become in a manner one man, who has many feet, and hands, and senses; that is a figure of their mind and disposition.79 This is what Jeremy Waldron terms the “doctrine of the wisdom of the multitude.”80 More colloquially, such aggregated wisdom may be revealed in the capacity of the studio audience on Who Wants to Be a Millionaire to be correct an impressive 91 percent of the time in its collective judgment.81 As pithily expressed by The New Yorker writer James Surowiecki, it is “as if we’ve been programmed to be collectively smart.”82 More formally, the Condorcet jury theorem establishes that so long as individuals have a better than even chance of being right, a group majority is more likely to choose the better of two alternatives.83 As a technical matter, this is simply the application of the law of large numbers whereby multiple iterations are likely to drive out random deviations. At a deeper level, however, the superiority of collective decision making forms the basis for operationalizing theories, most notably Rousseau’s, of the common good: “[I]f it is not impossible for a [private] will to agree on some point with the general will, it is at least impossible for the agreement to be lasting and constant; for the [private] will tends, by its very nature, to partiality, while the general will tends to equality.”84 The superiority of collective decision making translates smoothly into a preference for higher-level decision making.85 Most famously, James Madison’s 79 ARISTOTLE, THE POLITICS 74–75 (Benjamin Jowett & Thomas Twining trans., Viking Press 1957) (350 B.C.E). 80 Jeremy Waldron, The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle’s Politics, 23 POL. THEORY 563 (1995). 81 BRYAN CAPLAN, THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER 8 (Princeton Univ. Press 2007). 82 JAMES SUROWIECKI, THE WISDOM OF CROWDS 11 (Random House 2004). 83 MARIE-JEAN-ANTOINE-NICOLAS DE CARITAT, MARQUIS DE CONDORCET, ESSAI SUR L’APPLICATION DE L’ANALYSE À [ESSAY ON THE APPLICATION OF ANALYSIS TO THE PROBABILITY OF DECISIONS RENDERED BY A PLURALITY OF VOICES] (photo. reprint 1972) (1785). LA PROBABILITÉ DES DÉCISIONS RENDUES À LA PLURALITÉ DES VOIX 84 JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT OR PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL RIGHT 15 (G.D.H. Cole trans., Kessinger 2004) (1762). For an extensive discussion connecting the Condorcet jury theorem to Rousseau’s general will, see Bernard Grofman & Scott L. Feld, Rousseau’s General Will: A Condorcetian Perspective, 82 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 567 (1988). 85 It also was applied by Condorcet himself strongly to advocate unicameralism since, in his view, “increasing the number of legislative bodies could never increase the probability of obtaining true decisions.” MARQUIS DE CONDORCET, Letters from a Freeman of New Haven to a Citizen of Virginia on the Futility of Dividing the Legislative Power Among Several Bodies: Letter Four, in CONDORCET: FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND POLITICAL THEORY 292, 329 (Iain McLean & Fiona Hewitt eds., Fiona Hewitt trans., 1994), quoted in Nicholas Quinn Rosencrantz, Condorcet and the Constitution: A Response to The Law of Other States, 59 STAN. L. REV. 1281, 1293 (2007). Even more vituperatively, Condorcet characterized bicameral legislatures as a “fear of innovation, one of the most fatal scourges of the human race.” Quoted at id. 256 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 advocacy of the “extended republic” was based on the role of broad political constituencies as capable of warding off the evils of sectionalism and factionalism.86 This argument is then reproduced as a core feature of the contemporary defense of legislative primacy over judicial review. Thus, Waldron argues that legislation draws both its legitimacy and its strength from the fact that “the community for which the law is made is essentially plural, and in its essence incapable of representation by a single voice.”87 The legislative process claims its primacy from its ability “to gather together large numbers of people who are not necessarily on casual ‘speaking terms’ with one another, and who participate in legislative deliberations not as individual conversationalists but as representatives. . . .”89 Nonetheless, this account does not address itself to the mechanism by which higher-level decision making is thought to draw from collective bodies a measure of wisdom. For example, Avishai Margalit holds out as the key to Spinoza’s aspiration to turn the masses away from the hold of emotion and toward the realm of rationality the prospect of engagement in liberal democracy.89 Unresolved, however, is whether democracy as such is robust enough to prevent passion from overwhelming mass behavior, even in a society vested with a rights culture. Many observers of democratic politics worry that voting alone is insufficient to move the citizenry beyond a narrow attachment to base instincts or a simple desire for immediate gratification or out of a response to fear.90 As captivatingly expressed by the Indian Supreme Court, in upholding strict governmental controls on inflammatory electoral speech, voting provides the perfect medium by which to “whip up low hard instincts and animosities or irrational fears between groups to secure electoral victories.”91 The transformative role of broad-based political engagement is most evident in accounts of democracy that focus on the process of deliberation among the citizenry, generally in terms of either procedural norms or the capacity of collective exchange as raising individuals above their narrow station.92 The 86 THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, at 63–65 (James Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., Wesleyan Univ. Press 1961). 87 WALDRON, DISAGREEMENT, supra note 75. 88 Id. at 70. 89 See Avishai Margalit, The Lessons of Spinoza, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Apr. 12, 2007, at 71–72, available at http://www.nybooks.com/articles/20072. For example, Jeremy Waldron contrasts the transformative role played by “structured politics” in the legislative setting for Hannah Arendt with the isolation of the voting booth (“this booth has room for only one”), in which little more than narrow self-interest is likely to be manifest. Jeremy Waldron, Arendt’s Constitutional Politics, in THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO HANNAH ARENDT 201 (Dana Villa ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 2001). 90 91 92 Bukhari v. Mehra, (1975) S.C.R. 453. See generally David M. Estlund, Who’s Afraid of Deliberative Democracy?, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1437, 1440–1441 (1993). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 257 transformative capacity of exchange receives particular play in appeals to deliberative polling or even deliberation days, although these tend to focus on small group exchanges informing the broader polity.93 However, on most accounts, there is little precision to just how the transformative effect of democratic participation is to be realized. Even champions of deliberative theories of democracy may rely on more elusive concepts of “idealized” deliberation, rather than commit themselves, necessarily, to the outcome of actual exchanges.94 Despite the unresolved mechanism for the transformation of self-regarding impulses in the body politic, the collectivizing accounts still share a faith in the ability of broader institutions both to seek more public-regarding policies and to raise the quality of decision making. One mechanism is to leave unresolved whether large-scale engagement truly does transform the individual members of the polity and to vest collective wisdom in the repeated interactions of the legislative process. The individuals may remain parochial, on this view, but the institutional response mediates the failings of individuals. Alternatively, one can move to an even higher plane of collective wisdom by removing an increasing swath of decision making not only from individuals but from political bodies directly accountable to the citizenry. This recourse comes about as the end effect of expanding the domain of constitutional rights and, beyond that, of international law. If one of the hallmarks of rights jurisprudence is the placement of the best aspirational features of a society at a plane removed from quotidian politics, there is a convergence—even if not perfect—between the centralizing impulses of this strand of political theory and a constitutionalized vision of politics. 2.2. Capture and extremism It would be shocking if the claimed virtues of collectivized decision making, particularly in furtherance of a general will, survived the onslaughts of the twentieth century unalloyed. And, of course, they have not. A major challenge to collective decision making comes from the argument that group preferences are unstable and subject to agenda manipulation. As initially formulated by Kenneth Arrow, group preferences are subject to cycling, whereby—depending on the manner in which the question is presented—alternative outcomes are possible.95 Thereafter, Arrow’s theorem then became the focal point for contemporary public-choice analysis according to which the ability to obtain gains from the indecision of the majority 93 See James S. Fishkin & Robert C. Luskin, Bringing Deliberation to the Democratic Dialogue, in THE POLL WITH A HUMAN FACE 3 (Maxwell McCombs & Amy Reynolds eds., Lawrence Erlbaum 1999); BRUCE ACKERMAN & JAMES S. FISHKIN, DELIBERATION DAY (Yale Univ. Press 2004); JAMES S. FISHKIN, THE VOICE OF THE PEOPLE (Yale Univ. Press 1997). 94 See, e.g., Joshua Cohen, Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy, in DEMOCRACY 87 (David Estlund ed., Blackwell 2002). 95 KENNETH J. ARROW, SOCIAL CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES (2d ed., Yale Univ. Press 1970). 258 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 serves as an invitation to self-interested minorities to capitalize on the intensity of their self-regarding preferences.96 Under this view, the uncertainties of collective decision making undermine rather than reinforce the capacity for aggregated wisdom.97 In such circumstances, the public-choice critique may be pushed further than simply the problem of incoherence. When rational indifference infects the majority, Mancur Olsen cautions that “[t]here is a systematic tendency for exploitation of the great by the small.”98 Equally challenging to the proclaimed “wisdom of the multitudes” is an argument that contests not the inability of the majority will to prevail in the political arena but the integrity of the majority will itself. The founding insight of the American democratic experiment was that, if left unchecked, popular governance risked collapsing into oppression by the unreasoned passion of faction. Madison’s Federalist No. 10 formulated the issue crisply: Among the numerous advantages promised by a well constructed union, none deserves to be more accurately developed than its tendency to break and control the violence of faction. . . . [B]y a faction, I understand a number of citizens, whether amounting to a majority or a minority of the whole, who are united and actuated by some common impulse of passion, or of interest, adversed to the rights of other citizens, or to the permanent and aggregate interests of the community.99 As developed by De Tocqueville and John Stuart Mill, passion was most dangerous when it consumed the mass of the population, what De Tocqueville would term the “tyranny of the majority.”100 For Mill, this collective will “to oppress a part of their number” had to be “included among the evils against which society requires to be on its guard.”101 More recently, Cass Sunstein has 96 JAMES M. BUCHANAN & GORDON TULLOCK, THE CALCULUS OF CONSENT: LOGICAL FOUNDATIONS OF CONSTITUDEMOCRACY §§ 3.2.3–3.2.8 (1999), available at http://www.econlib.org/library/Buchanan/ buchCv3Contents.html. TIONAL 97 WILLIAM H. RIKER, LIBERALISM AGAINST POPULISM: A CONFRONTATION BETWEEN THE THEORY OF DEMOCRACY THEORY OF SOCIAL CHOICE (W.H. Freeman & Co. 1982). AND THE 98 MANCUR OLSON, JR., THE LOGIC (Harvard Univ. Press 1971). 99 OF COLLECTIVE ACTION: PUBLIC GOODS AND THE THEORY OF GROUPS 29 THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, AT 40-41 (James Madison) (Terence Ball ed., 2003). 100 ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 292 (Gerald Bevan trans., Penguin Classics 2003) (1835). 101 JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY 62 (Gertrude Himmelfarb ed., Penguin Classics 1982) (1859). Paradoxically, Mill also recognized not only the possibility but the need for a nation to be forged through the suppression of obstacles to national unity, including minority languages and other attributes hostile to the development of a national identity. As he expressed it, “When proper allowance has been made for geographical exigencies, another more purely moral and social consideration offers itself. Experience proves that it is possible for one nationality to merge and be absorbed in another: and when it was originally an inferior and more backward portion of the human race the absorption is greatly to its advantage.” JOHN STUART MILL, CONSIDERATIONS ON REPRESENTATIVE GOVERNMENT 313 (Henry Regnery 1962) (1861). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 259 argued strongly that, contrary to deliberativist claims about the virtues of collective decision making, the outputs of group interactions may be more extreme—instead of more reasoned—than individual judgments. Summarizing a host of empirical studies, Sunstein concludes, “The central empirical finding is that group discussion is likely to shift judgments toward a more extreme point in the direction indicated by the median of predeliberation judgments.”102 Outside the experimental setting, the evidence regarding broadscale collective decision making is more mixed. Certainly, plebiscites have proven a powerful mechanism to arouse mass anger against parliamentary bodies and were central to the rise of fascism in Germany and Italy.103 At the same time, Switzerland—a bastion of moderation—relies extensively on direct voting of the citizens on public policy, a feature that some have claimed contributes to a sense of civic engagement.104 Indeed, Robert Cooter argues that direct democracy best avoids the capture problem of public-choice theory and rewards temperate decision making: When citizens vote their preferences on a single dimension of choice, the median usually prevails. In general, direct democracy factors the issues, so the median voter should prevail. In contrast, members of legislatures bargain, compromise, and roll logs. In general, indirect democracy splices issues, which should result in bargains or cycles.105 Nonetheless, the claim that, absent institutional buffers, collective action risks devolving into the politics of passion and narrow self-interest is well recognized, if not universally accepted. As I have discussed elsewhere, the strong administrative hand overseeing Indian election campaigns is premised on the perceived need to control inflammatory rhetoric and the attendant risk of mass violence—and its constitutionality has been upheld on precisely that basis.106 3. Institutional temporizing Let us now return to what courts should do when confronted with first-order questions concerning the constitution of the polity. I have suggested, thus far, 102 Cass R. Sunstein, Deliberative Trouble? Why Groups Go to Extremes, 110 YALE L.J. 71, 118 (2000). 103 See generally RICHARD J. EVANS, THE COMING OF THE THIRD REICH (Penguin 2004); ADRIAN LYTTELTON, THE SEIZURE OF POWER: FASCISM IN ITALY 1919–1929 (Routledge 2004). 104 See, e.g., BRUNO S. FREY & ALOIS STUTZER, HAPPINESS AND ECONOMICS: HOW THE ECONOMY AND INSTITUTIONS AFFECT HUMAN WELL-BEING (Princeton Univ. Press 2002) (discussing positive effects of direct democracy on citizens in Switzerland). See also Caroline J. Tolbert & Daniel A. Smith, Representation and Direct Democracy in the United States, 42 REPRESENTATION 25 (2006) (arguing that the initiative and referendum processes increase civic engagement in American states based on empirical research). 105 ROBERT D. COOTER, THE STRATEGIC CONSTITUTION 232–233 (Princeton Univ. Press 1999). 106 Samuel Issacharoff, Fragile Democracies, 120 HARV. L. REV. 1405 (2007). 260 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 that courts are likely to have no fixed polestar in either established jurisprudence or in political theory to guide them through these difficult decisions. Let us further accept, at least for predictive purposes, that modern constitutional courts are unlikely to be deterred by some variant of the political-question doctrine.107 To a great extent, the creation of strong constitutional courts in emerging democracies is an indication that they are expected to play a more direct role in superintending the institutions of democracy and, particularly, in defining the limits of democratic decision making. Nowhere is this clearer than in South Africa, where the interim compromise between the African National Congress and the apartheid rulers of the National Party required the immediate creation of a constitutional court and provided that the Court would then have the power of judicial review over the final constitution. This was to ensure that the document conformed to the negotiated compromise principles—in effect, the power to determine the constitutionality of the constitution itself.108 By their nature, constitutional courts assume an oversight role with regard to the political process, since, typically, they have no jurisdiction to consider the operation of ordinary legislation.109 But it is not just newly minted constitutional courts that must deal with first-order questions of the political organization of the polity. In some sense, all courts confront these issues rather routinely in passing on matters of local governance, wherein an electoral question of the reconstitution of local boundaries presupposes a correct answer as 107 For a historic account of the development and erosion of the political-question doctrine, see Rachel Barkow, More Supreme than Court? The Fall of the Political Question Doctrine and the Rise of Judicial Supremacy, 102 COLUM. L. REV. 237 (2002). For a contrast between the jurisdictional limit on what courts may hear and the prudential limit on what courts should entertain, see Samuel Issacharoff, Political Judgments, 68 U. CHI. L. REV. 637 (2001). Many commentators have noted the increased willingness of courts around the world to entertain claims regarding the operation of the political process on terms that would previously have been deemed beyond judicial scrutiny. See, e.g., John Ferejohn, Judicializing Politics, Politicizing Law, 65 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 41, 61 (2002); Russell A. Miller, Lords of Democracy: The Judicialization of “Pure Politics” in the United States and Germany, 61 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 587, 588–592 (2004). For a broader overview, see C. Neal Tate, Why the Expansion of Judicial Power, in THE GLOBAL EXPANSION OF JUDICIAL POWER 27, 27 (C. Neal Tate & Torbjörn Vallinder eds., New York Univ. Press 1995). 108 For a discussion of the negotiated transition and the role of the South African Constitutional Court, see Samuel Issacharoff, Constitutionalizing Democracy in Fractured Societies, 82 TEX. L. REV. 1861, 1870–1883 (2004); Ziyad Motala, Constitution-Making in Divided Societies and Legitimacy: Lessons from the South African Experience, 15 TEMP. POL. & CIV. RTS. L. REV. 147 (2005). See also In re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, supra note 71. 109 For a critical assessment of the tendency to turn quickly to constitutional principle by specialized constitutional courts, see Victor Ferreres Comella, The Consequences of Centralizing Judicial Review in a Special Court: Some Thoughts on Judicial Activism, 82 TEX. L. REV. 1705, 1730 (2004) (arguing that specialized constitutional courts will tend to be relatively less deferential because “[a] constitutional court is not likely to earn its own space in the institutional system if it regularly upholds the statutes that are challenged before it”). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 261 to who should make the decision.110 Nonetheless, there is relatively little at stake in these quotidian instances of how to define the polity. Institutions of local governance, significant thought they may be, do not carry the incidents of sovereignty about them. Even when applied in repugnant fashion, such as to further racial subjugation,111 the excluded population remains a part of the broader state enterprise, even if denied some of the benefits that might flow from local inclusion.112 However courts respond to matters of local governance, there is just no comparing the stakes when the breakup of a country is at issue. There is no escaping the inherent difficulties courts face in superintending the political process. So long as democratic political institutions retain their flexibility to respond to internal domestic pressures, courts are invariably hard-pressed to assess the desirability of any particular accommodation. The natural inclination is to move to higher levels of principle, often found in the form of categorical rights claims, and to apply those in rather categorical fashion. To give just one example, the German Constitutional Court found itself perilously close to upholding a claim that the Maastricht treaty somehow violated individual voting rights in Germany.113 It is hard to imagine a more difficult political decision than to cede some of the historic badges of sovereignty by entering a Europe-wide political and monetary union. Whatever the arguments on behalf of European integration—and there are many—it would be sheer folly to view such a historic move through the distorting prism of individual voting rights. Of necessity, many claims of democratic engagement are presented, properly, as matters of fundamental rights. The ability to participate regardless of race or gender or ethnicity is the most obvious. These claims are almost invariably addressed by reference to higher authority at either the national level or 110 These questions can be routinely posed by annexations and deannexations of particular areas into municipal zones. Thus, by and large, most courts in the U.S. have upheld limiting the franchise based on geography or landholding, as well as on the basis of property holding in the area under consideration. See, e.g., Simi Valley Recreation & Park Dist. v. Local Agency Formation Comm’n, 124 Cal. Rptr. 635 (Cal. Ct. App. 1975) (permissible to exclude residents who do not live in area to be deannexed); Moorman v. Wood, 504 F. Supp. 467 (E.D. Ky. 1980) (permissible to limit franchise in deannexation to only those voters in area potentially to be deannexed). For an overview, see Clayton R. Gillette, Voting With Your Hands: Direct Democracy in Annexation, 78 S. CAL. L. REV. 835 (2005). 111 See, e.g., Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U.S. 339 (1960) (striking down disenfranchising racial redistricting in Tuskegee, Alabama). 112 See, e.g., Holt Civic Club v. City of Tuscaloosa, 439 U.S. 60 (1978) (upholding the city’s police jurisdiction over adjacent unincorporated areas despite the absence of a concomitant extension of the right to vote in city elections). 113 89 BVerfG 155 (1993) as translated in DONALD P. KOMMERS, THE CONSTITUTIONAL JURISPRUDENCE OF THE FEDERAL REPUBLIC OF GERMANY, 182–186 (2d ed., Duke Univ. Press 1997). 262 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 even at the supranational level.114 But it is important not to confuse these claims with those that address the structure of governance. The former are framed primarily in terms of the relation of individual citizens to the state, whereas the latter are concerned with the structure of governmental power. Drawing this distinction should serve as a caution against the easy adoption of a collectivizing template under the mandate of rights jurisprudence.115 The challenge to the complicated Belgian voting system is a useful case in point. Despite my discomfort with consociationalism as political theory, and despite extreme skepticism over its track record in actually deflating regional and ethnic antagonisms, I nonetheless find much to commend in the ECtHR’s treatment of the issue, focused as it is on the array of institutional arrangements in Belgium. An overinfatuation with rights claims risks having the courts assume a universalist assessment of politics, one that is likely to be insensitive to the complicated institutional arrangements that underpin modern democracies. We have long ago crossed the line that would keep courts away from first-order political questions, such as European trade agreements or the dissolution of Canada or the consociational core of Belgium. However, backing off from the easy universalism of rights claims may allow courts to extricate themselves from a logic that can be highly destabilizing for otherwise menaced democratic regimes. This may be the “exit strategy,” as Pamela Karlan terms it,116 by means of which the courts could restore a measure of deference to the institutional realities of politics and the ongoing efforts to protect democracy from the imperfections of human society. 4. Conclusion: Judicial oversight and political experimentation The cases under consideration in this article present in extreme form the conflict that emerges whenever courts confront the basic institutional arrangements of national politics. They are extreme because judicial intervention is 114 See Thomas Franck, The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance, 86 AM. J. INT’L L. 46 (1992) (describing increased rigor of international law commitments to democratic rights). 115 There is a debate of some duration now in the legal literature on the law governing the political process. Many have termed these debates as between “structuralists” and “rights advocates.” See Guy-Uriel E. Charles, Democracy and Distortion, 92 CORNELL L. REV. 601 (2007); Heather K. Gerken, Lost in the Political Thicket: The Court, Election Law, and the Doctrinal Interregnum, 153 U. PA. L. REV. 503, 510 (2004). A repeated claim is that “the structural approach leads inevitably to intrusive judicial involvement in states’ political arrangements.” Bruce E. Cain, Garrett’s Temptation, 85 VA. L. REV. 1589, 1600 (1999). One of the secondary points of this article is to show, quite the contrary, that the mechanical invocation of a rights-based approach threatens destabilization by the courts of reasonable and necessary political accommodations. 116 Pamela S. Karlan, Exit Strategies in Constitutional Law: Lessons for Getting the Least Dangerous Branch Out of the Political Thicket, 82 B.U. L. REV. 667 (2002). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 263 not conditioned by easy recourse to precedent or to an organizing theory of what is the proper allocation of political responsibility among different potential levels of governance.117 In the absence of readily distilled principles either in law or political theory, courts should be guided by a proper appreciation of the role that judicial oversight can play in the political arena. There are four key justifications for judiciaries to override local political arrangements, which may be applied in cases of high consequence, that nonetheless lack clear doctrinal moorings. This is not the place to develop at length the justification for each of these grounds for judicial intervention. Rather, these grounds are suggested by both the international case law and by the extensive literature on the role of judges in the political process. However, together they provide a useful buffer against the easy imposition of the one-size-fits-all approaches that disrupt functioning political arrangements. First, there are, of course, actual claims of rights violations. While this article has dealt with the need to avoid easy imposition of a simple rights template on complicated questions of political participation, nonetheless simple franchise rights are at the heart of the democratic enterprise. The denial of the ability to participate on the basis of race or gender or religion falls within the sort of individual entitlement readily recognized and addressed by courts. There is no shortage of cases from around the world upholding the basic elements of the franchise against discriminatory exclusions. Nevertheless, precisely because individual right-to-vote cases provide the path of least resistance, there is the unmistakable tendency for courts to package complex political questions in the ready formula of rights claims. In the United States, a presumed individual right extended to everyone to equally effective votes became the vehicle of choice for the Court to overcome the political-question barrier from Baker v. Carr forward. As the German Constitutional Court’s willingness to consider a rights challenge to the Maastricht treaty indicates, however, the temptation to see fundamental political arrangements through the prism of individual rights is by no means limited to the U.S.118 A second source of judicial authority to disrupt settled political arrangements lies in the obligation to ensure accountability of the process to the electorate. Ultimately, elections in a democracy “must provide the opportunity for 117 Some have tried to fill in this gap by relying on principles of citizen engagement in possible decision making, thereby drawing on a view of democracy that promotes participation and the generation of information from local bodies. The most intriguing of these approaches is advanced by my colleague Rick Hills. See Roderick M. Hills, Jr., Against Preemption: How Federalism Can Improve the National Legislative Process, 82 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1 (2007). 118 Another noteworthy example from the ECtHR comes with Bowman v. United Kingdom, 26 Eur. H.R. Rep. 1 (1998), a challenge to the entire British system of financing of political parties and election campaigns, also handled from the limited perspective of individual rights to participate. See Jacob Rowbottom, Access of the Airwaves and Equality: The Case Against Political Advertising on the Broadcast Media, in PARTY FUNDING AND CAMPAIGN FINANCING IN INTERNATIONAL PERSPECTIVE 77 (K.D. Ewing & Samuel Issacharoff, eds., Hart 2006). 264 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 genuine contestation, and their outcomes must not be preordained by the design of institutional structures.”119 The key insight is a skepticism toward the problem of “self-interest in institutional design,”120 a likely result when insiders are able to realize substantial protection by altering the rules of the game to their benefit. This issue has been at the heart of the arguments about legal regulation of the political process as well as central to the academic debates over the law of democracy for the better part of a decade.121 The overall question of the competitive vitality of the electoral system increasingly has instructed judicial inquiries into such critical matters as the threshold of representation in proportional representation systems,122 or the impact of party finance regulation on the overall accountability of elected representatives,123 or even the proper application of protections against minority vote dilution under the Voting Rights Act.124 The core insight is that courts remain important institutional actors standing against the manipulation of electoral institutions to the advantage of incumbent officeholders.125 119 Charles, supra note 115, at 609. 120 Elizabeth Garrett, Who Chooses the Rules?, 3 ELECTION L.J. 139, 139 (2005). 121 The opening gambit in this inquiry was Samuel Issacharoff & Richard Pildes, Politics as Markets: Partisan Lockups of the Democratic Process, 50 STAN. L. REV. 643 (1998). 122 In Germany, for example, the Constitutional Court upheld a 5 percent threshold for representation as a reasonable political accommodation, particularly in light of the postwar need for stability. See DONALD P. KOMMERS, THE CONSTITUTIONAL JURISPRUDENCE OF THE FEDERAL REPUBLIC OF GERMANY 186–187 (2d ed., Duke Univ. Press 1997) (discussing the Bavarian Party Case, 6 BVerfGE 84 (1957)). Subsequently, after reunification, the Court struck down efforts to expand the scope of newly integrated parties to “piggyback” in coalitions in order to achieve the 5 percent threshold. Id. at 188–189 (translation of the National Unity Election Case, 82 BVerfGE 322 (1990)). A similar issue was presented by the 2002 reforms to the Turkish parliamentary system, which raised the threshold of representation to ten percent. The European Court of Human Rights upheld the high threshold and ruled in a manner consistent with the thesis of this article: The rules in this area vary in accordance with the historical and political factors specific to each State; the large variety of situations provided for in the electoral legislation of numerous member States of the Council of Europe shows the diversity of the possible options. For the purposes of applying Article 3 of the Protocol, any electoral legislation must be assessed in the light of the political evolution of the country concerned, so that features that would be unacceptable in the context of one system may be justified in the context of another… , at least so long as the chosen system provides for conditions which will ensure the “free expression of the opinion of the people in the choice of the legislature.” Case of Yumak & Sadak v. Turkey, App. No. 10226/03, Eur. Ct. Hum. Rts., Jan. 30, 2007, available at http://www.legislationline.org/legislation.php?tid=1&lid=7475. 123 See McConnell v. FEC 540 U.S. 93, 247 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part, dissenting in part). 124 See Ellen Katz, Reviving the Right to Vote, 68 OHIO ST. L.J. 1163 (2007). 125 See, for example, the role of the Ukrainian Constitutional Court in forcing a showdown with the government over the election rules in 2004. The basic instinct here was well captured by John Hart Ely, who viewed elections cases as “[involving] rights (1) that are essential to the democratic process and (2) whose dimensions cannot safely be left to our elected representatives, who have an obvious vested interest in the status quo.” JOHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 117 (Harvard Univ. Press 1980). Issacharoff | Democracy and collective decision making 265 Third, and relatedly, courts may intercede as a backstop against institutional desuetude. The unresponsiveness of an electoral system can be a matter of a lock up of power by self-interested incumbents or of the calcification of institutional arrangements when there is insufficient political will for change. The problem of malapportionment in the U.S., the predicate for the Baker v. Carr line of cases, is an example of both the self-interest of the overrepresented rural constituencies and the inertial difficulties of political reform. By contrast, where political arrangements are more recent and reflect a genuine compromise, there should be a much greater presumption of legal tolerance of experimentation.126 Certainly this was a focus of the ECtHR in Mathieu-Mohin and Clerfayt v. Belgium, in which the recent negotiations between the various linguistic groups was one of the factors considered by the Court—and properly so. Similarly, Richard Pildes has argued that the U.S. Supreme Court should take into account the recent highprofile political negotiations over the McCain-Feingold campaign reform bill as a factor in considering the constitutionality of the legislation.127 Finally, judicial oversight may serve as a protection against opportunism, particularly when political boundaries serve to isolate those who bear the costs from any realistic ability to challenge political decision making occurring elsewhere. Evidence for this may be found in the U.S. Constitution’s prohibition on interstate compacts that potentially burden nonparticipating states.128 But the same problem can arise independently of a formal agreement between two states to privilege themselves at the expense of others. The simplest manifestation of this may come with pollution, as when any state in the Midwest has the power to permit the burning of high-sulfur coal for power, subject only to a requirement of tall smokestacks to send the fumes aloft. For the citizens of the Northeast, by contrast, the consequences of acid rain are not susceptible to any political form of self-protection. To provide such protection, therefore, is a task that some courts, such as the U.S. Supreme Court and the European Court of Justice, have read into the role of ensuring economic integration through doctrines such as preemption.129 126 The U.S. Supreme Court refused to consider just such an argument in the one case from the early Baker/Reynolds era that was the product of a recent political compromise rather than simply reflecting the dead hand of history. The clearest presentation of this issue is in Lucas v. The FortyFourth General Assembly District of the State of Colorado, 377 U.S. 713 (1964). 127 Pildes, supra note 74, at 135–138. “No State shall, without the Consent of Congress, … enter into any Agreement or Compact with another State… .” U.S. CONST. art. I, §10, cl. 3. “The Founders were acutely aware of the need to protect states and their citizens from sister-state aggression; that is why they adopted the Compact Clause … [to protect] comity and equality among the states.” Michael S. Greve, Compacts, Cartels, and Congressional Consent, 68 MO. L. REV. 285, 293 (2003). See generally JOSEPH FRANCIS ZIMMERMAN, INTERSTATE COOPERATION: COMPACTS AND ADMINISTRATIVE AGREEMENTS (Praeger 2002). 128 129 For an extended discussion of this theme, see Samuel Issacharoff & Catherine M. Sharkey, Backdoor Federalization, 53 UCLA L. REV. 1353 (2006). 266 I•CON April 2008 Vol. 6: 231 In more recent constitutional arrangements, such as that of South Africa, there may be a direct commitment that all spheres of governmental authority must “exercise their powers and perform their functions in a manner that does not encroach on the geographical, functional or institutional integrity of government in another sphere.”130 Almost invariably, the increased scope of market activity as it reaches national and international levels is a strong factor in the push toward the use of higher-order legal authority when dealing with regulation of economic activity. As discussed previously, however, the translation from the economic scale of market conduct to the proper form of political organization is far from direct. In sum, even a brief look at the court decision considered in this article shows that it is becoming commonplace for courts to confront questions that were long deemed beyond the realm of possible judicial competence. Simply as a descriptive matter, courts now routinely engage the complicated world of political power in ways unimaginable a few generations back. In some cases, extreme perhaps, this new state of affairs requires a confrontation with the first-order question of what is the proper form of governance for a nation of multiple peoples living in overlapping lands. Little in either the common law or civil law traditions prepares the field doctrinally for the resolution of such questions. This article is ultimately about some of the difficulties in confronting an area without clear markers in either legal or political theory. One may hope the article also provides a caution against courts being swept along too easily by the tide of rights claims that were, in many cases, the initial impetus for the courts to enter the political domain. The world of politics is too contested and too precarious for such a simple template. 130 S. AFR. CONST. 1996 § 41(1)(g).
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz