OVERVIEW OF THE TALK CAN CLOSEST CONJUNCT AGREEMENT BE DERIVED IN THE SYNTAX PROPER? Lanko Marušič, Jana Willer-‐Gold, Boban Arsenijević, Andrew Nevins Based on the EMSS project, funded by the Leverhulme Trust #emssproject • Closest-Conjunct Agreement Experimental Evidence (CCA) in South Slavic: • Modeling the basic patterns (closest-conjunct agreement and highest conjunct agreement) • Distributed vs purely syntactic approaches to CCA • Further constraining the theory: sandwiched agreement (two probes, one on each side) 1 2 IS THE MAN WHO IS TALL HAPPY? METHODOLOGY: ELICITED PRODUCTION • Chomsky 1975: Syntax refers to hierarchical, not linear order, when it comes to auxiliary movement; learners prefer hierarchically-based generalisations 1983: South Slavic languages show cases of agreement based on linear order: when two noun-phrases are conjoined, the verb can sometimes agree with the linearly closest one Participant sees model sentence Prevod je ovjeren pečatom. translation.M.SG. AUX.SG authenticated.M.SG. by.seal • Corbett • Bock & Miller 1991: English speakers show cases of agreement based on linear order, called ‘attraction’, with the plural complement of noun phrases (e.g. the key to the cabinets are) Participant sees replacement noun phrase (&P) displayed onscreen Molbe i rješenja requests.F.PL. and decisions.N.PL. Participant produces new sentence aloud and then clicks mouse Molbe i rješenja su ovjeren-i/-a/-e pečatom requests.F.PL. and decisions.N.PL. AUX.PL • How experimentally robust is linear conjunct agreement in South Slavic morphosyntax? Is it distinct from attraction? 3 Responses recorded, classified, tabulated 4 IP NP2 VP NP1 NP1 CP C METHODS AND MATERIALS • Nine &P combinations of two genders; 6 items per condition • All NPs inanimate and plural; dependent variable = gender agreement on participle • 54 distractor items (18 RCs, 18 QNPs, 18 epicene nouns) • Exp 1a: SV configurations (preverbal subjects), n=30 * 6 sites • Exp 1b: VS configurations (postverbal subjects), n=30 * 6 sites • Design and methodology identical across sites with local adaptation of vocabulary and morphosyntax • Participants 18-22, not linguistics students; native speakers who grew up in region tested VP IP GIVEN A HIERARCHICAL &P IP &P NP2 NP1 VP & SV VS Linearly closest conjunct NP1 VP … … V V &’P & NP2 Linearly closest conjunct VP &P V &’P &P NP1 &’P & NP2 Distal conjunct still hierarchically higher NP2 Distal conjunct hierarchically lowest VP V 1 &P NP1 &’P & NP2 5 6 CHOOSING THE AGREEMENT STRATEGY LINEAR AGREEMENT IS ROBUST GIVEN &PS (FN/NF) • The ‘default’ or ‘resolution’ value masculine 1 Results for SV condition (where first and closer diverge) for conjuncts with mixed genders is • When a &P has M+F, N+M, etc, and we see masculine agreement, we can’t tell if it’s default agreement or closest-conjunct agreement the combinations N+F and F+N, there are three distinct options: first-conjunct agreement (hierarchical), closestconjunct agreement (linear), and default agreement (resolution/ prescriptive) 61% Highest Closest 44% • However, in • (In VS contexts, the first-conjunct is the closest conjunct) 7 43% 40% 39% 42% 22% 16% 17% 11% 11% Ljubljana Niš 8% Novi Sad Sarajevo 8 Zadar Zagreb Willer-Gold et al (in prep) &P NP1 V IP &PS AREN’T JUST FLAT: DISTAL CONJUNCT AGREEMENT IF &PS WERE FLAT… &IP NPNP 22 VP VS NP1 &P NP2 V… NP1 VP & NP2 VP V NP1 NP1 NP2 BUT IF HIERARCHICAL… VP V &P &’P & & Distal conjunct “three nodes away” …V &P & &P & NP1NP2 Distal conjunct “three nodes away” VP V &’P 5 … IP V &P If &Ps were just flat, then the distal conjunct in both SV and VS conditions should be equally produced/judged VPVP IP % of distal productions C Linearly closest conjunct preferred … &’P & NP2 Distal conjunct still hierarchically higher * &P NP1 NP2 * 0% VP 4 Linearly closest conjunct preferred NP1 CP rating of distal agreement SV NP1 3 NP1 2 &P C 1 NP2 VP CP 60% & NP1 40% &’P 20% NP1 SV NP2 VS Willer-Gold et al (in prep) SV VS &Ps have internal hierarchical structure Distal conjunct hierarchically lowest 9 10 VP V 1 &P THEORIES OF CONJUNCT AGREEMENT: MARUSIC ET AL (2007/2015) SO WHERE CAN LINEARITY TRUMP HIERARCHY? NP1 &’P & NP2 • Key • In one principled corner of the grammar, in one small corner 1 of the world intense research focus is how to model the variability in agreement strategies within a restricted model of possibilities (Boskovic 2009, Puskar & Murphy 2014, Marusic et al 2007/2015) • Two-step Agree: Agree-Link • An can be grouped into purely syntactic approaches to CCA versus distributed approaches to CCA • These 11 idea: ConjP doesn’t have its own gender vs Agree-Copy •A Probe may establish a relation with a Goal (e.g. Pesetsky & Torrego 2007), but the actual copying takes place postsyntactically (see also Bhatt & Walkow 2013) 2 • Participles enact Agree-Link with ConjP, but depending on how and when Agree-Copy takes place, different parts of ConjP may be targeted 12 2 MARUSIC ET AL (2007/2015): AGREE-COPY CHOICE • ConjP has its own Number, but not its own Gender • Speakers who wish to avoid default Gender must therefore open up the lid on the ConjP and choose one of the individual conjuncts during Agree-Copy • Key BHATT & WALKOW 2013: DISTRIBUTED AGREEMENT • In Hindi/Urdu, while conjoined subjects show resolved agreement, conjoined objects show CCA – Closest Conjunct an the Illusion • AgreementMurphy must &bePuškar partly syntactic to Agreement account isfor Murphy & Puškar(repeated – Closest Conjunct Agreement is an Illusion Murphy & Puškar – Closest Agreement Illusion below) thatConjunct LCA is onlyis anacceptable • If Agree-Copy happens before linearization, HCA results • If Agree-Copy happens after linearization, CCA results • (ThereMurphy is no way to Conjunct choose a medial & Puškar – Closest Agreement is an Illusion conjunct (17) (repeated below) that LCA is only acceptable when the conjunct phrase is in preverbal position. It is entirely ungrammatical if the &P is postverbal. It is entirely ungrammatical theSve &P ishaljine postverbal. syntax, PF mechanisms step ini to sva furnish agreement, and these,. (54) (54) [if&P odela] su. juče prodata [ Sve haljine i sva odela] su juče prodata all may dress.fpl and suit.npl are sell.prt.npl (54) [post-syntactic, Sve haljine i sva odela] su be jučeall sensitive prodata .to all dress.fpl and allyesterday suit.npl are yesterday sell.prt.npl being linear order ‘All dresses and all suits were sold yesterday.’ &P if there 8are 3) all dress.fpl and all suit.npl are yesterday sell.prt.npl ‘Allwere dresses and all suits were sold yesterday.’ (55) su yesterday. prodata ’ [&P sve haljine i sva odela]. ‘All dresses and all suits*Juče sold (55) 8 An important starting assumption is that the participle is a single ϕ-probe, which probes for number and gender features of the noun together (following Bejar 2003). Another assumption is that (17) Juče su items prodata [&P sva odelaas valued/unvalued i sve haljine]. and interpretable/uninterpretable features on lexical are characterised Yesterday are sell.prt.npl suits.npl and all dresses.fpl (2007). The process of Last Conjunct Agreement (17) proposed in the spirit of Pesetsky & Torrego all ‘All suits and all dresses were sold yesterday.’ in this account proceeds following the steps in (18) – (21). Step 1: The probe establishes a Match relation withis &P for number NP1 for gender An important starting assumption is that the participle a single ϕ-probe, and which probes for num-(it enters ber and gender features of the noun together (following Bejar2007). 2003). Another assumption is that into Multiple Agree; Hiraiwa 2001, Pesetsky & Torrego THEORIES OF CONJUNCT AGREEMENT: BOSKOVIC (2009) features on lexical items are characterised as valued/unvalued and interpretable/uninterpretable [PrtP Participle ... The process of [&P NP2gender ]] uϕ: (2007). number gender & Torrego Last ConjunctNP1 Agreement (17)&proposed in(18) the spirit of Pesetsky in this account proceeds following the steps in (18) – (21). Step 1: The probe establishes a Match relation with &P for number and NP1 for gender (it enters StepMultiple 2: If theAgree; probeHiraiwa has an EPP of the subject is required. Valuators undergo into 2001,feature, Pesetskypied-piping & Torrego 2007). Multiple Agree pied-piping, and here pied-piping of the subject fails due to ambiguity of the target for movement (18) Participle ... as Serbo-Croatian [&P number NP2gender ]] uϕ:moved (either[PrtP &P or NP1 can be allowsNP1 for gender violations&of Coordinate Structure an entire conjunct phrase which has only inherited the features of one of its conjuncts, in The central claim of thiswith paper is that the nature of ‘closest’ is in Closest Conjunct Agreement this case, the final NP. In order to have an &P that has only inherited the features of the second entirely illusory. What we in fact have the case of LCA, example,( ↑Agr↑) is actually agreement conjunct, theclaim Agreein operation targetting the for first will have toof fail ‘closest’ to apply. We is in Closest Conjunct Agreemen The central of this paper isconjunct that↑Agr↑ theapplies with an entire conjunct phrase which has only inherited the features one ofnature its conjuncts, can achieve this with an order of operations in which of too early, i.e.inbefore the been The relevant in (56). this case, the finalentirely NP. Inconjuncts order tohave have anmerged. &P that has only inherited the features the second illusory. What we inorder factis given have in theof case of LCA, for example, is actually agreemen conjunct, the Agree operation targetting the first conjunct ( ↑Agr↑) will have to fail to apply. We (Move) >conjunct ↑Agr↑ > Merge > ↓Agr↓ with (56) an entire phrase which has only inherited the features of one of its conjuncts, i can achieve this with an order of operations in which ↑Agr↑ applies too early, i.e. before the Here, Merge applies after ↑Agr↑, an instance counterfeeding. Thethat derivation thismerged. case,The therelevant finalorder NP.isIn order toof have an &P hasproceeds onlyasinherited the features of the secon conjuncts have been given in (56). PUSKAR & MURPHY 2015: have to fail to apply. W can achieve this with an order of operations in which ↑Agr↑ applies too early, i.e. before th DERIVING CCA SYNTACTICALLY conjuncts have been merged. The relevant order is given in (56). follows: Move does not apply. ↑Agr↑ applies before Merge. Since there is no goal that this (56) Constraint according to the author) and they are assumed to count as equidistant. if Probe has EPP: Pied-Piping ambiguity; can’t move either (57) Since NP2 now as a valuator cannot be extracted, the only option is to move the whole &P to subject position, which results in the LCA pattern. • (In to fact ′ (59) N N (60) Move > ↑Agr↑ > (Merge) > ↓Agr↓:operation ↑Agr↑ and Agree will find a goal in T’s specifier (60): &′ (57) ↑Agr↑: & NP &P [gender: !] &P N suits N ➊ ↓Agr↓: (58) Merge:suits. to the target of EPP-driven movement, the gender features on the verb can be provided by NP1 (60) Move > ↑Agr↑ > (Merge) > ↓Agr↓: TP T′ ➋ N &P N T are [ϕ:!] vP NP VP v v & dresses.F sold tV T Move feeds T vP upward Agree; NP are v with VP &P T agrees [ϕ:!] suits. v sold t t (and hence NP2) ′ &′ t&P ➋ N &P addition, for 3-conjuncts, predicts medial conjunct agreement…) 15 TP &&′ [gender:!] & NP dresses. F NP The derivation ofTFirst[PrtP Conjunct Agreement is essentially same&process, the only (21) [TP Participle .(17) . . [&Pnumber NP1the NP2gender ]]] differuϕ: gender ence being that the pied-piping dilemma in (19) does not arise, as the probe does not have an EPP feature in this derivation. Since there is no conflict between the two valuators with respect The derivation of EPP-driven First Conjunct Agreementthe (17)gender is essentially theon same thebeonly differ- by NP1 to the target of movement, features theprocess, verb can provided ence being that the pied-piping dilemma in (19) does not arise, as the probe does not have an and the conjunct phrase can stay in situ, thereby yielding postverbal FCA. Thus, the availability EPP feature in this derivation. Since there is no conflict between the two valuators with respect of LCA or FCA is tied to the presence of an EPP feature on the probe. For LCA, the EPP feature F F dresses F gender F N NP Step 4: Since the probe bears an EPP feature, movement of the &P or one of the NPs is required. (20) [ Participle .move; .[ NP1 option is &to NP2 ]]] &P This &Pcannot canbe. extracted, preverbal CCA Sincetime, NP now[ only as a valuator theyielding only move the whole to Step 4: Since the probe bears an EPP feature, movement of the &P one of the NPs is required. • Disadvantage: beor impossible, (21) [predicts T preverbal [PrtP ParticipleHCA . . . [to NP1 gender & counter NP2gender ]]] TP uϕ: &Pnumber Here, Merge applies after ↑Agr↑, an instance of counterfeeding. The derivation proceeds a NP & &P dresses Move follows: not apply. ↑Agr↑ applies before Merge. Since there is no goal that th & does NP NP & Downward Agree: [gender: n] NP & operation can target, it does not find a goal (57) and thus applies vacuously. The next operatio suits dresses & & NP &P valued by NP2 dresses & NP [gender: n] [gender:!] Merge introduces the conjuncts via External Merge (58). Finally, ↓Agr↓ applies and the & suits [gender: !]operations must be maintained. There are At the TP level, the previous order of again two possible Merge: scenarios depending on whether Movesuits or not. Move the takes place, it willconjunct feed the next (59). As a result, the &P node bea head receives the genderapplies value ofIfonly lowest &P (59) thespecifier TP level, the previous order of operations must be maintained. There are again two possible ↓Agr↓: operation ↑Agr↑ and Agree will find a goal inAtT’s (60): scenarios depending whether Move applies or not. If Move takes place, it will feed the next the featuresorder of only the second conjunct. Uniform of operations within aonderivation: ′ ➊ Solution: do Agree again, this time with NP2: gender 27 ↑Agr↑: &P Step 3: To prevent a crash due to lack of valuation, another cycle of Agree is instantiated, resulting in(20) targeting NP2, because NP1 uϕ: was deactivated as goal afterNP1 thegender first Agree & cycle (i.e. its gender ]]] [TP&P and [PrtP Participle . . . [&Pnumber NP2 uninterpretable gender feature was deleted after Match, unlike the number feature of the &P, which is interpretable, and therefore not deleted after Match). &Pnumber Merge introduces the conjuncts via External Merge (58). Finally, ↓Agr↓ applies and the &- head↑Agr↑, receives the value only the lowest conjunct (59). As a result, the &Pas node bears Here, Merge applies after an gender instance ofofcounterfeeding. The derivation proceeds the features of only the second conjunct. follows: Move does not&apply. Merge. Since there is no goal that this 27 Murphy Puškar –↑Agr↑ Closestapplies Conjunctbefore Agreement is an Illusion (57) ↑Agr↑: operation can target, it does not find a goal (57) and thus applies vacuously. The next operation &P Merge introduces the conjuncts via External Merge (58). Finally, applies and the &(56) (Move) > ↑Agr↑ > Murphy Merge >↓Agr↓ ↓Agr↓ & Puškar – Closest Conjunct Agreement is an Illusion &P&N ➊ head receives the gender value of only the lowest conjunct (59). As a result, the &P node bears [gender:!] the features of only the second conjunct. (58) Merge: ′ (58) in targeting NP2, because was. .deactivated goal after the& first NP2 Agree cycle (i.e. its (19) [TP &P and [PrtP ParticipleNP1 . [&Pnumber asNP1 uϕ: gender gender ]]] uninterpretable gender feature was deleted after Match, unlike the number feature of the &P, which is interpretable, and therefore not deleted after Match). subject position, which results in the LCA pattern. the Agree operation targetting the first conjunct ( ↑Agr↑) will can>target, it does not find a goal (57) and thus applies vacuously. The next operation (Move) >conjunct, ↑Agr↑operation > Merge ↓Agr↓ &P N Step 2: If the probe has an EPP feature, pied-piping of the subject is required. Valuators undergo (19) [TP [PrtP Participleuϕ: . . . [&Pnumber NP1 gender & NP2gender ]]] pied-piping, and here pied-piping of the subject fails due to ambiguity of the target for movement (either &P or NP1 can be moved as Serbo-Croatian allows for violations of Coordinate Structure Constraint the due author) and of they are assumed to count Step 3: To according prevent a to crash to lack valuation, another cycleasofequidistant. Agree is instantiated, resulting uϕ: all dress.fpl and all suit.npl ‘All dresses and all14 suits were sold yesterday.’ Murphy & Puškar – Closest Conjunct Agreement is an Illusion PrtP yesterday are sell.prt.npl *Juče su prodata haljine i sold sva yesterday. odela].[&P (55) *Juče su prodata sve haljine i sva odela]. &P sveand ‘All [dresses all suits were ’ yesterday are sell.prt.npl all dress.fpl and all suit.npl yesterday are sell.prt.npl all isdress.fpl andAgreement all suit.npl The central claim of this paper is that the nature of ‘closest’ in Closest Conjunct ‘All dresses and all suits were sold yesterday.’ entirely illusory. What we in fact have in the case of LCA, for example, is actually agreement 13 2 26 conjunct 26 when the phrase is in preverbal positio is entirely ungrammatical if the &Paccessible is postverbal.within the • Idea: when Itobject phi-features are not (repeated below) that LCA is only acceptable when the conjunct phrase is in preverbal position. &P Juče su prodata [&P sva odela i sve haljine]. Yesterday are sell.prt.npl all suits.npl and all dresses.fpl ‘All suits and all dresses were sold yesterday.’ TP 2 subject/object asymmetry idea: linearization is post-syntactic ➊ V &P ➊ If Move does not apply, thereby leaving the &P in ′its postverbal base position, then ↑Agr↑ will If Move apply, thereby leaving the &P in its postverbal base position, then ↑Agr↑ will & doesbynotMove). probe upwards butNP not find a goal (i.e. it will be counterfed Following our assumptions probe upwards but not find a goal (i.e. it will be counterfed by Move). Following our assumptions about the ϕ-probe on T, the derivation crashes as soon as T cannot find a goal. (61) F > ↓Agr↓: ↑Agr↑dresses > (Merge) TP 16about the ϕ-probe on T, the derivation crashes as soon as T cannot find a goal. & (61) [gender: !] NP> (Merge) > ↓Agr↓: ↑Agr↑ TP EVALUATING PUSKAR & MURPHY (2015) that regardless of adjectival agreement, CCA on the verb is still possible, as shown in (7-8) where two to the verbal probe as well and necessarily trigger feminine gender agreement in (7-8), contrary to fact. distinct probes end up with different agreement. Theories of post-syntactic CCA do not face this problem as both adjectival and verbal agreement could look for the linearly closest goal, which is the first conjunct for the adjective and the (7) [Ene na drugih ležeče [ žage in kladiva]] so bila umazana. last for the verb. This argument against syntactic theories of CCA is similar to the one presented by one(9)on other Marušič lyingF.PL hammer dirty F.PL N.PL AUX wereN.PL examples like ((17) from et al. saw 2008), whereand two verbal probes on opposite sides of theNEU otherfeaturally lying sawsdifferent and hammers were which dirty.' is in both cases agreement with (Slovenian) subject end'On up each realizing agreement, the (8) [Jedne na drugima ležeće [ žage i kladiva]] su bila prljava. closest conjunct. Whatever syntactic mechanism one considers, only one set of features should be one on other lying saw and hammer AUX were dirty F.PL F.PL N.PL N.PL NEU visible to the verbal probes, which should both realize the same agreement. 'On each other lying saws and hammers were dirty.' (BCS) (9) Včeraj so bile [ krave in teleta ] prodana. (Slovenian) Theories of syntactic conjunct agreement predict that given the structure in (5b), the entire DP should yesterday aux beenF.PL [ cowF.PL and calfN.PL ] soldN.PL also carry feminine because the inner ConjP carries them (as in Puškar & ‘Yesterday cows andgender calves features––either were sold.’ Murphy 2015) or else because the derivation resulted in feminine features being copied to the (Bošković 2009). Regardless of the derivation, theagreement, subject's gender should be visible The adjective same logical argument comes from Dutch complementizer where features the C agrees with thesingular verbal conjunct, probe as well feminine gender agreement in (7-8), contrary to fact. only to one whileand thenecessarily lower verb trigger agrees with the whole ConjP: Theories of post-syntactic CCA do not face this problem as both adjectival and verbal (10) agreement Ich dink de-slook for [ the toow en closest Marie]goal, which kump. is the first conjunct for the (Dutch) could linearly adjective and the I for think that-This youSG and Marie comePL of CCA is similar to the one presented by last the verb. against syntactic theories 2SG argument ‘I think that Marie come.’et al. 2008), where(Haegeman van Koppen 2012) sides of the examples likeyou (9) and ((17) fromwill Marušič two verbal&probes on opposite subject end up realizing featurally different agreement, which is in both cases agreement with the In sum, closest-conjunct agreement cannot be the result one of computation purelyone within thefeatures ConjP and closest conjunct. Whatever syntactic mechanism considers, only set of should be agreement interfacing with the ConjP level,the as same such agreement. Probes can potentially access visible Probes to the verbal probes,only which should both realize individual conjuncts within the ConjP, in a way crucially sensitive to postsyntactically-determined linear(9) order.Včeraj so bile [ krave in teleta ] prodana. (Slovenian) yesterday aux beenF.PL [ cowF.PL and calfN.PL ] soldN.PL Aljović, N.‘Yesterday & M. Begović. 2015. Morpho-Syntactic Aspects of First Conjunct Agreement. Paper cows and calves were sold.’ presented at AAB conference Zadar, Croatia. Aoun, J., E. Benmamoun & D. Sportiche. 1994. Agreement, word order,argument and conjunction some varieties of Arabic. LIagreement, 25:195–220.where Bhatt,theR.C&agrees M. with The same logical comes in from Dutch complementizer Walkow. 2013. Locating agreement in grammar: An argument from agreement in conjunctions. NLLT only one singular conjunct, while the lower verb agrees with the whole ConjP: 31:951–1013. Bošković, Ž. 2009. Unifying first and last conjunct agreement. NLLT 27:455-496. Haegeman, L. & M. Van Koppen. 2012. Complementizer agreement and the relation between Co and (10) Ich dink de-s [ toow en Marie] kump. (Dutch) To. LI 43.3: 441-454. Marušič, F., A. Nevins, & A. Saksida. 2007. Linear Agreement in Slovene I think that- al. (eds) you Marie come SG and Conjuncts. In R. Compton et 2SG FASL 15. Ann Arbor: MichiganPLSlavic Publ. 210-227. Marušič, ‘I think that you and Marie will come.’ (Haegeman & van Koppen 2012) F., A. Nevins, & B. Badecker. 2015. The Grammars of Conjunction Agreement in Slovenian. Syntax 18.1:39-77. Munn, A. 1999. First conjunct agreement: Against a clausal analysis. LI 30:in643 – 683. together lying.N [invites.N and adverts.F ]] aux.pl landed.F trash In sum, agreement cannot be the resultis of purely within the ConjP and Puškar, Z. &closest-conjunct A. Murphy. 2015. Closest conjunct agreement an computation illusion. Ms. University of Leipzig. agreement Probes interfacing only with the ConjP level, as such Probes can potentially access individual conjuncts within the ConjP, in a way crucially sensitive to postsyntactically-determined linear order. SANDWICHED AGREEMENT When agreement can be with different parts of &P Complementizer shows CCA; main verb shows resolved agreement • Correctly DCA Rules in Preverbal HCA & Rules out Postverbal Leftward participle shows CCA with NP1; Rightward participle shows CCA with NP2 • Even rules out impossibility of Medial Conjunct Agreement in 3-conjunct coordinations • Disadvantage: as all the action is internal to &P, faces difficulty when different agreement targets pick different parts of the conjunction… 17 EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN: SANDWICHING & DEPENDENT VARIABLES • PARTICIP1 [Skupaj ležeča [ vabila in reklame ]] so [ pristale v smeteh DP-internal adjective shows CCA with NP1; participle shows CCA with NP2 Such challenge models in which Aljović, N.examples & M. Begović. 2015. Morpho-Syntactic Aspects of First Conjunct Agreement. Paper presented at AAB conference Zadar, Croatia. Aoun, J., E. Benmamoun & D. Sportiche. 1994. all CCA is computed internally to the &P Bhatt, R. & M. Agreement, word order, and conjunction in some varieties of Arabic. LI 25:195–220. Walkow. 2013. Locating agreement in grammar: An argument from agreement in conjunctions. NLLT 31:951–1013. Bošković, Ž. 2009. Unifying first and last conjunct agreement. NLLT 27:455-496. Haegeman, L. & M. Van Koppen. 2012. Complementizer agreement and the relation between Co and To. LI 43.3: 441-454. Marušič, F., A. Nevins, & A. Saksida. 2007. Linear Agreement in Slovene Conjuncts. In R. Compton et al. (eds) FASL 15. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publ. 210-227. Marušič, F., A. Nevins, & B. Badecker. 2015. The Grammars of Conjunction Agreement in Slovenian. Syntax 18.1:39-77. Munn, A. 1999. First conjunct agreement: Against a clausal analysis. LI 30: 643 – 683. Puškar, Z. & A. Murphy. 2015. Closest conjunct agreement is an illusion. Ms. University of Leipzig. 18 RESULTS: SANDWICHING OK, AND SO IS DOUBLE HCA [C1 & C2] PARTICIP2 • Split Agreement: Participle 1 agrees with C1 and Participle 2 AgrF FN AgrN AgrF FN AgrF agrees with C2 * • Double HCA: Both participles agree with C1 • Double LCA: Both participles agree with C2 Split Agreement 19 Double HCA 20 AgrF NF AgrF Double LCA THIS LATTER ASYMMETRY IS EASY FOR MARUSIC ET. AL • Agree-Copy After • Agree-Copy • Lack Linearization Yields Split Agreement Before Linearization Yields Double HCA of Agree-Copy Yields Double Default • There is no way in our theory to get Double DCA PURELY SYNTACTIC THEORIES FOUNDER ON SANDWICHING • Split agreement is already a problem necessitating revisions • But even given those, there is no obvious syntactic way to rule in Double HCA while ruling out Double DCA • Feature deactivation (with multiple cycles of Agree) would help rule in Double HCA, but would then rule out Double Default 21 22 THREE FUTURE EMPIRICAL PATHS WE’LL INVESTIGATE OVERALL CONCLUSIONS • The Marusic et al 2015 model predicts masculine agreement to be freely available in split agreement cases (e.g. CCA on one side and default on the other). This is worth testing; it may be that we overgenerate. • We’ve shown two ways of sandwiching; are there different results for the DP-internal adjective cases? Is concord inherently different (cf. Norris 2014) • Slovenian already has more CCA than BCS without sandwiching; we should test the relative amount of double HCA vs split agreement in BCS 23 • Closest-conjunct agreement is the result of external Probes that can access individual parts of the ConjP • We’ve proposed three (and only three) strategies, based on Agree-Copy: No Agree-Copy yields default, prelinearization Agree-Copy yields HCA; postlinearization Agree-Copy yields CCA • The real kicker comes with sandwiched agreement, which vindicates the possibility of double CCA (different results on each probe) and double HCA, which are not easily derivable in purely syntactic approaches 24 THANK YOU! SELECTED REFERENCES • Marušič, Franc, Andrew Nevins & Bill Badecker (2015): ‘The Grammars of Conjunction Agreement in Slovenian’, Syntax 18(1), 39–77. • Bhatt, Rajesh & Martin. Walkow (2013): ‘Locating agreement in grammar: an argument from agreement in conjunctions’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 31(4), 951–1013. • Bošković, Željko. (2009): ‘Unifying first and last conjunct agreement’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 27(3), 455–496. • Puskar, Z. & Murphy, A. (2015). Closest Conjunct Agreement is an Illusion. Ms., Universität Leipzig. • Norris, Mark (2014). A theory of nominal concord. Phd, UCSC. • Haegeman, L. & M. van Koppen. Complementizer agreement and the relation between Co and To. LI 43.3: 441-454. 25 27 !! THE!EMSS!Team! ! 26 28 !
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz