ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Department of Philosophy - University of Padua [email protected] Abstract: Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples, is a presentation of the traditional accounts and examples of reasoning by composition and by division and serves as background information for the Finocchiaro-Woods exchange. The contribution by Adelino Cattani, is a presentation of the many accounts of composition-division fallacy that, being by and large confused and confusing at the conceptual level, and trivial and unreal at the illustrative-empirical level, generate the exchange between Maurice Finocchiaro and John Woods. The debate between the two distinguished scholars exemplifies a case of dialogue-debate, conforming to Eris’ manifesto, whose purpose is to reflect on theory of argumentation and on practice of debate and to promote confrontation of conflicting contributions on argumentation and debate. ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ «Space is nothing but a relation. For, in the first place, any space must consists of parts: and if parts are not spaces, the whole is not space.» (F.H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, Allen and Unwin, London, 18972, p. 37) 1. Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples To judge is, in the scholastic definition, to affirm or deny, to join or split, to unite or separate, i.e. an operation of composition or division. Therefore, it is of capital importance to know when to join and when to separate notions and parts. The part-whole relation can generate an universal inferential «locus communis», that is a fundamental argumentative scheme: part and whole are used as warrants, of remarkable theoretical and empirical significance, in a argument in order to provide the inference from premises to conclusion, from reasons to claim. All deductive arguments presuppose the rule that what is said of all is said of each. It works from a whole to the parts. Inductive argument is the reverse process of arriving at a whole starting from the parts. But the part/whole relation originates other so-called «partwhole arguments» and we find it also in the rhetorical domain, in connection with some special fallacies. There are some interesting mistakes in reasoning having to do with parts (fragments, individuals, persons, members) and whole (set, class, collection, body, group). Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 2 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] Composition and division are the names of the special fallacies regarding the combination and the separation of parts. The one is the flip side of the other. In this paper I will focus on this kind of flaw in an argument. Starting from the whole-parts relation, we may follow two opposite directions of reasoning: reasoning from parts to whole or reasoning from whole to parts. That is to say, we may proceed by: 1. Inclusion of the parts in the whole 2. Division of the whole into its parts Naturally, the whole/parts interaction may be a physical interaction, or a logical connection or a psychological one. This constitutes a first problem in the process of transition from whole to parts and from parts to whole. Furthermore, a whole is either a mere collection of elements or an organised arrangement of parts: a pile of books or a classified library, a mass of bricks or a house. This constitutes another problem. It is not at all simple to answer the question: «If all parts have the property x, does the whole has x too?». As Woods and Walton, two notable scholars of fallacies, say, for the great majority of properties and aggregates, the composibility or divisibility of the properties with respect to the aggregate cannot be determined abstractly; one needs (1) an interpretation of properties and of aggregate; (2) a knowledge of the world; and (3) a tolerable nose for metaphysical taxonomy (Woods and Walton, 1989). We need to compose/decompose at least in three situations: 1. In order to define. 2. In order to create figures of speech by means of a variety of expressions. 3. In order to organise and manipulate an argument. We will explain briefly every point. 1. Composition and division in definition. A good definition requires a good division, namely the setting out of all the different parts of a subject. Further, it is necessary to split complex matters in some way if we want to analyse them. If one says «There are three things to consider in order to analyse this matter: first is… second is … and finally…» this appears as a natural and perfectly acceptable division. But no division is naturally given and no division has to be accepted as inevitable. On the contrary, some cultural prospect or opinion lies behind every division. There are three rules of a good division. First, it should be based on the same criterion (have a common ground or root or basis); second, it should be complete; and, third, its parts should be mutually exclusive, that is not crossing or overlapping. If a dichotomy is supposed to be exhaustive and exclusive when in fact it is not, this generates a so-called “black and white” fallacy. Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 3 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] 2. Composition and division in rhetorical figures. Composition of parts and division of a whole can be used as a trope. The substitution of a part for a whole generates a common form of synecdoche, a trope in which the part stands for the whole, as in «sail » for «ship», or in «A hungry stomach has no ears». Decomposition is a condition for mastering our language and a means for enriching our variety and variations of style. 3. Composition and division in argumentative inference. Composition and division, as we will see, can be used also as an organising principle for an argument. The connection between parts and whole is used as an argumentative tool in many ways. One can deduce something about parts on the basis of their membership in a whole, or one can generalise about a whole on the basis of the qualities of the parts. Following Aristotle (Rhetoric 1401 a 25), one type of reasoning consists in combining what was divided, and another in dividing what was united. Here are some examples offered by Aristotle. «One who knows the letters knows the whole word, since the word is the same thing as the letters which compose it» (Rhetoric, 1401 a 28). If it were so, a busy believer could conceive a convenient formula for saying his prayer: it would suffice to recite every day in the morning the alphabet and leave to God the task of combining the letters in order to construct the prayer. «Two and three are five. Two and three are even and odd. Therefore, five is even and odd.» (Example of division drawn from Sophistical Refutations, 116 a 33) Aristotle deals with composition and division in two places, in Sophistical Refutations, 166 a 22-37 and in Rhetoric, 1401 a 25-35. As an example of an illegitimate reasoning, Aristotle gives the following. «I say that a man can walk while sitting, because that old man sitting over there can walk. Therefore he can both walk and sit at the same time.» This sentence is true if it means that a sitting man is able to walk (in the divided, potential sense). The assertion is false if it means that a man can walk while sitting (in the combined, actual sense). In addition, here is another similar example: Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 4 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] «A man can write while not writing.» (He maintains the power of writing even if he is not writing now.) Chaïm Perelman and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca claim that the inclusion relation (the inclusion of the parts in the whole and the division of the whole into its parts) is a quasilogical argumentative scheme, that is similar in form to mathematical or formal argument (like the contradiction, the tautology, the argument of reciprocity, the argument by transitivity, the argument by comparison), and therefore particularly persuasive, due to their logical validity. They deal with this type of argument in three sections: the section § 55 entitled «Inclusion of the parts in the whole», § 56 entitled «Division of the whole into parts», and section § 73 entitled «The group and its members». As we will see in the section «Group/member interaction», the disreputable or worthy action of an individual member of a group reflects on the group as a whole and vice versa. The authors of The New Rhetoric offer the following example, taken from John Locke: «For whatsoever is not lawful for the whole Church cannot by any ecclesiastic right become lawful to any of its members». William Rowe (1962, p. 92) asserts that not all inferences having the form «All parts of T have x. Therefore, T has x» are fallacious. Sometimes they are fallacious, sometimes are valid or sound, but there exists no formal or general way of sorting the acceptable from the unacceptable cases. There are properties that are universalizable: the lawn is in flower because daisies and pansies are in flower. Other qualities of the parts are not automatically transferable to the whole and vice versa. For example, when we are dealing with relative or cumulative properties: light or heavy, simple or complex, precious or worthless. Examples of these untransferable properties spring readily in mind: a cocktail is different from its components; not all the details of a nice picture are necessarily nice; a group of athletes may play together effectively without being outstanding individual players. On the contrary, even fine athletes may play poorly together. 2. Part-whole general «loci» We find two general and contrasting principles governing the whole-part relation. 1. The first affirms that what is true of the whole is true of the parts and vice versa. In other terms, the same reason or reasoning applies to the whole and to the parts. In Latin sentence: Eadem est ratio totius et partium. «All the parts of this machine are made of iron. Therefore, this machine is made of iron.» Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 5 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] Nothing to object. It is a valid form of composition. The argument presupposes the rule that whatever is predicated of every part of a whole may be predicated of the whole. A similar, but more problematic Aristotelian instance, is: «If a double portion of a certain thing is harmful to health, then a single portion must not be called wholesome, since it is absurd that two good things should make one bad thing.» (Rhetorica, 1401 a 29) The underlying general «locus» is: «It is not possible that if one is good, two are bad.» Consequently, «if two portions are harmful, also one portion is harmful; if one portion is wholesome, two portions cannot be harmful.» 2. The second principle takes the opposite direction and says that a whole is greater than or different from the sum of its parts. Something might be true of the whole without being true of the parts and vice versa. A work of art may be very different from the sum of all its details. It is imaginable that a medley of ugly things may turn out to be very lovely. Or a society may be a little different from the sum of its members: as the American poet and humorist, Keith Preston, said, «we have sometimes been tempted to define democracy as an institution in which the whole is equal to the scum of all the parts». If we transfer this second principle to the realm of reasoning, we can say that, the whole argument is not equal to the sum of its premises or its sub-arguments. This serves also as a response to the classical criticism of the vacuity of syllogism. These two principles are often misunderstood or applied when they shouldn’t. As an instance of this misapplication, we offer the following examples: «Every part of this aircraft is light. Therefore, the whole aircraft is light.» Invalid composition. But it does not seem to cause serious confusion in the common affairs of life. The exact reverse of the fallacy of composition is the fallacy of division, which consists in transferring to the parts the characteristics of the whole. The fallacy of division is committed when it is argued that because the whole has a characteristic, the parts has this characteristic too. For division, the same considerations and principles hold. «Water is one of the lightest substances, for it is composed of the lightest substances, hydrogen, which is combined with oxygen.» (Sprangler, 1986, p. 130) Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 6 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] If we accept this reasoning, we fall into the fallacy of division. For example: «The machine is heavy. Therefore all the parts of he machine are heavy.» Sorry! It’s clearly a faulty argument. That the whole item weights more than one kilo does not implies that every individual component will weight more than one kilo. 3. All together or one at a time? We have to distinguish between every and all taken distributively or collectively. The difference between distributive and collective is exemplified by the notions of human nature and of human race. Human nature is a distributive notion (it is entire in every man taken singularly); human race, on the contrary, is a collective notion. Consider: «A Ferrari uses more gasoline than a small car. Therefore, all Ferrari use more gasoline than all small cars.» It is true that singularly one Ferrari use more gasoline than a small car, but, because there are many more utility cars than Ferrari circulating, it is obviously false that Ferrari all together use more gasoline than all other small cars. There are situations where a characteristic cannot be legitimately transferred from parts to whole or vice versa. But the connection between «the soldiers of the regiment are strong» and «the regiment is strong» is not totally ineffective. The premise seems a good and necessary (but not sufficient) reason for the conclusion. «Every animal is rational or irrational. But not every animal is rational. Therefore, every animal is irrational.» (Peter of Spain, Summulae Logicales, 27 va 20) Or consider the following, only a little less silly mistake: «All of our employees get eight hours of sleep, as well work for eight hours. Therefore we are proud of the fact that our employees can sleep and work at the same time.» The fallacy of composition has occurred. «This fallacious combination misconstrues the fact that two opposing things may exist in combination, but only if one is potential and the other is actual.» (Sprangler, 1986, p. 130) «Each brick is three inches high, thus the brick wall is three inches high.» Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 7 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] «Since the life expectancy of the inhabitants is 75 years, the city can be expected to perish after about 75 years.» «Conventional bombs did more damage in World War II than a nuclear bombs. Thus, a conventional bomb is more dangerous than nuclear bomb.» (Example of faulty division, drawn from Irving Copi) «All items in this stand cost € 9,90.» (If «all» is used collectively, take all of them. It is an unrepeatable deal! If it is used distributively, think twice before you buy.) 4. Group/members interaction. Our concept of the group influences our concept of the individual belonging to the group and vice versa. The relation between individual and group is considered analogous to the relation existing between acts and person (Perelman e Olbrechts-Tyteca, § 73). But «great care is called for in any argument from a part to a collective group, from one human person to his community; and still greater care when the argument is in a reverse direction, above all in questions of social philosophy» (Gilby, 1949, p. 76). We know that an individual person behaves differently if he/she is alone or included in a group: this phenomenon is testified by mob psychology researches, but well known by instigators and demagogues too. So the questions of collective and distributive categories are not only affairs of logic but also of sociology. As is noted by Thomas Gilby, «there is always something about the whole that does not belong to the parts; in the composition another entity is produced, over and above the components, of a character different, and sometimes less admirable: the voice of the mob, the yell of the crowd, and even public policy, these are less than human. When real and individual personality is merged into a pack, take care» (Gilby, 1949, p. 70). The individual and the group interact. Interaction means that a membership influences our concept of the members and our concept of the members influences our concept of the group to which a person belongs. A high estimation of the qualities possessed by the group influences our opinion of the qualities possessed by its members. Or, in order to disqualify the entire group, we may stress the errors of individual members. Example of this simple argumentative scheme, aiming to guarantee transition from the whole to its parts, is: «N is member of a prestigious group. Therefore N is prestigious.» Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 8 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] No reasoning of this type should obviously be accepted without close scrutiny of the contents, in particular of the acceptability of substitution of a part for a whole. Consider the following assertion of a child: «My father is working at a very important corporation.» (He is the garbage man of the corporation) «The Logic Club of Padua is known as an intelligent association. Therefore, Leo, a member of the Club, is intelligent» (A silly induction to be sure. One is conferring upon an individual some of the skill attached to the group or class that the individual belongs to). «Too stupid, again», you say. In order to avoid this type of fallacy of division one should carefully examine if: 1. The composition or division are allowable, given the nature of the properties considered: perhaps one is incorrectly transferring to the whole its members’ qualities or the quality of whole to its members. (Unfortunately, as we have said, for this transition there is no formal or general rule. The logical rules are not enough and we need some more pragmatic, substantial rules of relevance concerning the extensibility of our data). 2. There is an equivocation on collective and distributive sense of words, i.e. if something that is true only in a separate sense is taken in a combined sense or if «all» is taken in the sense of «all together» in one occurrence and in the sense of «each individual» in another one. This is the reason why a committee whose members are all resolute and firmly determined may be not at all resolute and determined in his final decision. The intuitive idea that the collective behaviours correspond to the individual ones is denied by Bernard Mandeville in his Fable of the Bees, about private vices and public virtues. 5. Part/whole fallacies If we make incorrect inferences from properties of a whole to properties of its parts, and from properties of parts to properties of the whole of which they are parts, special forms of wrong reasoning occur, called fallacy of composition or fallacy of division. These fallacies require naturally an analysis in terms of part-whole relation. 5.1. Verbal composition/division Composition and division are, in the first place, forms of discursive connection and separation, operations carried out in the act of speaking. Sometimes the fallacy originates from the linguistic ambiguity of the term «all», meaning either «every singular part» or «the whole taken together». In order to obviate this confusion, the rigorous languages, such as Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 9 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] Latin, had a collective «tota» and a distributive «omnia», making a grammatical distinction between the collective entity and the individuals within it. Grammatical and structural identity is not a guarantee of soundness, since not all properties are subject to generalisation. The risk is to slip on a banana skin of terms used with different meanings. There is a story to the effect that, addressing a women audience, a preacher pointed out that they were «all destined to become wives of some good man». Either he was a strong supporter of polygamy or he meant «each» of them. Care is needed in distinguishing between terms used in a collective or distributive sense. A term is used distributively if it says something about each and every member of the group; a term is used collectively in order to say something about the group as such. We know that the whole is sometime different from the sum of its composing parts. If it were otherwise, we could not use the salt in our food, considering that both chlorine and sodium are poisonous. In addition, cartoons would not move on the movie screen. To assert that the perception of a moving picture on the screen is an illusion because a film consists of many motionless frames is an example of a wrong composition. «All the wise men of Greece are seven. Solon and Periander are wise men of Greece. Therefore Solon and Periander are seven.» A classical instance of division, an extreme example, caricature of the real ones for sake of clearness, due to Thomas Blundeville (Blundeville, 1599, p. 191). «The apostles are twelve. Paul is an apostle. Paul is twelve.» The argument is, in its formal structure, similar to the following «The apostles are saints. Paul is an apostle. Paul is saint.» (“Twelve” refers to all-together, “saints” to each and every). A valid and disambiguating argument, where there is no confusion and no division, could be: «The apostles as a group are twelve in number. Paul is one of the apostles. Paul is one of the twelve apostles.» Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 10 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] 5.2. Non-verbal composition/division The strong principle of composition asserts that what is true of each part of a whole is also true of the whole itself. «Each member of the team is married; therefore the team also has a wife». «Too stupid». «Too artificial», you say. It is hard to image that anyone would be convinced by this argument. But not all instances of this kind of fallacy are so obvious. There are less silly and more sophisticated situations. «No jury verdict is safe, as every juryman is liable to error.» It is true that each and every individual juryman may err, but this does not means that any whole jury will err (Evans e Palmer, 19862, p. 247). This quality of unreliability is true of a group distributively but not collectively. In order to see that the argument is invalid, it is sufficient to inspect the following reasoning having a similar form: «Every side of a square is a straight line. Therefore a square is a straight line.» (Black, 19522, p. 232) «Everybody in the city pays his debt. Therefore you can be sure that the city will pay its debts.» (Black, 19522, p. 232) Similarly and conversely, a strong principle of division asserts that what holds true for a set as a whole holds true for each member of the set. «Because the brain is capable of consciousness, each neural cell in the brain must be capable of consciousness.» (Faulty brain process and faulty division.) You might just as well try: «Italy is a catholic country. Thus, each Italian is catholic.» Here are some more examples of the fallacy, generally found in the literature. «The brick wall is six feet tall. Thus, the bricks in the wall are six feet tall.» «Germany is a rich country. Thus, each German is rich.» Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 11 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] «This must be a good team, because each of its members is an excellent athlete.» (An athletic team, like an orchestra, is not good because all the players are separately good, if they are incapable to play co-operatively. Each player’s readiness to work under a good trainer is one of the necessary conditions for the excellence of the team. The opposite line of reasoning consists in assuming that the parts of a whole must have the properties of the whole. «Since this is a good team, the members of the team must bee good players.» One very interesting context involves the relationship between partial and total truth. Why is a witness in court made to swear that he will tell «the whole truth and nothing but the truth»? Because partial truth may be a total lie. As an example of the fallacy of the half-truth, we may offer the following. «The captain was sober today.» It is left unsaid that he was sober yesterday too, the day before yesterday and always. What is said is perfectly true, but what is left unsaid is essential for the representation of the total accurate picture. «The captain was sober today» is a way for insinuating falsely something by saying something that is true: here a partial truth is not part of the total truth but of a falsehood. Lying while saying the truth is an art.1 5.3. Hasty generalisation Arguing from parts to whole and arguing from individual cases to a general case is similar to the process of generalisation. A generalisation has the following form: «A lot of A is x. It is probable, therefore, that all A are x.» This form of reasoning is supported by a weak principle of composition: «What is true of most parts of a whole is also true of the whole itself» (the converse weak principle of division affirms that what holds true for a set as a whole holds true for most members of the set). In general, the more the parts that are examined, the stronger the argument is. If the sample used is not adequate or the cases examined are not enough, we commit the fallacy of hasty generalisation. Hasty generalisation differs from composition only because Examples of sentences that are literally true, but are used as a vehicle for falsehood are examined in Cattani, A. (1995). 1 Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 12 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] the first is a prediction about individuals of a whole (from «some» to «all»), the second about whole formed by individuals (from «all parts» to «whole»). I infer that the next swan will be white on the basis that the swans I have seen in the past were all white. This is generalisation that might be too hasty. It is sound and valid only if every individual swan has the property attributed to all swans. On the contrary, it is not necessary that every part of an organisation be democratic in order for the whole organisation to be considered democratic. You may argue that an organisation is undemocratic because the executive committee is appointed by different groups rather than elected. This might be a fallacy of composition if you fail to mention that decisions of executive committee are by majority vote (Capaldi, 19722, pp. 103-104). 5.4. False dichotomy To present a whole as if naturally divided into two opposed alternatives, whereas there is at least one other possibility, generates possibly a false dichotomy. A dichotomy is false when it is supposed to be exhaustive and exclusive when in fact it is not. A dichotomy is not false if the two alternatives cover all the possibilities and the choice of one rules out the other. In order to verify the soundness of a statement having the form «it is either x or y», we should ask the following questions: 1. Is it really an either-or situation (namely a disjunction where the two things exhaust all the possibilities)? 2. Is it the only possible division? Are the choices the only ones possible? If it is so, the argument is a sound form of reasoning; if it is not so, the so-called bifurcation or “black and white” fallacy occurs. 5.5. The Gambler’s fallacy We can see in the gambler’s fallacy a variation of the fallacy of division. «Perhaps the gambler confuses the individual probability of p1 & p2…& pj (where each is equal to 0.5, but where the probability of the entire sequence is decreased as each one pi is added) with the conjunctive probability. Thus the probability of some individual pi is confused with the probability of a whole sequenced of pi’s» (Woods and Walton, 1989, p. 116). 6. Conclusions To sum up, we briefly highlight some points that we can draw from the preceding considerations. First. Composition and division (or decomposition), which are the converse one of the other, are generally classified as linguistic fallacies, characterised by a semantic or syntactic ambiguity, following Aristotle (at least the Aristotle of Sophistical Refutations), who included them into the six fallacies depending on language. But, as Walton notes, this practice is hard to explain, because the examples typically given are arguments that have to do with relationships between parts and whole of physical and non-verbal aggregates: «they Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 13 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] are more accurately and usefully seen as formalistic fallacies that have to do with inferences from parts to wholes and vice versa» (Walton, 1995, pp. 64-65). The modern conception of these fallacies is generally non-linguistic and more substantive. On that account, we may distinguish al least three different types of erroneous and simplistic reasoning concerning the whole-part relation. 1. The fallacy determined by the word «all» used equivocally. 2. The fallacy created by arguing directly from the properties of the component parts to the properties of the whole itself or vice versa. 3. The fallacy committed when one assumes that the attributes of single parts, taken distributively, hold collectively for the global whole or vice versa. Second. It seems that these types of fallacies fit more naturally into the category of the unintentional fallacies, that is the kind of wrong reasoning that occurs without any deliberate intent to mislead. Certainly, forms of composition and of division such as those we find in the literature are unusual in real life, but not absent. Usually the context makes it clear how a term should be interpreted. The fallacies of composition and division are connected with some other fallacies, namely syntactical amphiboly, faulty generalisation, gambler’s fallacy, guilt by association fallacy and accent. Further, they are sometimes connected with «category mistakes» too. Third. Since the possibilities for argumentation depend on what each participant is ready to concede, on the values he recognises, on the facts on which he indicates his agreement, we can say that any argumentation is good or bad for some audience. Most of, if not all, the traditional fallacies of informal logic may be viewed as valid arguments but with an unacceptable major premise, and therefore as unsound arguments. In the case of composition, the erroneous premise and the unsoundness consist in believing that what is true of all the parts is true of the whole, without qualifications. Fourth. We have seen that a fallacy of composition is an argument that requires the untenable premise that if all parts of a set have some quality, then the whole set will also have this quality. Erroneously attributing a property of a whole to its constituent parts or vice versa is a violation of one of the «Ten Commandments» of critical discussion elaborated by F. H. van Eemeren e R. Grootendorst, namely rule no. 8: «In his argumentation a party may only use arguments that are logically valid or capable of being validated by making explicit one or more unexpressed premises» (van Eemeren e Grootendorst, 1992, pp. 208209). Violations of this rule occur if one is confusing the properties of the parts and wholes, in two ways: - a relative or structure-dependent property of a whole is ascribed to a part of a whole Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 14 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] - a relative or structure-dependent property of a part of a whole is ascribed to the whole. In daily life we find an incredible number of unacceptable arguments. Most of them are formally valid (and therefore extremely convincing), but unsound: we have examined some examples of unsound arguments and conclusions because the major premise concerning the part/whole relation is unacceptable. Some of the examples given in the literature are so stupid that it is hard to imagine they could deceive anyone. Raymond Boudon gives more serious instances of fallacies of composition and division. There are situations where what is locally true may result globally false. Or what is true at a given time may become false on the long run. He offers two examples. The first concerning the socialeconomic domain: the introduction of machinery in industry may provoke strikes in some farms and reduce the strikes at the level of the economic system as a whole. Similarly, whereas an individual worker may get rich, workers as a whole may worsen their condition. The second drawn from epistemology: the conceptions of two rival groups of scientists may be both founded on subjective reasons, but this does not mean that in the future one of them will not prevail over the other because his reason will result objectively true (Boudon, 1986, cap. 6; Boudon, 1990, pp. 225-226). To take the words of Woods and Walton (1989, p. 117), «composition and division are indeed fallacies of some genuine importance - easy enough to commit and mischievous enough to avoid committing». Composition and decomposition remain interesting to logicians; and to epistemologists and sociologists too. And mostly to economists, because society is greater and more than just the people who live in it and vice versa. Using Finocchiaro’s words: “With regard to the fallacy of composition, the problem of how frequently it occurs is more striking than for the case of the other fallacies, because the contrast is greater and starker between the scarcity of scholarly analyses and the triviality of textbook examples on the one hand, and the widespread claims made (especially by economists) about its prevalence and importance. Thus, the empirical search for real or realistic examples is a relatively urgent task” (Finocchiaro, 2015, p. 36). References Black, M. (19522). Critical Thinking. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Blundeville, T. (1599). The Art of Logicke. Boudon, R. (1986). L’idéologié. L’origine des idées recue. Paris: Fayard. Boudon, R. (1990). L’art de se persuader des idées douteuses, fragiles ou fausses. Paris: Fayard. Capaldi, N. (19722). The Art of Deception. Buffalo and New York: Prometheus Books. Cattani, A. (1995). On implicative function of the obviousness, or “You shall not take anything in vain”. In F. van Eemeren et al. (eds.), Proceedings of the Third ISSA Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 15 ERIS Rivista internazionale di argomentazione e dibattito www.eris.unipd.edu.it [email protected] Conference on Argumentation, vol. III: Reconstruction and Application, pp. 96-101. Amsterdam: Sic Sat. Cattani A. (2011). 50 Discorsi ingannevoli. Padova: Edizioni GB. Crosswhite J. (1993) Being unreasonable: Perelman and the problem of fallacies. Argumentation, 7 (4), 385-402. Evans, D. e Palmer, H. (19862). Understanding Arguments. Cardiff: University of Wales Press. Finocchiaro M. A. (1981). Fallacies and the evaluation of reasoning. American Philosophical Quarterly. 18 (1), 13-22. Finocchiaro, M. A. (1970). The Fallacy of Composition: Guiding concepts, historical cases, and research problems. Journal of Applied Logic, 13(2), 24–43. Finocchiaro, M. A. (2005), Arguments about Arguments: Systematic, Critical, and Historical Essays in Logical Theory. New York: Cambridge University Press. Finocchiaro, M. A. (2014). Meta-argumentation: An Approach to Logic and Argumentation Theory. London: College Publications. Gilby, T. (1949). Barbara Celarent. A Description of Scholastic Dialectic. London: Longmans Green. Hamblin C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen. Kienpointner M. (1992). Alltagslogik. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog. Perelman C. and Olbrechts-Tyteca L. (1958). Traité de l’argumentation. La nouvelle rhétorique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Rowe W. L. (1962). The fallacy of composition. Mind, 71, 87-92. Sprangler, M. M. (1986). Logic. An Aristotelian Approach, Lanham-New York-London: University Press of America. van Eemeren, F. H. and Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, Communication, and Fallacies. A pragma-dialectical Perspective. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Walton, D. (1995). A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy. Tuscaloosa and London: The University of Alabama Press. Woods J. and Walton D. (1989). Fallacies. Selected Papers 1972-1982. Dordrecht: Foris. Woods, J. (2013). Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference. London: College Publications. Reasoning by composition and by division: traditional accounts and examples Adelino Cattani Eris, Vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 2-16 (2016) ISSN 2421-6747 16
© Copyright 2024 Paperzz