THE LETTER Editor Heiena Texier Editorial Board: Cormac Gallagher Jean KflcuDai Scientific Committee: Aisling Campbell, Olga Cox, Mary Cullen, Nellie Curtm, Mae\e Daly, Nlartn Daly, Mary Darby, Anne Jackson, Patricia McCarthy, Tom McGrath, 'laeve Nolan^ Gerry Sullivan, Rob Weatherill. Corresponding Editors: Marcel Czermak (France) Claude Dumezil (France) Guy Le Gaufey (France) Christiane Lacote (France) Charles Melman (France) John Muller (U.S.A.) C. Edward Robins (U.S.A.) Filip Geerardyn (Belgium) Gertrudis Van de Vijver (Belgium) Paul Verhaeghe (Belgium) Advisory Board: Yves Baumstimler, Professor of Psychopathology, Universite de Paris XHI, FRANCE. John Forrester, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge, ENGLAND. William Richardson, Professor of Philosophy, Boston College, U.S.A. Noel Walsh, Professor of Psychiatry, University College, Dublin and St. Vincent's Hospital, Dublin, IRELAND. All manuscripts, letters and other communications should be addressed to: The Editor, THE LETTER, Centre for Psychoanalytic Studies, LSB College, 6-9 Balfe Street, D ublin 2, Ireland, or fax: +353-1-6794205. THE LETTER is produced by the Centre for Psychoanalytic Studies in association with the School of Psychotherapy, St. Vincent's Hospital, Dublin 4 and the Association for Psychoanalysis and Psychotherapy in Ireland (APPI). Articles will be accepted on computer disk (see back page for details). All papers will be subject to blind-peer review. The Editor thanks The Board of Trinity College, Dublin for permission to use a reproduction from the Book of Kells. THE LETTER EDITORIAL NOTE This issue of the journal is given over to a collection of articles submitted by the various authors as a tribute to Cormac Gallagher on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday. This is the fourteenth issue since the inaugural conference of the European Foundation for Psychoanalysis which was held in Dublin, the left-overs of which were to constitute the ingredients of the Irish Stew we are still consuming as our basic diet in THE LETTER. It w ill soon become apparent to the reader that the theme of that conference, The Unconscious and Language(s), finds itself echoed in the format of this birthday present, -literally. Admittedly, this is a strange sort of a gift since one is not usually obliged to share one's birthday treats with all and sundry. However, since the man himself has set the trend by graciously sharing his many gifts with whoever showed an interest in psychoanalysis, we can excuse ourselves by saying he has only himself to blame. Perhaps amends can be made if, in addition, we send him something special for himself, something from the heart of psychoanalysis, -a wish! Long life and nappiness! From the Editorial Board (Jean Kilcullen, Rik Loose, Helen Sheehan and Helena Texier) BY WAY OF AN INTRODUCTION Mary Darby and Noel Walsh It is an honour to introduce this issue of The Letter and particularly to celebrate with Dr. Cormac Gallagher on the occasion of his Sixtieth Birthday. We owe much to Cormac for the years of service and scholarship that he has dedicated to our Department of Psychiatry at St. Vincent's Hospital. He has instructed us in the works of Sigmund Freud and Jacques Lacan, introduced us to eminent European psychoanalysts and broadened the academic horizons of our medical students and psychiatric trainees. With his energy and commitment, he encouraged us to establish the School of Psychotherapy to which he has brought great distinction in his role as Director. The Department of Psychiatry at St. Vincent,s was established in 1971 when Noel Walsh returned to Ireland from Montreal where he had trained in psychiatry at McGill University and was supervised by the eminent psychoanalyst Dr. Karl Stem. This background in psychiatry and psychoanalysis influenced the therapy and the teaching in the new psychiatric unit which welcomed Cormac when he joined the hospital staff as Senior Clinical psychologist in 1975. He maintained his links with psychoanalysis in Paris, began his translations of the work of Jacques Lacan and generously shared his experience with medical and nursing staff through reading groups and supervision. In 1974 Noel Walsh became Professor of Clinical Psychiatry at University College Dublin and St. Vincent's and a larger in-patient unit was opened in 1977. Doctors, nurses, social workers, psychologists and counsellors were attending case conference and academic sessions and in the early 1980s discussions began regarding the establishment of more formal academic training programmes. In 1982, after he was awarded a PhD from University of Paris VII, Cormac drew up a discussion document recommending the introduction of a training course in psychoanalytic psychotherapy at St. Vincent's. We worked with the help of Therese Brady of UCD, Michael Fitzgerald of the Eastern Health Board and Conal Larkin of St. John of Gods's Hospital in drafting the syllabus for this first course. Niall Crowley, Chairman of Allied Irish Banks with Ivor Kenny and Liam Connellan of the business community assisted us in raising funds to establish the School of Psychotherapy. With a strong academic programme supported by a firm clinical base we approached UCD with a proposal for a Masters' Degree in Psychoanalytic Psychotherapy which was enthusiastically welcomed by the President, Dr. Tom Murphy and accepted by the Medical Faculty. The first intake of students was in 1984. We were particularly pleased when the Departments of Psychology and Social Science later offered their Master's degrees to our graduates. Cormac's commitment to the teaching of psychoanalytic psychotherapy was also the catalyst that brought together the Institute of Group Analysis London and the School of Psychotherapy in a joint venture introducing a training programme for the Diploma in Group Analysis which began in 1986. In 1993 we were honoured to be invited by Cormac and by Jean Kilcullen to assist in the establishment of the Centre for Psychoanalytic Studies at LSB College and to be involved in the development of their innovative BA in Psychoanalytic Studies. From the early reading groups in the Department of Psychiatry at St. Vincent's to the current wealth of teaching programmes, Cormac has played a significant role in the training of a large number of Irish psychiatrists, psychologists, psychoanalysts and psychotherapists, teachers and supervisors. Many retain their links with him through their work, their research and their membership of the Association for Psychoanalysis and Psychotherapy in Ireland. Attendance at the annual Congresses and the standard of scholarship demonstrated in the presentations is ample testament to his teaching and influence as is "The Letter" which was conceived at the first congress of the European Foundation for Psychoanalysis held at St. Vincent's at the invitation of Cormac who is a founder member. We wish to acknowledge our debt to Cormac for the service he has given to the Department of Psychiatry at St. Vincent's. We have all benefited from his administrative skills and academic excellence and his influence has fostered the highest standards of patient care. We thank him for his loyalty and friendship and join with all our colleagues in saying 'Happy Birthday Cormac'! Address for correspondence: St. Vincent's Hospital Elm Park Dublin 4 THE LETTER TABLE OF CONTENTS W illiam J. Richardson Lacan for Beginners 1 W illiam J. Richardson The Subject of Ethics 3 Marcel Czermak Peut-on Parler de Psychose Sociale? 27 Helen Sheehan The Follower 39 Claude Dumezil Symptome, Ethique et Desir D'Analyste 62 Rik Loose A Review of Freud's Early Remarks on Addiction: From an Ideal to Masturbation 65 Trauma and Hysteria Within Freud and Lacan 87 Paul Verhaeghe Tom McGrath Psychology and Psychoanalysis -A Scientific Paradigm 106 Lecture Raisonn6e et Critique des CEuvres de Freud et de Lacan 120 Lacan and Dali -An Anamorphic Encounter? 134 Christiane Lacote Une Torpeur Ordinaire Ib l Helena Texier We Can Remember It For You Wholesale 165 Guy Le Gaufey The Tight-Rope Walkers 182 Charles Melman Olga Cox Cameron LACAN FOR BEGINNERS October 1, 1998. Dear Cormac, It is time for celebration, and I have been invited to take part. I do so with pleasure and with embarrassment: pleasure, because it is indeed gratifying to look back over the years and realise how much you have achieved for the cause of Psychoanalysis—not only in Ireland but for us Anglo-Saxons in America,, toosince you definitively left Paris for home; embarrassing; because I have nothing to offer by way of gift at the present time that is sophisticated enough to merit publication in a professional review of quality such as The Letter. But the most recent issue contained an Appendix of sorts (containing two short contributions of your own), entitled Lacan for Beginners. When I saw it, I said immediately 'That's for me'. For my most recent endeavour was an attempt to respond appropriately to an invitation from the 'Division for Psychoanalysis' of the American Psychological Association to deliver the keynote address at its Annual Convention, dedicated to the theme, 'The Ethics of Psychoanalysis.' Specifically, I was asked to present as cogently as possible a philosophical understanding of what ethics is. All my psychologist friends urged me to be as simple and straightforward as possible, proceeding on thè supposition that many professional psychologists in America could have gone through their entire educational process without any experience of philosophy, let alone formal exposure to ethics. The presentation should be a cram course in Phil 101 that would bring everyone up to speed in forty minutes. That is how the following piece came about: an effort to make acceptable sense to a group of highly educated and experienced people material that, when all was said and done, remained on a beginner's level. This is all I have to offer as contribution to the party and I am afraid it will have to suffice. Yet there is something to be said for beginnings. Husserl is reported to have said aver and over in effect, 'we are always only beginners' - one way of understanding, I suppose, Eliot's 'in my end is my beginning\ In any 1 case, let the piece, such as it is, serve to ivish you well, in the hope that another birthday be not the sign of years gone by but of a fresh beginning ~ beginning of what still remains in advent of power, and light and peace. Sincerely, William ]. Richardson THE SUBJECT OF ETHICS William J. Richardson It was the time of the Lie. The following reflection was born in the moment when an entire nation held its breath in anticipation of its President testifying before a Grand Jury about an alleged denied of an alleged sexual liaison with a White house intern in a pre-trial deposition concerning another alleged sexual liaison (also denied), and allegedly encouraging the intern in question to lie about it. To ask about the subject of ethics under these circumstances was to ask about what was most deeply at stake in the whole unhappy brouhaha. Arthur Schlessinger, Jr., had claimed in an Op Ed piece in the New York Times1 that 'every gentleman lies about his sex life. Only a cad would tell the truth.' It may be so, but this is not an ethical issue - it is a sociological one. On August 14* the national press reported that the President's advisors were designing a strategy by which he would admit the liaison but deny that he had encouraged the intern to lie about it. Shrewd enough, perhaps, but this was not an ethical issue. It was a political issue, perhaps, or at most a legal issue, but had nothing to do with ethics. The previous week's New Yorker had carried a fine article by Jeffrey Rosen entitled The Perjury Trap, in which he distinguished eight different kinds of 'lie,' including: kidding, exaggeration, fudging, halftruth, bent facts, white lies, falsehood, and perjury.2 But this was not the ethical issue either. For Rosen it was another version of the legal issue. But it does imply an ethical issue. For the ethical issue is: ought a human being - or ought he not - abstain from lying under any circumstance? If he ought, then the ethical question becomes: why? If he ought not, then 1 A. Schlessinger, Jr. 'Presidency Under Siege: Enough is Enough' in New York Times, August, 1998. 2 J. Rosen. 1The Perjury Trap' in The New Yorker LXXIV/23 (August 10,1998), pp. 28-32. 3 Rosen's spectrum of 'liesf from kidding to perjury suggests a way to differentiate various modalities of a ’lie1and differentiate accordingly the various levels of 'ought* that may pertain to them. Ethics is all about Ought. Psychologists/psychoanalysts clearly have their own kind of Ought. On April 19th, 1998, the front page of the Sunday Metro section of the New York Times, bore a bold headline that read: Child Psychiatrist and Pedophile, with the subhead: His Therapist Knew but Didn ' t Tell; a Victim Is Suing. The ethical question: ought he have told? The essential facts: Denny Almonte (21) is the son of struggling immigrant parents from the Dominican Republic. When he was 10 years old, abnormally depressed and troubled by suicide thoughts, he was brought by his parents to Connecticut State Hospital for treatment. There he was sexually molested by a Dr. Joseph De Masi, a 31 year old resident in child psychiatry on a 4-month hospital rotation at that time. Now 21 years old, Amante is bringing suit against New York Medical College, where De Masi was trained, and against Dr. Douglas Ingram, De Masi's therapist while in training, who was aware of De Masi's pederastic tendencies at the time. The suit holds New York Medical College liable for having failed to supervise and evaluate De Masi properly, and Dr. Ingram liable for having failed to inform the proper authorities of the latent danger De Masi presented to the children he was preparing to treat. The case will be heard in the First District Court in Bridgeport, and the trial is scheduled to begin September, 1998.3 The family argues that Dr. Ingram had an obligation to oppose New York Medical College's approval of De Masi as a child psychiatrist, because, although he was De Masi's therapist, he had a special responsibility 3 New York Times, pp. 4/19/98: A35-40. 4 toward the College inasmuch as he was, when the treatment began, also member of the Faculty of the College, whose consensual approval of De Masi's qualification to be a child psychiatrist would be decisive. Moreover, there was more than one way to make such opposition effective without revealing privileged information about the patient. Dr. Ingram, of course, sees the matter differently, and he is no naive apprentice. He finished a term as President of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis in 1998, has been editor of the American Journal of Psychoanalysis and is leader of a Manhattan Task Force on psychiatry and confidentiality for the American Psychiatric Association. He reports in his deposition that when De Masi first reported pederastic tendencies in 1986, he immediately terminated formal psychoanalysis of the patient on the grounds that psychoanalysis is incompatible with unrepentant pederasty (szc) but continued a more generalised psychotherapy with the purpose of challenging his thinking, managing distress and trying to make sure that he did not act out his desires. For his part, De Masi continued to defend these desires, presenting Dr. Ingram with a dubious study that presumably proved that children were not harmed by sex with adults. And besides, what about the Greeks? They survived, even flourished, and they did it all the time. Dr. Ingram took all this to be a sign of progress, inasmuch as De Masi was at last reflecting on the issue 'intellectually,' etc. Dr. Ingram claims to have 'agonised' over his decision, consulting both lawyers and several other psychiatrists for advice. In the end, though, he judged De Masi's pederastic interests to be rather a matter of 'attitude' than a plan for action, and did nothing to block his promotion But where is the Ought in all this? How does it arise? Whence comes its force? What is its scope? How does it function in the conjunction of the many factors just mentioned: the intention of the agent in making a decision, the nature of decision-making process, and of the responsibility that follows from having made it? Such questions as these are the stuff of ethics. They are essentially reflective (some would call them ’philosophical') questions that probe the deeper sources of human activity in its very humanness. If 'theory' (from the Greek theorem, meaning to 'behold' or 'look at') means to take a look at things from a distance in order 5 to see them more dearly, then ethics may be called a theoretical examination of human life in that activity involving the Ought that we have come to call 'moral'. Given the constraints of the present context, I propose to review, however sketchily, the general course that such theorising has taken over the years so as to understand more clearly the kind of challenge it poses for us today. Since the question about the 'ethics of psychoanalysis' has been brought into focus by Jacques Lacan in his seminar entitled, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis (1959-60),41 shall take as foci those philosophers of the tradition with regard to whose ethical thought Lacan has chosen to position his own ethical reflection, principally Aristotle and Kant. With this much to clarify what is meant by the subject of ethics in general, I shall then consider the 'ethics of psychoanalysis' in particular, asking whether this means something more than the application of general ethical norms to the problems of a specific profession ('professional' ethics, as it is called), and if so, how so. * * * * * The experience of Ought is much older than the word. Among the ruins of Pompeii there is a mural that portrays Agamemnon as he is about to sacrifice his daughter at Aulis. You will recall that, according to the myth, he is Head of State and General of the Armies whose responsibility it is to lead the Grecian assault against Troy. But the ships are becalmed and cannot move. Consultation with the seer informs him that the ships will remain becalmed until he offers his daughter, Iphegenia, as a human sacrifice to the gods in reparation for some ancestral sin. In the mural, Iphegenia is bound for the sacrifice and turns her eyes pleadingly to Agamemnon, begging for her life. Agamemnon refuses to meet her gaze and looks off into the distance, steeling himself for the decision he feels he has to make. For the Danish philosopher, Sdren Kierkegaard (1813-55), this mural serves as paradigm for every ethical dilemma. Agamnenon is 4J. Lacan. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book VII. The Ethics of Psychoanalysis (1959-1960), ed. by Jacques-Alain Miller, trans, by Dennis Porter. New York: W.W. Norton, 1992. bound by two forms of Ought that oppose each other: one obliges him as chief of state to expedite the liberation of his ships as efficiently as possible; another obliges him as father of his family to nurture the child he helped bring into the world and defend her from all harm. Yet choice between the two is necessary - it can not be evaded. Kierkegaard stresses the difference between the ethical dilemma confronted by Agamemnon and the religious dilemma confronted by Abraham when commanded by God to offer up his only son Isaac in sacrifice. With Agamnenon, the decision and act are his own. For Abraham, the authorisation for the act comes from God; Abraham merely acquiesces to it in religious faith. Let that say that ethics is a specifically human enterprise whose only instruments are human reason, knowledge, language and honesty. Moral issues based on religious faith of any kind, together with the notion of 'sin,' ‘redemption,1etc. they often comport, are left to theologians and philosophers of religion to discuss.5 The moral sense dramatised so powerfully by Aeschylus (525-456 BC) and Sophocles (496-406 BC) in sixth and fifth century B.C. Athens was based on sheer intuition, unconscious if you will, into the nature of the human predicament. Ethics as we know it would have to wait for the reflections of the philosophers. First among these, was Socrates (469-399 BC). We know him best as gadfly to the Sophists, the spin-doctors of his day. Their function was to teach people to 'live well,1that is, to 'do well1in the law courts, trading and political structures of the thriving City-State. Socrates took as his task to sting them into clarity about some of the ethical notions they bantered about so easily, like piety, justice, and the like. But in the final days of his trial and its aftermath that preceded his death, it became evident that the deepest question for him personally was what it meant for a human being to 'live well' simply as human. His answer: 'To live well means the same thing as to live honorably or 5 See S. Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, ed. and trarts. by H. V. and E.H. Hong. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University, 1983. pp. 1-123. rightly'.6 To keep asking this question is 'the best thing that a man can do'. Without such examination, 'life. . . is [simply] not worth living'.7 For Socrates, then, ethics meant asking about what it means to 'live well', that is, 'honourably and rightly', in the society in which he found himself—in other words, in a properly human way. In its essence, that is what ethics still means today. Everything turns around what we conceive a human being to be. But Socrates did little more than articulate the problem. It was Aristotle (384-322 BQ who addressed it formally, Aristotle who first elaborated ethics into a system that remains the baseline for all ethical thinking up to our own day. Aristotle poses the question in his master work, the Nicomachean Ethics, named after his son, Nicomachus, who edited the text after his father's death. In approaching the question, Aristotle first makes it clear that ethics as he deals with it here, with the focus on individual human life, is only part of, and propaedeutic to, a much more comprehensive science which deals with human life in its social and political dimension, the science of politics, 'truly the master art'.8 Let that say that every ethics worthy of the name implies a correlative political theory congruous with the social nature of the human phenomenon, even if it is impossible to retain that aspect of the problematic here. For Aristotle to ask what it means for a human being to 'live well' is to ask what we want most out of life. Whatever it may be, Aristotle calls it a 'good', meaning by that something that 'suits' us or 'fits' us, hence, somehow 'right' for us and, to that extent, satisfying. What we want most and would find most satisfying, would be some supreme good, exceeding all others, of which all other goods are but a shadow or an anticipation. Specifically, what is it? Aristotle examines the obvious options (wealth? honour? pleasure?, etc. - pleasure is very nice, of course, but far too ephemeral to be considered supreme among the rest) and settles on what 6Plato. 'Crito' 48b, in Plato: Collected Dialogues, ed. by E. Hamilton and H. Cairns. New York, Pantheon, Bollingen Series DOG, 1961. 7Plato. 'Socrates' Defence (Apology)' 38a. op.cit. 8 Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. by R. McKeon. New York,: Random House, 1941.1094 a 225 - b 5-10. Hereafter: NE. 8 he calls eudaimonia (lit. to be blessed with a good daimon, that is, genius, or guiding spirit), which is normally translated 'happiness'. This is how he defines it: Human good turns out to be activity of the spirit [for our purposes, understand this as 'self'] in accordance with excellence [that is, at the highest pitch of that activity, at its peak) and if there is more than one kind of excellence, in accordance with the best and most complete [of these]. But we must add 'in a complete life.' For one swallow does not make a summer.9 Aristotle has often been criticised for calling the supreme good for human beings 'happiness,' as if this were some fantasised pie in the sky when you die. But that misses the point completely. What human beings want most out of life, he claims, is some stable condition in which it is possible for them to flourish as being everything they can be, within the limits (that is, the risks and vulnerabilities) that are indigenous to human life as such.10 The nine books of the Nicomachean Ethics that follow analyse in detail how one ought to lead one's life in order to achieve this kind of fulfilment. Aristotle qualifies these excellences of the spirit as either 'intellectual' or 'ethical,' the first formal use of the word 'ethics' that we have. Here the word derives from the Greek ethos, meaning 'custom' or 'habit', in the sense of those habits that gradually form character in a human being. A lot happens here all at once: the Greek word for 'habit' (ethos) translates into Latin as mos, moris, giving us the word 'moral' (hence the confusing overlap between the words 'ethics' and 'morality' - Freud used the two terms interchangeably and we need not take time to insist upon a difference here), and the Greek word for 'excellence' (arete) translates into the Latin virtus, meaning 'strength', 'power'/ 9 ibid, 1098 b 15-20. 10See M. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge, University Press, 1986. pp. 31842. 9 ’empowerment' giving us the English 'virtue'. Sometimes Aristotle’s ethics is referred to as a 'virtue' ethics, meaning that the power of Ought is mediated through the traction that these virtues/excellences/powers exercise in the self.11 At this point, Aristotle elaborates what he understands by moral excellence. First of all it is 'a stable state of character, that is, a permanent disposition, as opposed to spontaneous impulse or passing phase, like the blue' phase of a Picasso, which then may yield to a subsequent phase of development. It has the following characteristics: 1. It includes the power of choice to perform a given action. 2. The appropriateness of this action is determined by a norm conceived as a mean between two kinds of extreme (that is, between excess and defect in the action itself): for example, for that tedious but de rigueur official reception, one ought not have too little to drink lest one appear unsociable, yet not too much either, lest one be thought a fool - just enough to wedge one’s way through the evening with a minimal amount of pain. Note the flexibility of such a norm: its measure is relative to the agent who discerns it here according to the circumstances that occasion the party, to one’s capacity to handle alcohol, to one's physical condition at the time (fatigued? empty stomach?), as well as to circumstances that are purely external (for example, one's status as the evening's 'designated driver'). 3. This choice must be a rational one, passing muster before the court of human reason - before a logos, therefore, and Aristotle sometimes adds orthos, that is, upright reason, with all the rigor that that implies. Heidegger has called our attention to the fact that logos in Aristotle also means 'speech,' suggesting that Aristotle's definition of human being as zdon logon echon, normally translated 'an animal having reason1 (that is, 'rational animal'), could also be translated 'animal having language' (that 11NE, n, 1,1103 a 15-19. 10 is, 'speaking animal'). This legitimates Lacan's reading of logos in this context as 'discourse'. In any case, ethics for Aristotle is the business of intelligence articulated in language, not simply of feeling or affect of any kind. 4. This reason must be such that a prudent man, the man whose wisdom in dealing with practical matters has been earned through long, hard years of experience, would concur with it. The opinions of the ‘best and the brightest' are not good enough here. What is needed is a fought for wisdom that is dearly won on the battlefield of life itself. To gain a concrete (though maybe simplistic) sense of what Aristotle means by moral excellence, recall the story of the 'Unabomber'. By all accounts, the mother and father of the Kaczyinski boys were 'good enough' parents as measured by the standards of our time. Apparently they did their best to instil good habits in their sons. Both boys were bright (eventually each would take an Ivy League degree), both reflective and reserved in manner (though from the beginning Ted was the more withdrawn of the two). Despite the seven-year age difference, the two related fairly well to each other, sharing a love of nature and life in the wild, a disdain for the excesses of technology as threatening the destruction of mankind, and a compelling sense of justice. After a successful stint as a high school English teacher, followed by several years as a solitary living close to nature in a desolate corner of Texas, David finally shaved, clipped his hair, pared his nails and returned to normal living in 1990. He trained as a social worker, married his high school sweetheart and became a counsellor to troubled adolescents in Albany, an unspectacular but well respected member of the community. As for Ted, the seeds of the family training fell upon rocky soil. Despite brilliant promise as a mathematician, he became more and more alienated through his academic career that began at Harvard and ended at Berkeley. In 1970 he dropped out completely and withdrew into a hut built by himself in the recesses of the Montana forests. Except for 11 occasional short trips to mail his bombs, there he remained until his capture in 1996. In the summer of 1995, David's suspicions were aroused when newspaper reports surmised that the Unabomber had associations in Chicago, Berkeley and Salt Lake City - all places where he knew Ted had been. When the Unabomber's manifesto appeared in the New York Times, David could hear the echo of Ted's voice in peculiar turns of phrase, He brought his suspicions to Susan Swanson, childhood friend of his wife then working for a local detective firm. She engaged the help of Clinton Van Zandt, behavioural scientist and formerly the FBI's chief hostage negotiator, who ran a security consulting firm. He, in turn, engaged a psychiatrist and a linguist, and together the three compared the Unabomber's manifesto with two of Ted's earlier letters to his family. Their conclusion: a 60% probability that all 3 were the work of the same author. As further confirmation, two more communications specialists reviewed the material and raised the probability ratio to 80% - 90%. At that point, Swanson turned to Anthony Bisceglie, respected Washington attorney, who then in guarded fashion approached the FBI* A month later, he persuaded David to talk directly to the agents, who promised a discreet and unobtrusive investigation. We know the rest of the story. Convinced that his brother was the Unabomber, David had several extreme options available: He could have remained completely silent out of visceral loyalty to his own flesh and blood ('My brother is my brother is my brother'). The other extreme could have been to go straight to the FBI on the first suspicion, with no precaution for his family’s privacy or heed to second thoughts, to stake a claim on the reward and hire an agent to negotiate the book contract. In fact he chose a mean between these two extremes, first by confirming his suspicions through a second, third, fourth, sixth and even seventh judgement (the issue was serious enough to warrant such care), then by seeking the discretion and mediation of the man of proven practical wisdom, a savvy Washington lawyer. Only then did he allow himself to be persuaded to reveal what he knew to the FBI. If one were to ask him why he did what he did, he might be surprised by the question. Whatever the pain and shame to his family and himself, the 12 lives of other possible victims, and with them the common good of society at large, all of these were at stake - reason enough to motivate a man of true moral stature, as Aristotle conceives him to be. As for the Unabomber himself, he, too, can be seen through Aristotelian eyes. However well intentioned by a sense of justice and justified anger at the abuses of technology, he chose a solution that was an extreme one, a mad one. Indicted and convicted, he nonetheless received a very Aristotelian sentence, for he was spared the death penalty. Aristotle saw very clearly that actions compelled from the outside, or proceeding from overwhelming passion or ignorance (here: insanity) do not proceed from an agent in a responsibly human way. A responsible choice is a deliberate choice. As Aristotle puts it: 'Choice will be a deliberate desire of things within our power; for when we have decided as a result of deliberation, we desire in accordance with our deliberation'^ By this standard, Ted Kasczynski's choice was not a properly deliberate one, hence he can not be held fully accountable for his action. The 'insanity defence' is as old as that, as valid today as it ever was and for a constantly Aristotelian reason. Does Aristotle have anything to say about lying? Not very much. In discussing various kinds of virtue in Book IV, he speaks, among other things, of love for the truth. 'The lover of truth' he writes, 'eschews lying as [a] shameful [thing],' and, indeed, 'in itself' (kath auto) - I take him to mean, apart from any circumstances or motivation that might mitigate iU3 If asked for comment on CNN, he might have wished for the sound-bite wit of a Samuel Johnson to be able to say: 'Even the devils themselves do not lie to one another, since the society of Hell could not subsist without truth anymore than the others'.14 In any case, Aristotle's point presumably would have been the same. *2 Aristotle, NE, III, 4,1113 a 10-15. 13 Aristotle, NE, IV, 7,1127 b 5. 14S. Johnson. 'The Adventurer' 50 (28 April 1753), in Selected Essays from The Rambler, Adventurer, and Idler, ed. by WJ. Bate. New Haven, Vale University, 1968. Cited by Sissela Bok in Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life. New York, Pantheon, 1978. pp. 18-19. What, then, may we retain as the essentials of Aristotelian ethics? At least this much: 1. The Ought for Aristotle is exercised through the power by which every human being strives toward the supreme good of being all one can be within the ineluctibie limits of one's finitude. 2. This implies that an ethical act is a specifically human act, in which one's essential humanity (including intelligence and power of choice) is at stake. 3. What constitutes the norm of human propriety is clearly 'situational'. It is discernible in a unique situation as a mean between extremes relative to a single individual agent, yet it escapes the arbitrary and approximates the universal to the extent that it is determined by right reason as confirmed by the judgement of the man of practical wisdom. 4. The ethical agent is responsible for his decisions and is to be held accountable for them. * * * * * If Aristotle is the most important ethical thinker of the ancient world, it is Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) who holds that distinction for modernity. I take ’modernity' here to refer to that historical epoch that began in the sixteenth century when human attention shifted from focus on the external world of a theocentric universe to the subject's awareness of itself as fundamental reference point for all thought and action. We all know about the lightning-bolt effect of Descartes' discovery that an unshakeable ground of truth and certainty could be found in one's certainty about one's own existence as verified in the very questioning of it. This turn towards the subject reached its apogee two centuries later in what we know as the Enlightenment, and Kant was its brightest star. 14 Springboard of Kant's thought was his confrontation with the English philosopher, David Hume (1711-1776), who argued that we can have no valid knowledge beyond what the evidence of sense impressions leaves us. What we call 'ideas' are representations of these impressions in the mind but fainter than they. Abstract or general ideas are clusters of individual ideas united by association with each other, but truly universal ideas, that is, one single meaning (for example, 'water') that can be predicated univocally of many inferiors, are impossible. Yet there was Isaac Newton (1642-1727) using universal ideas initially grounded in empirical data to formulate the universal and necessary laws of mechanics. Kant's challenge was to reconcile the apparent contradiction. This meant exploring on a much deeper level than Descartes had been able to do the fundamental structure of the human subject's power to know in the very roots of its possibility. In the simplest terms, he admitted with Hume that there are indeed data presented to us by the world outside us that are 'sensibly' perceived, but the perceiving of them presupposes that these data first be registered on a perceptive apparatus constituted by radar systems of space and time. These sense perceptions are then processed through certain organising systems of the understanding called 'categories' that enable the understanding itself to supply to its judgements the universality and necessity that constitute the 'law' character of Newton's scientific discoveries. But Kant did not stop there. With this much momentum, he proceeded to examine still more abstract ideas of reason in its purest form, that is, stripped of any relation at all to sense experience such as the laws of science can claim. Such ideas are found on the turf where metaphysicians feel most at home and like to claim as their own: ideas such as the world itself (as distinct from the things that are in it), the immortality of the soul, and the existence and attributes of God. But without any connection to sense experience, such ideas have no ground to stand on. Ungrounded, they are without validity. Invalid, they serve at best to regulate our thought processes, giving them order and orientation but nothing more. This whole examination he called a 'critique', in the sense of a 'determining of the limits' of human reason in its purity (that is, independent of sense experience), hence the title of his epoch-making work: Critique of Pure Reason. Deprived of the God of metaphysics, Kant was nonetheless the son of Pietist parents with a deeply moral sense of Ought. Whatever must be said about Reason in its speculative function, it has a practiced function too, in our daily moral life. In the order of practical activity, pure Reason is referred to as pure Will and, as such, the Law of all morality. Elsewhere he tells us that 'nothing in the world - indeed nothing even beyond the world - can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will1.15 That human will is good, then, that conforms to pure Reason as Will, that is, as Law, and, indeed, motivated solely by reverence for the Law, which Kant calls 'duty'. This is a hard saying, of course. Kant is aware, to be sure, that many other motives stir us to action - for example, sensual pleasure, hope of reward, love, compassion, and above all desire for happiness, but none of these suffice to make an act morally good. Kant gives the example of the honest shopkeeper. If the reason for his honesty is that it is good for business, that is not enough to make his behaviour moral. Duty alone must be the motive, if an act is to be considered conformed to pure Reason as Will as Law. The good news is that since the Law is Reason itself as it is inscribed in every rational being, hence in every human being, Reason may be said to be the giver of the Law, that is, to be the Lawgiver that gives the moral Law to itself. This is what Kant calls the 'autonomy' of the moral subject. For a human being to submit to the Law that its own reason imposes upon itself is already a profound form of freedom. But how is one to know whether a given act is conformed to the Law or not? Kant proposes a rule of thumb that he calls the 'categorical imperative.' That's the bad news. This is a command ('imperative') of conscience that is unconditional ('categorical') in its demand for obedience. This is what Freud takes to be the paradigm of what he calls the 'super151. Kant. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by L.W. Beck. New York, BobbsMerrill, 1959. p. 9. 16 ego1. Kant opposes this to a 'hypothetical' imperative, based upon a condition to be fulfilled (for example, if you wish to qualify for third-party payment, you ought to [must] have proper professional accreditation). A categorical imperative is unconditional and may be formulated as follows: 'So act that the maxim of your will could always hold at the same time as a principle establishing universal law'. In other words, if the maxim that guides an action can be considered valid for every human being without inconsistency or contradiction, then its very universalisability is a guarantee that it is in conformity with universal Law/Reason. Take, for example, the issue of promise-keeping. If my maxim is that in making a promise I implicitly affirm that I am not bound by this promise, that is already a contradiction in itself. Stretched to the universal level, the maxim would permit no social organism to survive. Again, with regard to the lie, let the maxim be: ’I have a right to lie if I have a good reason to do so’. Now Kant assumes that the natural purpose of the speech acts in which lying occurs is the ’communication of one's thoughts'.16 To tell a lie, even for a good reason, contradicts the very nature of a speech act: 'It cannot hold as a universal law of nature that an assertion should have the force of evidence and yet be intentionally false'.17 Again: The man who communicates his thoughts to someone in words which yet (intentionally) contain the contrary of what he thinks on the subject has a purpose directly opposed to the natural purposiveness of the power of communicating one's thoughts; [he] therefore renounces his personality and makes himself a mere deceptive appearance of a man.18 161. Kant. Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor. Cambridge, University Press, 1991. pp. 225-7/429-30. Hereafter: MM. 171. Kant. Critique of Practical Reason, trans. by L.W. Beck. Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill, 1956. p. 45/44. 18Kant, MM, pp. 226/429. 17 This sounds pretty rigorous and it is. The acid test is a classic case, which, transposed into terms of the Anne Frank era, would read: if a Gestapo officer were to inquire of a Dutch householder whether there were any Jews inside his house, might the householder lie to save an innocent person's life? Kant himself will say 'no,1on the ground that obligation to speak the truth is an obligation to society at large as a guarantee of its integrity and harmony. 'Here is an unconditional necessitation through a command (or prohibition) of reason, which I must obey; and in face of it all my inclinations must be silent1.19 Opposition to this rigorism has been all but universal, but some nuance is available in Kant's reflection on rules that conflict with each other. Since all moral obligations are absolute, one cannot say that one obligation is more binding than another, but rather that the stronger ground of obligation should prevail. Hence: When two such grounds conflict with each other, practical philosophy says, not that the stronger obligation takes precedence ..., but that the stronger ground of obligation prevails ...20 Thus, in the case in question, protecting another person's life provides a stronger ground of obligation than that of telling the truth. Hence, in this case, following the rule against lying would in fact be 'contrary to our duty'.21 However austere Kant's position may be, in fairness we should add that he does not want us to take the negative injunction that one must never lie as identical with the positive injunction that one must always tell 19 Kant MM, pp. 270/481. This position was confirmed when challenged by HenriBenjamin Constant who had argued that one has a duty to tell the truth but only to someone who has the right to the truth, and then only when it will do no harm to others. Kant's repudiation of the idea in Supposed Right to Lie from Altruistic Motives (1797) was adamant. See Sullivan, pp. 173-7. 20 Kant, MM, pp. 50/224. 21 R. J. Sullivan. Kant's Moral Theory. Cambridge, University Press, 1990. p.177. Hereafter: KMT. 18 the truth, 'the whole truth and nothing but the truth’. There are many verbal interchanges that do not purport to tell the truth, and prudent reserve is an essential part of daily living. Besides, Kant points out elsewhere that there are many morally acceptable ways by which we may avoid telling the truth without lying: for example, silence, mental reservations, noncommittal answers, evasions, equivocations, and the like.22 Case in point: would a statement, made in a deposition in a civil suit, that is 'legally accurate' but, by the standards of ordinary language, factually untrue qualify as a justifiable mental reservation? Or as a lie? If it be a lie and made under oath, is it subject to the charge of perjury? What precisely constitutes perjury? Is it a legal fault or a moral one? What is the relationship between the legal order and the moral order? What is the difference? These are the kinds of questions that pertain to the subject of ethics. But there is more than one formula for the categorical imperative. Much more significant to psychologists and psychoanalysts is a formula that emerges when Kant argues as follows: since every human being is autonomous, that is, its own Lawgiver, it is by the same token irreducible and unique, that is, an 'end' in itself. Thus, he can express the categorical imperative by the following formula: 'Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never only as a means'23 - a formula that permits us to understand the entire human community as a 'Kingdom of Ends'.24 This formula expresses the acme of Kantian ethics - it makes the whole long climb 22 See Sullivan, KMT, 172. It should be noted that Kant's Lectures on Ethics, trans. by L. Infield (Indianapolis, Hackett, 1963) are sets of notes largely taken down by students from his lecture courses at the University of Königsberg, 1775-80, which were largely commentaries on Alexander Baumgarten, Initia philosophiae practicae primae (1760) and Ethica philosophica (3rd ed., 1763). They are more familiar in style and less rigorous in argument (for example, he expresses a certain tolerance for the 'white lie' here) than CPrR and MM. They may not be taken, then, as representing his definitive position on these matters. See L.W. Beck, 'Foreward' to Kant, Lectures on Ethics, ix-xiv. 231. Kant. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by L.W. Beck (New York: BobbsMerrill, 1959. pp. 47/429. 24 ibid., pp. 51/433. 19 worthwhile. Let the words be said again and carved in stone: 'Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or that of another, always as an end, never only as a means'. What, then, is the subject of ethics? Taken in the sum of its history, it is a theoretical reflection upon moral action, which has as its fundamental question: what ought one do to lead a decent human life, that is, in terms of one's own humanity and that of one's fellow humans, including the broader community in which one lives. Its essentials are a theory of Ought and an accountable subject that responds to that Ought. Every ethical principle derives from the conception of what makes a human being human from which it starts. For a capstone formula, we can't do better than Kant: Act in such a way as to respect humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never only as a means.1 Given all this we are in a position to evaluate the conception of ethics proposed by Edwin Wallace, in an otherwise excellent article on Freud as Ethicist: The definition of 'ethics' by Abelson and Nielson25 approximates as closely as any to what I mean by the term: '(1) a general pattern or 'way of life,' [No! That is the work of sociology or anthropology. Ethics is reflection on the Ought that lies at the basis of such a pattern]; (2) a set of rules of conduct or ’moral code1 [No! Reflection on the Ought implies consequences that follow, but not a 'set of rules' imposed, as it were, from outside human being as such]; (3) inquiry about ways of life and rules of conduct [No! That may make for sociological research or 25 R. Abelson and K. Nielson. 'History of Ethics' in Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by P. Edwards. New York, Macmillan, 1967. pp. 81-117. Cited by Edwin R. Wallace, IV, 'Freud as Ethicist,' in Freud. Appraisals and Reappraisals, ed. by Paul E. Stepansky. Hillsdale, N.J. Analytic Press, 1986. pp. 83-141. 20 investigative journalism but it implies no reflection at all upon the meaning and implications of Ought]'.26 * * * * * What, then, is the subject of the ethics of -psychoanalysis? General principles must be translated surely into the specifics of daily life and, more particularly, into terms appropriate to the various circumstances and problems proper to different professions. Result: 'professional ethics.' Basic paradigm for this would be the ethics of the medical profession as formulated in the stentorian tones of the Hippocratic Oath: You do solemnly swear, each man by whatever he holds most sacred, that you will be loyal to the profession of medicine and just and generous to its members; that you will lead lives and practice by our art in uprightness and honor; that into whatever house you shall enter, it shall be for the good of the sick to the utmost of your power, you holding yourselves far aloof from wrong, from corruption, from the tempting of others to vice; that you will exercise your art solely for the cure of your patients and will give no drug, perform no operation for a criminal purpose, even if solicited, far less suggest it; that whatsoever you shall see or hear of the lives of men which is not fitting to be spoken, you will keep inviolably secret. These things do you swear.27 Is the ethics of psychoanalysis anything more than a general ethics adapted to the particularity of psychoanalysis, as the Hippocratic Oath has been applied to the practise of medicine? If so, then why make an issue of it now? Psychologists are already amply guided by the ’Ethical Principles 26 E.R. Wallace. 'Freud as Ethicist,1 in Freud. Appraisals and Reappraisals, ed. by P.V. Stepansky. Hillsdale, N.J: Analytic Press, 1986). pp. 83-142,83. 27Columbia Encyclopedia. New York, Macmillan, Columbia University, 1950. 21 and Code of Conduct' of the American Psychological Association, and the American Psychoanalytic Association has had its own set of guidelines in place for years. If not, how does it differ from all other forms of professional ethics so as to need a version all its own? The 'Code of Conduct' for psychologists in my copy runs to fourteen pages, includes eight sections, one hundred and ten entries, dealing with: the clinical or counselling practice of psychology, research, teaching, supervision of trainees, development of assessment instruments, conducting assessments, educational counselling, organisational consulting, social intervention, administration, and other activities as well. Reduced to simplicity, the code echoes and re-echoes the following themes: regarding the psychologist, the crucial word is ’responsibility,' first toward oneself in developing and maintaining one's professional expertise, then toward the profession, then toward the community at large, and last but most of all toward the client(s), and this primarily in the form of ’respect'. Respect for what? Again and again the word 'dignity' recurs, and this keeps referring to 'rights', 'values', 'autonomy1, ‘privacy1, 'confidentiality' etc. Taken in the sum, these indices add up to a conception of the human being that far transcends the impression given by some of the literature: for example, that a human being can be understood basically as a bundle of stimuli and responses, or as a computer that can be programmed if only we can develop the right software, or as a substance that, in principle, is totally quantifiable. Responsibility, dignity, rights, autonomy, privacy - none of these can be quantified, assessed by statistics or displayed on a graph. Vet these are heart and soul of the psychologist's ethical code. The 'Ethical Principles' of the American Psychoanalytic Association essentially overlap those for psychologists. Differences are largely matters of detail: the Code for psychologists includes reference to the rubrics of testing, etc., while the Code for psychoanalysts refers to consultations between analysts, the setting of fees, etc. Both Codes are equally adamant against sexual relations between therapist and client. Does not all this suffice to handle the problems of a Dr. Ingram? Of course it does. Why, 22 then, speak about an ethics of psychoanalysis now as if it were something new and unique? If we turn to Freud, we find no answer - there is no mention at all of an 'ethics of psychoanalysis' as such. To be sure, he speaks a great deal about ethical (more precisely, ’moral') issues, and often in radical fashion, but none of this adds up to a formal ethics. And we know that in his personal life his morals were quite conventional - even austere.28 True enough; he was opposed to repression of any kind (though he realised it was inevitable), but the closest thing to an ethics one can find in his work, perhaps, is what Philip Rieff called an 'ethics of honesty1.29 No, it is Lacan, and Lacan alone, who forces the issue of an ethics of psychoanalysis upon us and won't let us turn away. His claim is that Freud's fundamental insight was of its very nature an ethical one, and implied the opening up of a new dimension of ethics that far transcends any of its traditional forms: ... The deep dissatisfaction we find in every psychology including the one we have founded thanks to psychoanalysis - derives from the fact that it is nothing more than a mask, and sometimes even an alibi, of the effort to focus on the problem of our own action - something that is the essence and very foundation of all ethical reflection. In other words, we need to know if we have managed to do anything more than take a small step outside ethics and if, like the other psychologies, our own is simply another development of ethical reflection, of the search for a guide or a way, that in the last analysis may be formulated as follows: 'Given our condition as men, what must we do in order to act in the right way?'30[-question as old as Socrates!] 28 E. Wallace, 'Freud as Ethicist,' pp. 128-36. 29 P. Rieff. Freud: The Mind of the Moralist 3rd ed, Chicago, University Press, 1979. pp.30028. See also E. Wallace, 1Freud the Eihicist' in Freud: Appraisals and Reappraisals ed. by P. Stepansky. Analytic Press, 1986. pp. 82-141. 30J. Lacan, op.cit., pp. 19/27-28. 23 [But Freud] has changed the problems of the ethical perspective for us to a degree that we are not yet aware o f ... ... [His] discourse facilitates something that allows us to go farther than anyone has gone before in a domain that is essential to the problems of morality .. .31 What is it in Freud's experience that has such profound ethical import, despite his failure to generate any proper ethics in its own name? The fact, claims Lacan, that for Freud the unconscious comports the function of desire: Analysis is the experience which has restored to favour in the strongest possible way the productive function of desire as such. This is so evidently the case that one can, in short, say that the genesis of the moral dimension in Freud's theoretical elaboration is located nowhere else than in desire itself.32 The entire Seminar on The Ethics of Psychoanalysis becomes, then, the orchestration of an ethics of desire. For Lacan, psychoanalysis opens up an entirely new dimension of a human being (the unconscious), which challenges every conception of what makes human beings human that the ethical tradition has considered. Until now, every ethics has taken into account only the conscious subject; no ethics has taken into account the unconscious as Freud conceived it. That is why an ethics of psychoanalysis cannot be simply an application of general ethical principles to a specific practice - a professional ethics like the rest. It must be formulated precisely as an 31 ibid., pp. 36/47. 32 ibid., pp. 3/11. Cp. 38/48,84/101,133/159,152/182,291/338,312/360 24 ethics of desire as such. We cannot take the question any further here and must be content with Lacan's own formulation of his project: ... It is because we know better than those who went before how to recognise the nature of desire, which is at the heart of this experience, that a reconsideration of ethics is possible, that a form of ethical judgement is possible, of a kind that gives this question the force of a Last judgement: Have you acted in conformity with the desire that is in you? We are left with certain questions, however, that an elaboration of such an ethic must sooner or later confront: 1. Lacan hints at the first question himself, when he says in the closing session: 'If there is an ethics of psychoanalysis - the question is an open one - it is to the extent that analysis in some way or other, no matter how minimally, offers something that is presented as a measure of our action - or at least claims to'.33 But what can be the measure of desire except desire itself? Does this mean that desire is unlimited by any Ought that constrains it? In the analytic situation, we have in fact not one desire but two: desire of the analyst and desire of the analysand. For the analyst, the desire is constrained by an Ought that binds one to yield to the exegencies of the analytic process as such, that is, to do everything in one's power to allow the unconscious of the analysand to manifest itself to itself, so that he may acknowledge and assume it as his own. But what Ought 'measures,' that is, constrains, the desire of the analysand? If the measure of the analysand's desire is desire itself as metonymied through language, how are other essential ingredients in the analysand's life (for example, the needs, demands, desires, legitimate rights of other subjects -like spouse, children - dependents of any kind) to be factored in as limits to the analysand's desire? 2. How does an ethics of desire as described account for the subject of that desire? The nature of desire emerges as the subject reconstructs the 33 ibid., pp. 311/359. 25 narrative of her past slowly (painfully) recognising it as her own and accepting responsibility for it, eventually acquiescing to the castration that must be embraced. But this implies a continuity in the subject that the process itself supposes. How are we to understand that continuity - 1 do not say substantiality - but con-sistency and co-herence of the subject necessary for the analytic process itself to take place, when the most that can be said for the subject of psychoanalysis is, in Lacan's own words, as follows: My hypothesis is that the individual who is affected by the unconscious is the same individual who constitutes what I call the subject of the signifier. That is what I enunciate in the minimal formulation that a signifier represents a subject to another signifier. The signifier in itself is nothing but what can be defined as a difference from another signifier. The subject is never more than fleeting (ponctuel) and vanishing, for it is a subject only by a signifier and to another signifier.34 How can so fleeting a subject abide long enough to accept responsibility for anything, that is, be an ethical subject at all? Yet without an accountable subject, there is no ethics, and an ethics of psychoanalysis no more than chimera. The whole enterprise would have to be rethought, then - or call itself something else. Address for correspondence: Boston College Chestnut Hill MA 02167 U.S.A. 34 J. Lacan. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan XX. Encore. On Feminine Sexuality, the Limits of Love and Knowledge (1972-1973), ed. by J.-A. Miller, trans, by B. Fink. New York, W.W. Norton, 1998. pp. 142/129-30. 26 PEUT-ON PARLER DE PSYCHOSE SOCIALE? Marcel Czermak* xLe Maître modem se fiche éperdument du savoir. De toute façon, le savoir est à son service. Il lui suffit que ça marche. Et plus le savoir (S2) veut se faire reconnaître comme savoir, plus il conforte (SI), le Maître. Ce qui explique la phobie institutionnelle Le praticien est fondé à divers titres d'intervenir dans le débat si aigu soulevé par notre conjoncture sociale et la subjectivité qui s'y forme. Dans cette conjecture, il est un élément essential: la référence générale au développement de la science dont le 'discours' semble faire autorité pour tous. Or, ce qui fait ses fondements, son universalité comme sa communicabilité tient essentiellement au rejet de toute question ontologique, de toute interrogation sur le sujet. Est-il envisageable qu'un discours qui étend son filet sur toute la planète, à la condition que nous venons de repeler, ne voie pas ces questions réapparaître ailleurs, sous forme de réponses étranges et déguisées? Ce n'est pas parce que l'on a appuyé sur le bon bouton, qu'il n'y a pas de réponses ailleurs due là où elles sont attendues, qui cachent leur nature de réponse. C'est en tout cas ce que la psychanalyse enseigne, puisque c'est ce sujet éliminé de la Science (forclos, disait Lacan) dont elle a à traiter, quand il lui fait retour en ses plaintes et symptômes. Et, dès lors, ce que la psychanalyse aborde, c'est la vérité comme cause - cause de la souffrance là où la Science en exclut le terme pour la réduire à l'opposition du vrai et du faux. En effet, si la vérité est contestable, c'est moins par défaut que par structure: elle concerne toujours un rapport à ¡'Autre dans lequel nous sommes tous pris. C'est-à-dire que l'une de ses moitiés git dans cet autre même, ce qui la rend impossible à dire toute. *This article appeared originally in Passage - la férocité sociale, fevrier 1995, No. 67. 27 L'exactitude, qui fonde le vrai et le faux, est d'un autre tonneau: elle tient à une axiomatique qui, par définition, se passe de cet Autre. La Science est sans adresse. Au point de soulever la question de savoir si elle peut être dite discours, puisqu'y est évacué le problème du fantasme (ce qui rend le plaisir apte au désir). Alors mieux vaudrait dire ce qu'elle sert: actuellement, il est clair que ce sont les discours de la maîtrise. Et cependant, Science comme maîtrise se révèlent supportées par un fantasme de totalisation, d'universalisation don't l'une des conséquences est de masquer le manque-à-être central de 1' être parlant, divisé par le langage. N'énonçant ses formules qu'en évacuant toute division, elle installe un pur sujet, sujet absolu. Ce qui, d'ailleurs, n'empêche pas ce drame de certains savants, chez qui la vérité fait retour. Comment alors peut-on créditer la Science d'une 'ambition de comprendre1 ... 'besoin primaire de l'humanité' (A. Lichnerowicz) quand toute l'experience analytique nous enseigne qu'il n'est nulle pulsion épistsémologique, mais bien au contraire que l'on ne fait jamais que s'empresser d'oublier, méconnaître ce que l'on a appris. Au point que la Science puisse être qualifiée de cas local de la logique du fantasme: celui où l'on se débarrasse des soucis ordinaires de l'humanité. Mais les façons ne manquent guère de vouloir arriver à de telles fins. En tout cas la Science y échoue, ce qui ne signifie pas qu'elle puisse avoir du bon, mais pas sans les maladies afférentes. D'autant que d'un bien peuvent surgir des maux encore plus grands que ceux qu'il s'agit de combattre. En effect, quand A. Lichnerowicz conclut: 'Ainsi la physique nous offre-t-elle un conception du monde'^id), celle-ci est pour le moins curieuse puisqu'elle ne traiterait de rien d'essentiel: qu'est-ce qu'un père, une filiation, la jouissance, le courage et la lâcheté, enfin tout ce qui fait que les hommes tournent autour d'insaisissables, qui cependant les actionnent quand ils s'illusionnent d ’une quelconque maîtrise, là-même où ils ont évacué l'interrogation sur l'objet qui causerait leurs désirs? 1 A. Lichnerowicz. Les Scientifiques parient, sous la direction d’A. Jacquard. Hachette, 1987. 28 Cet objet, qui n'est pas celui de la Science, quel est'il? Car il faut bien se prononcer làdessus: toute la vie sociale y prend appui, comme s'en détermine. Et quel en est le corrélat, sujet de cet objet? Pour autant que c'est de la chute de cet objet énigmatique liée à l'incidence du signifiant, que surgit un sujet qui n'est nulle hypostase, ni homoncule dans l'homme. Le sujet divisé Les questions sont liées et incontournables: quelle sorte de sujet devons-nous concevoir? Le simple fait de l'inconscience, qu'il y ait un discours qui parle en nous sans que nous en ayons la moindre idée, indique assez son caractère divisé. Parfois il se manifeste dans les lapsus, mots d'esprit, actes manqués, rêves. Plus souvent, il agit dans les déboires que nous nous sommes préparés, sans avoir la moindre notion des raisons pour lesquelles ils nous adviennent. Et un sujet divisé n'est nulle entité, il faut le répéter. Aussi, dès lors que la Science vaut pour maîtresse, il devient vain de prôner amélioration de l'enseignement, de l'information voire de la formation: puisque la transmission de ce savoir y est conforme à ses prémisses d'exclusion subjective, la suite ne peut qu'y être conforme, soit alimenter ses conséquences inaperçues: à l'intrusion galopante et triomphale de la science, répond l'injonction terrible du triple champ de la crainte, de la culpabilité et de la haine (E. Jones). Déploiement des magies, des guerres de religion et des phénomènes ségrégatifs de tous ordres. Là oû la Science collabe besoin et demande rejetant ce qui, dans toute demande, relève du désir, on aboutit à un 'faisable' que ne bride aucun 'souhaitable'.2. C'est-à-dire qu'on tombe sous le coup d'un impératif généralisé. Alors resurgit cette magie qu'il ne suffit pas de traiter de 'fausse science', puisque le qualificatif laisse intact le questionnement sur sa cause efficiente, qui ne doit rien à la physiologie, mais inciterait plutôt à s'interroger sur ce qui est au principe du moindre effet de commandement, et pour chaque homme. Resurgit également, forclos du 2 C. Castoriadis, Les Scientifiques parlent, op.cit. symbolique de la science, un sujet absolu qui inonde le réel: ce Dieu de la religion, à qui est laissée la charge de la cause, cependant que le religieux formule sur le mode impératif les désirs supposés de ce Dieu dont il recherche les bonnes grâces. Et l'on n'a même pas ébauché la réflexion sur les effets, en général glorifiés, de l'universalisation de la Science - car nous bafouillons - effets fracassants par leur immixtion dans des montages symboliques qui lui sont hétérogènes, mais plutôt des réponses dans le réel, et souvent déconcertantes quand elles ne sont pas dramatiques. La science et son maître La Science a basculé du côté du Maître. Elle le sert. Le Maître y a mis du sien: nos politiques, administrateurs et gestionnaires répètent à l'envi: ’Nous ne sommes que vos représentants. Dites-nous ce qu'il faut faire'. Eludant la charge de leur position d'agents, ils font proliférer commissions et comités de sages sur la recherche, l'enseignement, l'éthique, organisent des Etats Généraux de la Sécurité sociale. Et nous disent: 'Vous êtes des gens formidables mais vous ne donnez aucune réponse immédiate. Rien n'est résolu, alors nous qui sommes dans l’action, il faut bien que nous décidions'. Passe-passe où, la Science comme les autres savoirs et savoir-faire, passés aux mains du Maître lui permettent - dans la dénégation, la dissimulation de son pouvoir - d'exercer des lois dont il n'a jamais à rendre compte du savoir d'où elles procéderaient. Le Maître a actuellement d'autant moins de comptes à rendre (quand voit-on un ministre démissionnaire pour cause d'incompétence se suicider, ou simplement aller en prison?) qu'il a embobiné tout le savoir, passé à son service, cependant qu'il est dispensé de produire son savoir propre, lequel n'est pas celui de la Science. Quant à l'université, il est devenu clair que, quoiqu'elle en aie (y compris dans ses refus de collaboration, car le refus peut être aussi une collaboration), elle a également basculé au service du Maître: elle produit des unités de ’valeur', cependent que les citoyens sont saisis par les 30 'valeurs' boursières. Et la vérité crie à côté de nous: en décembre 1986, ces étudiants qui récusaient d'être réduits dans leur valeur d'usage, demandaient simultanément que leur soit garantie - dans leur angoisse leur valeur d'échange sur le marché: valeur comptable de plus-value, en économie 'libérale'. Ceux qui veulent leur place dans la société la réclament dans les termes mêmes dont ils pâtissent, ce que l'on qualifie en termes actuels: 'Il faut savoir se vendre1et avec 'un plus' (capitalisable de préférence). En URSS, la chose était claire: pour être professeur, il fallait servir le parti qui est le Maître. Les choses sont plus camouflées pour nous: l'université prépare les plusvalues, seraient-elles incarnées. En ce joint de cauchemar et d'angoisse, que la Science élude, rien ne sert d'y faire appel à une bonne volonté quelconque: les hommes n'ont jamais, pour la plupart, voulu connaître autre chose que ce qui les arrangeait. Le problème est affaire de structure. Et ce qui les arrange est cause du discours qui les fait produire. Mais la vérité est ailleurs que dans la production, et - de surcroît - refoulée. C'est ça qui est à examiner. Alors, dans cette tâche, où trouverons-nous notre cap? On peut douter que la culture nous y aide: C. Jullien,3 dans son premier article de la série du Monde diplomatique sur: 'Des sociétés malades de leur culture', relevait bien comment sous Vichy, des hommes de même culture pouvaient, les uns sombrer dans la barbarie (que ce soit par souci d'être du côté du manche, ou par capture par le Dieu obscur qui réclamerait le sacrifice ségrégatif, ou encore pour dormir tranquille) et ceux qui, dans un courageux regard toisaient en face le monstre, au risque le leur vie. La question relève de ce qu'un homme peut apprécier des objets qui le déterminent, soit s'en conforter, soit pour s'en déprendre. Alors, pensée sans objet? Se demandait-il? Il ne me semble pas: la pensée n'est pas une catégorie. Lacan disait qu'elle serait davantage du côte de l'affect; soit la façon dont nous pâtissons des discours qui nous traversent. Et, comme tout affect - d'angoisse spécialement - elle n'est pas 3 C. Jullien.'Des sociétés malades de leur culture1in le Monde diplomatique. Manière de voir, no. 1,1987. sans objet, même si ce dernier est dur à nommer. Ainsi, dans la société capitaliste s'appellera-t-il plus-value, à quoi se ravalent tous les plus-dujouir dégradés, ou encore Souverain-Bien. Mais ces plus-du-jouir n'existent que dans un réel dont la saisie nous est impossible, même s'ils nous déterminent. Alors, société sans projet, se demandait-il encore? Certes pas: ces objets nous conduisent le plus sûrement du monde vers les pires désagréments, par des voies réelles et fléchées, quand bien même serionsnous sans projets articulables. Ils nous tirent: voix, regards, apparences, look divers, media. Le réel comme tel n'est qu'effet des discours qui le produisent, dans lesquels nous sommes tous pris. Alors quelle action mener? Au moins, situer cette part d'impossible à démontrer qu'emporte avec lui tout discours, cette part qui est son réel et sans l'appréciation duquel nos actions ne valent pas pour actes, mais pour chimères et semblants. En tout cas, le monde moderne ne s'est certainement pas complexifié: il est devenu d'une clarté brutale, sinon aveuglante. Mais nous sommes ses aveugles. Férocité sociale Tout cela est parfaitement conforme à l'atmosphère économique où nous sommes: crainte pour la survie, compétition effrénée, rivalités exténuantes. Le Maître moderne étant aveuglé, il ne sait même plus qu'il sert lui-même la plus-value qui le commande. Quant aux institutions, nous savons qu'elles sont avant tout, des phénomènes d'écriture fabriquant des places et qui manœuvrent les identifications. De fait, cette méconnaissance, refoulement, camouflage, les institutions tombent en plein dans ce que Legendre appelle la férocité sociale. Le juridisme accru des rapports sociaux et l'appel de l'Etat, comme à l'Administration témoignent alors d'une soumission remarquable à ce monstre qui s'appelle l'amour social, dont la seule finalité est de faire en sorte que les sujets se reproduisent à moindre frais pour faciliter la circulation des objets ready-made de la consommation qu'ils sont d'ailleurs devenus eux-mêmes. Il s'agit alors bel et bien d'une guerre pour la maîtrise de la distribution des places dans l'échange, et cette guerre ne va pas sans un goût étrange du contrôle et de la frénésie organisationnelle. Fureur à produire de l'institution, labelisée, garantie. Et dans cette guerre, il s'agit, comme souvent dans les guerres, beaucoup moins d'oppositions des uns aux autres, que d'identification des uns aux autres. Car on est toujours plus ou moins captif des voies et des enjeux que l'on a promu soi-même, en ignorant qu'ils ne sont que la réitération d'enjeux sociaux, économiques, culturels qui nous gouvernent à notre insu. Lacan disait: 'Li'nconscient, c'est le social'. Formule qui a pu heurter nombre de psychanalystes. Pourtant l'inconscient nous est extérieur, c'est le Discours de l'Autre, anonyme, impersonnel, qui n'est nul sujet mais une grande gueule et qui nous gouverne, cepedant que, comme il n'y a dénonciation collective, les énoncés prolifèrent. Lacan disait: 'Dans la névrose, le rapport à l'Autre a toute son importance. Dans la perversion, le rapport au phallus a toute son importance. Dans la psychose, le rapport au corps propre a toute importance'. Or, ce que nous voyons se développer est bel et bien cecci: (1) Le rapport à VAutre fait de moins en moins problème, puisque tous les sujets deviennent eux-mêmes les objets interchangeables d'un échange économique généralisé et unifiant. La problématique est donc de moins en moins névrotique; (2) Le rapport au phallus prend de plus en plus d'importance dans la captation du désir de la clientèle. On se présente comme l'Autre dont la maîtrise phallique peut capter son désir. C'est 'le plus' (je psychanalyse 'plus', je lave 'plus' blanc, je gère ‘plus', mon père est 'plus', etc.) et donc la perversion s'amplifie; (3) Avec comme conséquence rétroactive, circulaire, une exclusion de l'Autre. Les citoyens sont alors d'autant plus fragmentés qu'ils sont gérés par un monstre monobloc, sans division subjective, mais que - cette opération - elle est passée réellement en eux. Coup que nous appellerons: celui de se faire passer pour l'Autre de l'Autre. Opération de forclusion du Nom-du-père, c'est-à-dire verwerfung de la castration, propre au capitalisme; (4) Le centralisme - particularité française, auparavant - va croissant sous la forme de multinationales supra-gouvernementales qui sont les vrais centres décideurs de la vie économique, sociale et culturelle; (5) Du coup le Maître (SI) en est conforté et le savoir (S2) passe à son service. Le moi bon pour la casse Le Maître moderne se fiche éperdument du savoir. De toute façon, le savoir est à son service. Il lui suffit que ça marche. Et plus le savoir (S2) veut se faire reconnaître comme savoir, plus it conforte (SI), le Maître. Ce qui explique la phobie institutionnelle, publique et poltique de beaucoup de psychanalystes qui n'osent même plus ouvrir la bouche sur leur vie collective et leur vie de citoyens, mais de cela ils payent le prix, comme Fenichel et ses amis. On lira avec intérêt le livre de Russel Jacoby sur Fenichel. Le titre original était: Destins de la gauche freudienne. A voir ce panorama - et il est certain que je suis en-deça de la main, étant mal au fait des dernières subtilités de la vie économique - il devient clair que c'est le social qui prend prévalence d'un réel, au point que le nom propre y devienne valeur monnayable, comme les autres fragments du corps. En somme, ce qu'il s'agit de sauver, c'est le moi, mais en l'occasion c'est l 'objet a que le moi sert, c'est-à-dire que le moi lui-même ne sera pas sauvé: il ne peut être que déclassable, bon pour la casse, selon la conjoncture du marché. Les mystères de l'Etat, seraient-ils psychanalytiques, sont peut-être insondables, mais passon cœur, et son amour vous est garanti. Les événements de 1989 en Chine illustrent bien la collusion du maoïsme avec le familialo-centrisme chrétien identifiant dans sa pente totalitaire le Nom avec le texte sacré et le corps. On pourrait appeler érotomanie d'Etat ce type de montage, conduisant à la chaîne de scenarii divers, dont - entre autres - une psychanalyse prêt-à-porter, psychanalyse de confection, comme la psychiatre d'ailleurs - et davantage encore. It faut remarquer par exemple, du côté des hôpitaux, comment en France, l'une des mesures de tel gouvernement des dernières années a été de subordonner les médecins à leur directuer administratif, cependant que se développait la notion d'hôpital-entreprise. Quant à la psychanalyse, elle risque fort de devenir une 'psychanalyse-entreprise' avec comme discours dominant, celui bien connu dans les Forces armées: celui du 'rendre compte', 'justifier', 'garantir', ’assurer'. Ce discours, au service de l'évaluation et de la quantification, croit dans une science qu'il a mal digérée - parce que la Science n'y croit pas elle-même - cependant que la Science est mise à son service. L'actualité paranoïaque ... Vous l'avez compris: ce jeu de fictions institutionnelles rédigées par la fausse Science et l’Administration n’apporte de réponses qu'aux questions fictives posées. A question fictive, réponse fictive, cependant qu'à côté le réel prolifère comme réponse vraie, mais méconnue. Tout se passe comme si nous assistions à la tentative d'homogénéiser: 1. Le réel de l'entreprise; 2. Le réel de celui qui fait savoir; 3. Le réel de qui a le savoir-faire. Je m'explique: le réel de qui a le savoirfaire s'abdique devant le réel de celui qui fait savoir, sous couvert de ce qu'ils auraient besoin l'un de l'autre. Quant au réel de celui qui fait savoir, il s'abdique devant le réel de l'entreprise sous couvert de ce qu’ils auraient besoin l’un de l'autre. în fine, conjoncture obscurcissante où c’est le savoirfaire comme éthique qui - devenu esclave - fonctionne au service d'une entreprise qui se prend pour une culture. Il est vrai que si le discours dominant est celui de la recherche du meilleur rapport qualité/prix, s'il faut ’en donner à chacun pour son argent', et si - en plus - il faut savoir se vendre, cela augure très précisément des combats que nous aurons à mener. Pour me résumer: l'actualité est paranoïaque, c'est-à-dire que le monde devient sans trou et que tout doit y être prévu. Autant par son extension que les phénomènes sociaux de fond qui y poussent. D'une part: désagrégation des modalités symboliques qui assuraient dans les groupes humains transmission et génération, en garantissant la stabilité de leur horizon, mondialisation sans butée des échanges et des phénomènes migratoires. D'autre part - et l'un ne va pas sans l’autre - montée en force de la science véhiculant l'exigence et la certitude qu'elle nous débarrasse de toutes contigences cependant que rejetant le sujet - elle en fait le plus contingent des objets. Bref: décapitonnage. Alors voit-on monter les phénomènes ségrégatifs, tensions jalouses et revendicatives, guerres de religion cependant que nul Dieu ne vient répondre à l'appel érotomaniaque d'élus qui - dans un appel sans médiation à l'Autre - ne peuvent qu'éprouver la déception de leurs espoirs, comme leurs compensations imaginaires exaltées. Parallèlement, les fractures générationnelles accentuées rejettent pères et fils dans une position radicalement autre, les mettant en posture de ne s'autoriser que d'un discours - la science comme bien commun en fait partie - qui va jusqu'à invalider et court-circuiter les gouvernements: ce sont les Biens qui gouvernent, par la promesse d'une jouissance Autre, cependant, que les responsables eux-mêmes se réduisent à l'état de fantoches artificiellement animés. Sommés de répondre aux tension, ils n'y parviennent que sous la forme d'idéologies unificatrices et unitaires, imposant la multiplication des règlements, procédures de contrôle, législation 'communes'. Mais la demande est assurément de 'plus de droit'. Mais de quel Droit s'agit-il? Du droit d'un sujet à bénéficier d'une existence pacifiée parmi les siens, à quoi aucun droit ne peut répondre? Ou du Droit du code, comme prothèse sans cesse augmentée, à la carence du droit symbolique? Dans ce cas, elle n'y apporte qu'une réponse quantitative sur le mode impossible d'une jouissance qui devrait être également répartie et identique pour tous, pendant que la sexualité, comme la sexuation - ordonnées phalliquement - en prennent un coup. 36 Quand au lieu, évidé, de la vérité, il se comble d'un vrai dont la forme de bien de consommation prend la place de Maître aveugle et anonyme de Tout et que nulle butée ne vient plus interrompre sa tyrannie. Le corps des hommes n'y échappe pas, dont chaque partie, désormais démembrable, transplantable, voire fécondable, l'offre à une capture monnayable et que chacun - juridiquement - doit tenir le discours que sa place dans l'administration des biens lui assigne. Ainsi se véhiculent des énoncés sans énonciation, collaborant le lieu de l'Autre à celui du code (devenu civil et pénal) imputant à chacun une castration collective inexistante, cependant que - dans un réel projectif prolifèrent oppositions et conflits effectifs en réponse à l'Un. A la jubilation mégalomaniaque qui fait de chacun le citoyen d'un monde qui gravite autour de lui, répond pour le même citoyen l'effondrement micromaniaque par où il témoigne que, dans ce monde, il n'est rien, avec l'agression narcissique concomitante. ... et hypocondriaque Quant à la faute et à la dette: elle est devenue impayable (cf: le tiersmonde), renvoyé à l'Autre incarné, le voisin le plus proche, dont ne me sépare plus nul continent ni mer, cependant qu'elle est pour moi-même éludée au titre des dommages irréparables que j'ai subis: sans auteur et sans objet, s'y substituent la crainte, la haine et le tremblement. Alors, faute de castration, l'objet a, non échu, incarcéré dans le langage le rend inapte à l'échange cependant que - faute de coupure signifiante, liée au Nom-du-Père - c'est la décollation capitale qui prévaut: de même que chacun est tenu de produire sous la forme d'un 'plus' ce qui met en souffrance son discours, il ne peut le faire qu'au nom d'un 'mon père est plus', selon l'heureuse expression d'Elie Doumit, fiction qui recreuse dans le réel le manque dans le symbollique qu'elle était supposée combler. Si l'actualité que nous rappelons est juste, c'est alors une actualité sans limites ni spatiales, ni temporelles, ni corporelles. C'est l'actualité hypocondriaque de l'objet qui ronge - névrose actuelle - celui qui ne parvient pas à s’en diviser et cherche dans l'autre la frappe - réelle celle-là qui ne parviendra pas à opérer soulagement d'une complétude intolérable. Actualité d'un sujet universel qui - dans son hypocondrie planétaire - tend à sa fission, éventuellement nucléaire. Address for correspondence: Association Freudienne Internationale 15 Rue Bouchardor 75010 Paris France 38 THE FOLLOWER* Helen Sheehan As the President of the United States of America William Jefferson Clinton signed the new Electronics Treaty at Gateway Computers in September of this year, we are reminded that home may no longer be a space we occupy in language but a glint in the smooth seductions of a radar beam. Kathym Holmquist, in The Irish Times, put it succinctly thus: 'The Irish Dream of the 1990's celebrates the computer and seeks a better quality of life through the profitable movement of information through cyberspace'.1 It is almost a commonplace now to say that profound social changes are underway in the Ireland of the 90's.2 We can say that these changes began in the 1960's. An Ireland on the run like Richard Kimble, in The Fugitive, as exemplified in Michael O'Louglin's poem of the same name, published in 1982.3 In the hour before the metro opens I remember you, Richard Kimble with my hands dug deep in my jacket pockets walking the streets of a foreign city. I am indebted to my colleagues at the Milltown Institute of Theology and Philosophy, Brid O'Brien and Brendan Woods S. J. for pointing me in the right direction. 1K. Holmquist in The Irish Times. September 9th1998. p.12. 2 It is interesting to note that, as J.J. Lee remarks, the 60's were marked in actual terms in Ireland by a reduction of one third in terms of emigration/ compared to the 50's. J.J. Lee. 'Emigration, a contemporary perspective' in Migrations: The Irish at Home and Abroad. Ed Richard Kearney. Dublin, Wolfhound Press, 1990 p.33 3M. O'Loughlin. 'The Fugitive' in Atlantic Blues. Dublin, Raven Arts, 1982 p.38. But if the 1960's are remembered as the fugitive years in more ways than one, the 1970's are characterised by the particular modernisation of Ireland and are marked also by being a decade of the return. The symbolic verification of Ireland's entry into the 20th century was acknowledged when on January 1st 1970, half crowns went out of circulation to be replaced by the new 50 pence coin.4 On March 21st of that year All Kinds of Everything sung by a certain Dana won the Eurovision Song Contest in Amsterdam. Ireland had indeed arrived in the new Europe. 1970 was also the year in which the Catholic Bishops announced that it was no longer obligatory to abstain from eating meat on Fridays and the hierarchy's ban on Catholic attendance at Trinity College was lifted. It was also the year in which Martin O'Cadhain, regarded as the greatest modem writer in the Irish language died. For some the fugitive years were apparently over in earnest - after being found not guilty in the Arms conspiracy trial Charles Haughey called on Jack Lynch to resign as Taoiseach. There was a lot of movement that year too, some less conspicuous than others. The Irish School of Ecumenics was inaugurated in Milltown Park, Dublin. St. Vincent's Hospital moved to its new £5,000,000.00 site at Elm Park, after 136 years in St. Stephen's Green. The final phase of the transfer was to move 73 patients by ambulance. That was the year Cormac Gallagher went to Paris, France. In 1974, Jacques Lacan came to Ireland. He came not merely in a personal capacity nor on a flying visit to see for himself the land of the sinthome about which he has said: In so far as the unconscious is knotted to the sinthome which is what is proper to each individual, that it can be said that Joyce, as we read somewhere, identifies himself with the individual. He claims the privilege of having gone to the 4 J. O'Donnell. Ireland - the past 20 years. An illustrated Chronology 1967-1986. Institute of Public Administration, 1967 - 1986. Dublin, 1986 p. 22 Unless otherwise noted all information regarding the events of 1970 and 1974 are from this source. 40 extreme to embody the symptom in himself, by which, he escapes all possible death by being reduced to a structure, which is that of the LOM (man).5 It looks as if he came to stay. Analysing the effects of this visit by this important but then largely unknown visitor to our shores in 1974 will need more time than the scope of this present paper allows, but the least we can say is that he continues to leave his mark. This very modem link to France provides a kind of lifeline for many who have been traumatised by an altogether too incestuous relationship with our neighbouring island, where for too many Irish people England has for too long been a reminder of how close we are to that first stranger who is so near but who is also so hostile. John Hume’s call in 1988 for a 'new republicanism’ bears witness to this oppressive relationship and our need to forge new kinds of links. The real new republicanism (is) the development of processes which will allow people to preserve their culture, rights and dignity; to promote their well being and have a means of controlling the forces which will affect their lives; rather than being any reversal of the national destiny this will allow us better to fulfil our potential as a people; to contribute to our world; to rediscover the cultural interaction between Ireland and Europe; to re-involve ourselves in political relations with those on the continental mainland and to properly enjoy the inchoate European outlook and vision which was lost in our oppressive and obsessive relationship with Britain.6 5 J. Lacan. Seminaire Du 16 Juin 1975. 'Joyce le Symptôme I' in Joyce avec Lacan.. Ed. Navarin, Paris, 1987 p. 28. 'Lom' is the homophone of the French 'Vhomme' (my translation) 6 J. Hume. 1Europe of the Regions' in Across the Frontiers, Ireland in the 1990's, Ed. R. Kearney, Dublin, Wolfhound Press, 1988. p.56 41 1974 was a very busy year. Brian Faulkner resigned as Leader of the Unionist Party, but continued to lead the pledged Unionist Group in the Northern Ireland assembly. The McCormick report, The General Practitioner in Ireland published that year, recommended a comprehensive state health service. Seanad fiireann refused the second reading of Mary Robinson's Family Planning Bill. Sr. Stanislaus Kennedy of the Kilkenny Social Services Centre was appointed to chair the new advisory committee to initiate and co-ordinate pilot schemes to combat poverty while Charles J. Haughey bought Inishvickillane, a mile long uninhabited island in the Blasket archipelago, as a summer home. In May 1974 a young couple succeeded in their High Court action to have declared unconstitutional that Section of the 1952 Adoption Act, which prohibited them from adopting the wife’s son, who was bom before her marriage, because his religion differed from that of his mother. Also in May of that year the five month old Northern Ireland Executive collapsed because of deep divisions between Unionist and S.D.L.P. ministers over whether to negotiate with the organisers of the Loyalist anti Surmingdale strike, and the Northern Ireland Secretary Merlyn Rees refused the request of Brian Faulkner and his five fellow Unionist Ministers to negotiate with the Ulster Workers Council. Some people were incarcerated that year for their crimes. Dr. Rose Dugdale was sentenced to nine years imprisonment at the Special Criminal Court in Dublin for receiving nineteen stolen paintings from the home of Sir Alfred Beit. She pleaded 'proudly and incorruptibly guilty'.7 Ritchie Ryan, Minister for Public Service, announced that Irish was no longer obligatory for entry into the Civil Service or for promotion within it. Roy Jenkins, Britain's Home Secretary, introduced tough new measures in the Prevention of Terrorism Bill; proscription of the I.R. A., the arrest without warrant of suspected persons, and control of travel from the Republic and Northern Ireland to Britain. In December of that year 7 The Irish Times, June 25th 1974. p.3. 42 eighty delegates in Dublin decided to break away from the official I.R.A. and to form the Irish Republican Socialist Party. Cearbhall O'D&laigh was installed as President of Ireland following on the death of Erskine Childers. Liam Cosgrave was Taoiseach. Ireland's soccer team defeated the Soviet Union 3 - 0 at Dalymount Park, in a European Nations Cup game. Don Givens scored all three goals. Kilkenny won the all Ireland hurling final defeating Limerick by 3.19 to 1.13. That year the Rev. Ian Paisley announced 'we do not accept the word of the slanderous bachelor who lives on the banks of the Tiber'.8 It was also the year in which Donal Foley writing in Man Bites Dog remarked; a family who claimed direct descent from Brian Boru tried last night to take over Aras an Uachtarain. They were rejected on the grounds that the official records made no mention of the Boru family. The spokes man for Ireland appealed to the people yesterday to make their claim in an orderly fashion. There would be plenty of pay back for everybody he said. He announced that a national hooley of thanksgiving would be held at Tara.9 That was the year Cormac Gallagher returned from Paris, France. Cormac Gallagher, no more than the rest of us may not be able to claim descent from Brian Boru but the records tell us the name Gallagher goes back further than that. In Sloinnte Gaedeal is Gall, O'Gallcobair10 is 8Ian Paisley in Sayings of the Year, the Irish Times Review, December 23rd 1974. p.2. 9D. Foley. 'Man Bites Dog' in The Irish Times 4thJune, 1974. p.10 10 The Punctum, in Irish 'Bualadh1, which initially in Irish Orthography was used to express the lenition of T and 's’ and later in free variation with 'h' in various digraphs began in the 19th century to replace 'h' altogether, in the printed text. With the advent of the New State, Roman type, (an C16 Romhinach) began to be used extensively in publications, and with the reforms, proposed in Litriti na Gaeilge, the bualadh disappeared. listed as 'the name of a numerous and once powerful family in Tirconnell, who derive their descent from Maolchoba, King of Ireland in the 7th century. As Marshals of O'Donnells' forces the O'Gallaghers took a prominent part in all the military movements of Cineal Conaill during the 14th and subsequent centuries1.11 According to McLysaght; ... the name of this sept. O'Gallchobhair in Irish signifies descendant of Gallchobhar or Gallagher, who was himself descended from the King of Ireland who reigned from 642 654. The O'Gallaghers claim to be the senior and most royal family of the CinSal Connaill. Their territory extended over a wide area in the modem baronies of Raphoe and Tirhugh Co. Donegal and their chiefs were notable as marshals of O'Donnells' military forces from the fourteenth to the sixteenth century. The principal branch of the sept were seated at Ballybeit and Ballynaglack.12 What's in a name? Psychoanalysis knows something of the price one pays for one’s name. Moses learned that too at the burning bush when he said to God 'I am to go, then, to the sons of Israel and say to them 'the God of your fathers has sent me to you1. But if they ask me what his name is what am I to tell them? And God said to Moses 1 am who I am'.13 Freud in his monumental Moses and Monotheism tells us in the very first lines how important is the act of naming: To deprive a people of the man whom they take pride in as the greatest of their sons is not a thing to be gladly or 11 Rev. P. Woulfe. Sloinnte Gaedeal is Gall, Mac an Goill agus a Mhac, Baile Atha Cliath, 1923. p. 538 12 Ed. McLysaght. Irish Families, their names, arms, and origins. Dublin, Allen Figgis, 1972 pp. 1 154. n Exodus. 3.13-14. The Jerusalem Bible. London, Darton Longman and Todd, 1966. 44 carelessly undertaken least of all by someone who is himself one of them. But we cannot allow any such reflection to induce us to put the truth aside in favour of what are supposed to be national interests; and moreover, the clarification of a set of facts may be expected to bring us a gain in knowledge.14 There are four very important issues mentioned by Freud here in the very first lines which set the tone for all of what is to follow. The first thing we notice is that Moses is the greatest of Israel's sons. The Bible does not call Moses a father. The Book of Genesis tells us: 'Yahweh appeared to Abraham and said: 'It is to your decesendants that I will give this land'.15 So that Abraham is the ancestor of the chosen people, but the question for Freud as for all of us is how does a son become a father, or, to be more precise Freud calls Moses a 'father figure' by that he means that Moses is a name of the father for Freud. Secondly, Freud too is a Jew, thirdly this still being the case, he continues, I am not going to put the truth aside in favour of any kind of nationalism or ethnicity, and fourthly let us do a little bit more work and let us see whether we can get some more clarification, some new insight into the matter. Now, some interpreters of Freud have seen in this Freud's total identification of himself with Moses. I don't think this is the case. We see he sees both himself and Moses as 'sons'. Here, we have Freud calling Moses the greatest of the sons of Israel. Freud would have known that to call a person by his name - to know the proper name - was to give power to the person named and it seems to me that Freud wanted to start at the beginning - before the name - and find out if he can call him by his proper name. In this way it's as if Freud is really beginning an analysis because when we first go into analysis we are not able to recognise things and people properly - that is by their proper name. 14S. Freud. (1939 [1934-38]) Moses and Monotheism: Three Essays. S.E., XXIII, p. 19. 15 Genesis op rit, 12:7:8 James Plastaras (a Christian exegete) tells us: 'Moses was the first of the prophets and the prototype of the prophetic office'.16 So too Freud recognises that Moses is the greatest of Israel's sons, who set the Jewish people free, who gave them their laws and founded their religion. So, although he regards himself as a son of Israel we cannot say that he identifies with Moses. Look at what Moses did for the Jewish people. This Freud says and accepts. There are other important issues raised in Part I, Moses an Egyptian. The first thing that fascinates Freud is Moses' name. What does the name Moses mean? He is obsessed with trying to find out what this name means and he quotes the Biblical interpretation as 'he who is drawn out of the water', that is, in the passive sense. But, he is not happy with that interpretation because he argues that it can only mean 'he who draws out', that is, in the active sense. He believes that the name Moses is derived from the Egyptian vocabulary. Yet he concludes this part of section I by saying: 'it emerges that the recognition that the name of Moses is Egyptian has not been looked upon as affording decisive evidence of his origin and that no further conclusions have been drawn from it'.17 This Egyptian background of Moses is Freud's starting place for his construction of the prehistory of Judaism. Freud does indeed take this Egyptian name seriously, as he tries to come to terms with the consequences of this name. Plastaras tells us 'the name Moses is really of Egyptian origin, meaning 'bom of' or 'son of' - because names were supposed to 'say something' the Semite would always be puzzled by a foreign name or a loan word and would always try to find an etymology for it in terms of his own language'.18 Freud believes in Moses as an actual historical person and he is not for example just a legend as someone like Ed Meyer, the historian, would have him. Why was Freud so obsessed with the name - Moses1name? Freud somewhere knew that to name someone, to know him by name was to 16 J. Plastaras. The God of Exodus, The Theology of the Exodus Narratives. Milwaukee, The Bruce Publishing Company, 1966. p.5. 17S. Freud, op.cit., pp.9-10 18 J. Plastaras, op.cit., p.42 46 define him. Freud knew that to name someone is the first Symbolic act par excellence. Even before we are bom we are named - our parents have (hopefully) been thinking about us and have invested us with all sorts of unconscious desires and motivations, but in giving us a name they have anchored us in the Symbolic order. Of course, the Bible tells us that Yahweh says to Israel 'Do not be afraid for I have redeemed you. I have called you by your name, you are mine'.19 As Jacques Hassoun notes 'To name is the first act, Symbolic par excellence that the Biblical myth gives as a privilege to us humans; Adam does not designate, He names. From then on we can say that naming comes from language itself, which precedes the Imaginary part of representation'.20 Only Yahweh can designate because to designate involves indicating one's destiny. To designate means to indicate the whole function and destiny of a subject. On the contrary to name means that you can understand it, control it. In Semitic thought, knowledge of a name gave power over the thing named; to know God's name was to be able to call on Him and to be certain of a hearing. The true God does not make himself man's slave in this way by revealing a name expressive of his essence; this refusal to reveal is contained in the formula, Ehyeh Asher Ehyeh (I am who I am, I am what I am) having an active dynamic presence, which in the third person becomes Yahweh 'He is'. Yahweh means that he is there ready to act, ready to help. Yahweh is part of the verb 'to be' from Raya - to be.21 If we understand it in this way the name does not define God; for the people of Israel, it will always call to mind God’s great deliverance of His people and the divine generosity, fidelity and power that prompted it. In Christian thought this interpretation brings out the transcendence of a God for whom man can never find a worthy name. Biblical tradition has preferred to take Ehyeh 19Isaiah. 43:1-2 op.cit. 20]. Hassoun. 'Des Noms du père' in Che Vuoi? Actualité de Totem et Tabou, No. 3 Revue du cercle Freudien, Editions L’Harmattan, ( my translation). 21 I am grateful to my colleague at Milltown, Paddy Byrne. C.M. for careful advice on the theological implications of Moses and Monotheism. asher Ehyeh as meaning ‘I am the One who is, I am who am': the name Yahweh would then express not necessarily the absolute nature of God's essence but at least God's unlimited existence as opposed to the 'nothingness' of the Gods. Lacan states in The Psychoses: Indeed it's one of the most profound characteristics of the mental foundation of the Judaeo-Christian tradition that against it speech clearly profiles the being of the I as its ultimate ground. On all the essential questions the subject always finds himself in a position to justify him as L The I who says I am the one who am, this I, absolutely alone, is the one who radically sustains the thou in his interpellation.22 André Chouraqui says in his Moïse that this is not a sufficient translation because 'Ehyeh asher Ehyeh', may be rightfully translated as being in the past and the future as well as in the present. Therefore Chouraqui suggests ’that I am who I am seems to be saying to a questioner who is too curious: you wish to know my name? You will not know it. I am who I am, or I will be who I will be1. But, Chouraqui continues; ... the text says exactly the contrary of this interpretation. In effect the asher which joins these two Ehyeh is the most subtle of conjunctions. It could also be translated in a more accurate way by two points, thereby eliding this equivocal who; I am: I am.23 Raymond Abba, remarks: 'the origin of the name has been the subject of much controversy and there is as yet no general agreement among Old 22 J. Lacan.. The Psychoses. Book HI trans. R. Grigg, London, Routledge, 1993. p.287. 23 A. Chouraqui. Moise. Edition du Rocher, Paris 1995. p.148 (my translation). 48 Testament Scholars'.24 Abba suggests that the name is extremely ancient and there is thus considerable support for the Biblical tradition that the use of this divine name goes back to primeval times. The link between Yahweh and the God of the Patriarchs is made in Exodus. 'Yahweh is the God of your fathers'.25 And by virtue of this already existing bond he can speak of Israel 'as my people'. Abba also says: The divine name is always associated with a sense of mystery as well as of presence. Yahweh is not thought of as dwelling at Sinai as some have maintained; he 'comes down1 upon the mountain to the accompaniment of thunder and lightning, fire and cloud. His presence is unapproachable As the Holy One of Israel, he is the Wholly Other. He is unapproachable even for the seraphim who sing trisagion with covered faces and feet. This is best understood as a plural of intensity expressing Yahweh's dominion over all the powers in heaven and on earth.26 S. Mowinckel, in Two Sources of the Predeuteronomic Primeval History says 'Yahweh is not telling his name to one who does not know it - the whole conversation presupposes that the Israelites know this name already'.27 Similarly E. Jacob says 'We do not have in the Exodus narrative the revelations of a new name but the explanation of a name already known to Moses, which in that solemn hour is discovered to be charged with a content the richness of which he was far from expecting'.28 24 R. Abba. The Journal of Biblical Literature, Vol. LXXX, Society of Biblical Literature, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania U.S.A p.320. 25 Exodus. 3:13:-16. 26 Abba, op.cit, p.327. 27 Abba, op.cit., p.323. 28 E. Jacob. The Theology of the Old Testament trans. A.W. Heathcote and P.J. Alcock, London, Hodder and Stoughton, 1958. pp. 49-50. 49 The revelation given to Moses at the burning bush was not therefore the revelation of a new and hitherto unknown name 'it was the disclosure of the real significance of a name long known'.29 What of the name O’Gallchobhair? The first mention of the name O'Gallchobhair or O'Gallagher in the Annals O f The Four Masters is in 1231 A.D., which describes it thus: O'Gallchobhair or O'Gallaghers, derived from Gallchobhair, a warrior, were a clan of note in Donegal in the baronies of Raphoe and Tirhugh and had a castle at Ballyshannon and also possessed the castle at Lifford and were commanders of O'Donnells army.30 It is interesting to note that Lacan refers to the four Masters in Joyce le Symptome I when he says 'I am not an academic, contrary to what is said about my being a professor or master or other such banter. I am an analyst. This surely is a homophony of the Annals of the Four Masters of which Joyce in Finnegan's makes much, and which are the basis of the Annals of Ireland. I am another sort of analyst'.31 An 'ancestral impulse' as Professor Richard Kearney puts it,32 exciting as it may be, could also prove dangerous if not tempered by the Symbolic. Thus, love of a country. Begins as attachment to our own field of action and comes to find that action of little importance though never indifferent. History may be servitude History may be freedom, see now they vanish 29 Abba, op.cit, p.323 30 The Annals of Ireland. Trans, from the original Irish of The Four Masters by Owen Connelan. Dublin, Brian Geraghty, 1845. p.53. 31 Joyce avec Lacan, op.cit., p.23. 32 R. Kearney. Migrations: The Irish at Home and Abroad. Dublin, Wolfhound Press. 1990. the faces and places, with the self which, as it could, loved To become renewed, transfigured, in another pattern.33 Historians like Myles Dillon, former senior Professor at the Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies, says that with the fifth century we enter a new phase of history. The prestige of written research claims to displace oral tradition and though we now know that our written annals and many records of institutions of the early millennium are themselves based on oral tradition; ... the fact of their subsequent written form when incorporated into the annalistic histories gives them a place for the first time in the historiography of Europe. How far these records are to be depended upon is a very difficult question and one which is at the moment much debated.34 Seatrun Ceitinn, in his celebrated Forus Feasa ar Eirinn (the foundation of knowledge about Ireland), mentions O’Gallchobhair for the first time in Volume III when he is describing how the Kings after the time of St. Patrick were inaugurated. Now on the occasion of the their being inaugurated the chronicler came forward bearing the book called the Instruction for Kings, in which there was a brief summary of the customs and laws of the country, and where it was explained how God and the people would reward the doing of good, and the punishment that awaited the king and his descendants if he did not carry out the principles of justice 33 T.S. Eliot 'Little Gidditig' in Collected Poems 1909-1962. London, Faber and Faber, 1967. p.219. 34 M. Dillon and N. Chadwick. The Celtic Realms, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1967. p.59. 51 and equity, which the Book of Kings and Instructions for Kings direct to put into practice’.35 Ceitinn continues: It was the Chronicler’s function to place a wand in the hand of each Lord on his inauguration, and, on presenting his wand he made it known to the populace that the Lord or King need not take up arms thenceforth to keep his country in subjection, but that they should obey his wand as a scholar obeys his master. For, as the wise scholar loves and obeys and is grateful to his master, in the same way subjects are bound to their Kings, for it is with the wand of equity and justice that he directs his subjects and not with the edge of the weapon of injustice. The wand which the ollamh places in the King’s hand is altogether white, as a token of truth as symbolised by the whiteness of the rod, since whiteness is likened to truth and blackness to falsehood. The reason why the wand is straight is to signify to the people and the tribes that the King is bound to be straight and faultless, without bias in his words and judgements between friends and enemies, between the strong and the weak, as if there were a contention between both his hands. It was at Tara on Leic na Riogh that every one of the Kings of Ireland who possessed the kingdom of all Ireland, by the consent of the ollamhs and the nobles, used to be inaugurated before the Faith and by the consent of the Church and of the ollamhs ever since the faith. 35 S. Ceitinn. Foras Feasa Ar Eirinn. An Treas imleabar, ina fbuil An Dara Leabar den Stair. Cumann na Sgribeann Gaedhilge, London, 1908. p. 10. 52 At Cill Mic Creann&in, O'Domhnaill was inaugurated and it was O'Fiorghail who inaugurated him and O'Gallchobhair was his marshal of the hosts.36 It is important to note that Seatrun Ceitinn's work is regarded as an apologia against the detractors of Ireland in the form of a history of the Country from pre-Christian times down to the Anglo Norman invasion of 1169. This being said, his work was hugely influential and informed generations of ordinary people about their history in a way that gave them a better sense of their beginning and their destiny. Padraic 6 Conaire's poignant description of a tormented and displaced man, called Miche£l, at a social gathering in a part of London called Little Ireland bears witness to the power of Forus Feasa or Eirinn. There would be a man there who could relate the contents of Keating's History of Ireland as well as a man who knew nothing about it. And if somebody were to disagree with anything the savant said, he would just go to the big trunk he had brought with him from Ireland and take out a parcel wrapped in linen. He would open the parcel and take out a large book in manuscript. And how careful he was of that book. He would show you in black and white where you had been wrong. And when he closed the book to put it away he would look at you as if to say 'now, what have you to say for yourself?' But, he never said a word ,37 A noticeable aspect of An Ceitinneach's description of this inauguration ceremony is the Symbolic one. In fact the Real, Symbolic and Imaginary aspects are woven so closely together here that they do indeed form a knot. This is the inauguration of a King, not a crowning so there is something of an initiation at work. We are safely in the Symbolic. The 36 ibid, pp 11-13. 37 P. O'Conaire. Deoraiocht. (Exile) trans. G. MacEoin. C16 Iar Chonnachta, 1994. p.104. Real is most poignantly attested to in the marriage-like aspect of King and Country, watched over by God and the people. The wand is something light, so the King will not rule with a rod of iron. The weapon will be the word. It is also interesting to note that God and the people work together. The power of the word is stressed and the King is reminded of his duties and that there will be a Judgement. The Ollamh or the one of highest degree among the learned caste held the father's function and it was he who spoke the words. In a curious way, the more deeply Symbolic aspects of the ceremony are in the Imaginary or are capable of so becoming. After all 'whiteness is likened to truth' only if one wishes it to be so. The truth may be very black indeed. The Symbolic if insisted upon too much is in danger of becoming the Real and the only possible exit then becomes a reverie of a future which never comes. This eternal aspiration of the dawning of a new age is embodied in the word, passed down to the King who from the time of his inauguration will rule with justice and truth. As Brendan O'Buachalla, says; The heroic age of Irish literature was celebrated from within an ideoogy of Kingship and from the oldest texts we have available to us down to the poetry of the 19th century the golden age is always saved with the coming and the reign of the rightful king.38 The great Niall Noighiallach was one such King. 'Niall of the nine hostages' was high King of Ireland A.D. 379-40539 and from him O'Gallchobhair can claim descent. Niall has, as Thomas O'Rahilly explains, 'the distinction of being the ancestor of all but two of the long 38 B. O'Buachalla. Aisling Ghear, An Clochomhar tta. Baile Atha Cliath, 1996. p.467 (my translation) I have translated 'C6ir', by 'rightful' but it also implies the notions of 'just', 'proper' and 'duty1. 39 Historians are not totally agreed on these dates. According to Dillon these dates are a matter of considerable uncertainty. 54 line of kings of Ireland that ruled from the second quarter of the 5th century down to the Battle of Clontarf'.40 Therefore through a rather circuitous route it is possible to trace the Cin^al Conaill from which the name Gallagher descends back to a time earlier than the 7th century, contrary to what Woulfe and McLysaght state. Niall had four sons, Loegaire, Eogan, Enda and Conall. The Cineal Conaill is descended from the latter. Niall Noighiallach got his name because 'he obtained a hostage from each of the five provinces of Ireland and four from Britain or alternatively, five from Ireland, one from Alba (Scotland) and one from the Saxons, one from the Britons and one from the Franks, for Niall went to Letha and to Italy to seek a kingdom'.41 O'Rahilly advises us: ‘we may safely leave the foreign hostages out of account as a later embellishment and take it that Niall's nine hostages were Irishmen’.42 According to Ceitinn, Niall sent 'a fleet to Brittany in France, which is called Armorica for the purpose of plundering that country and they bought two hundred noble youths as captives to Ireland with them; and it was in this captivity that they brought Patrick, who was sixteen years old with them, and his two sisters Lupida and Darerca and many other captives besides'.43 While historians like Francis John Byrne agree that the tangled chronology of St. Patrick is 'inextricably linked with that of Niall'44 he would not go so far as to agree with Ceitinn that it was Niall who first brought the saint here. The link between these two great men of action will have to be left for another day. Niall Noighiallach is therefore fascinating from many points of view. But from a psychoanalytic viewpoint the story of his birth, upbringing and how he came to be called King is what proves most 40 T.F. O'Rahilly. Early Irish History and Mythology. Dublin, The Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies, 1946. p.217. 41 F,J. Byrne, op.cit., p.76. 42 T.F. O'Rahilly, op.cit., p.232. 43 S. Ceitinn, op.cit, Vol II. p. 375. 44 F.J. Byrne, op.cit, p. 78. interesting. T.F. O'Rahilly dismisses this story as 'mythology, pure and simple',45 while J. F. Byrne says 'of Niall's historicity there is little reason to doubt'.46 As regards the relationship between historical truth and material truth Freud himself had some very important things to say. This was a subject which much puzzled him during the writing of Moses and Monotheism. One could say that Moses is at least in part an attempt to come to terms with this relationship. He has above all shown that in writing the history of Moses he is in fact writing a name of the father, by which he has come to terms with both the external difficulties which were raging all around him at the time and internal difficulties of his own. Lacan too has shown the importance of writing, because as he says the unconscious has ’already been written down elsewhere'.47 As Lacan reminds us, we gain access to the unconscious 'in part in traditions and even in the legends, which, in a heroicized form bear (my) history'.48 As Niall Noighiallach is calling us, let us take a closer look at this period of Irish history which, according to Myles Dillon 'forms a bridge between the older purely oral records of prehistoric Ireland and the later written records. It is with the rise of Niall and his family to the chief power in central and northern Ireland that Irish history really begins'.49 The following is the story of Niall as taken from four principal sources."50 Eochu Mugmed6n, High King of Ireland, had five sons; Brian, Ailill, Fiachna, Fergus and Niall (the youngest). Mionnfionn was his queen and the mother of four sons, but Niall was the son of Caireann Chasdubh, the curly black haired daughter of Sachell Balb, King of the 45 T.F. O'Rahilly, op.cit, p.217 46J.F. Byrne, op.cit., p.71 47J. Lacan. Ecrits, Trans. A. Sheridan. London, Tavistock Publications, 1977. p.50 48 ibid, p.50. 49 M. Dillon,, op.cit. p.59. 50 (1) O'Rahilly, op,cit. (2) Byrne, op.cit . (3) Dillon, op.cit. (4) K. Meyer. Eriü. The Journal of the School of Irish Learning, Dublin. Vol. IV. Ed. K. Meyer., and O. Bergin. Dublin and London, 1910. p.91. All poetic citations are from the latter. 56 Saxons. Princess Caireann had been carried off on a raid and was kept as a slave. Mionnfionn, daughter of Fldeach the King of Munster was a bitter, jealous and ambitions woman, who set her heart upon having her favourite son Brian succeed his father as Ard Righ. Niall's brothers conceived deep envy towards him, through Mionnfionn's influence. It is also said that they loved their mother greatly but 'small love had they to Niall's mother'. Mionnfionn inflicted much hardship upon Caireann, who was compelled to draw water from the well. Even when she was pregnant with Niall she was compelled to do it and the child was bom in the open as she lay beside her pail. She dared not take up the child but left it there and none dared take it up for fear of Moinnfionn. Then Torna Eices, the Munster poet, also known as Toma the learned, came by and took up the child and he foresaw all that was to come. He took him up, reared and educated him 'keen, vigilant his government, he fostered him till he was nine years old1. When he had reached budding manhood Toma brought him back to Court to take his rightful place - much to his father's joy. Then Niall showing strength of character even in his early youth took his mother from her menial task and restored her to her place. 'Fresh as the grass about the Brugh, of rapid rushing waters full, was Niall's shining mantle about his shapely back, on the lordly height of Taillte's hill'. Mionnfionn was angry and called upon Eochu to judge between his sons as to who should succeed him. He referred to the matter to Sitchenn who was his drui and a prophet. Sitchenn set fire to the forge in which the five sons were at work. Their father, observed with interest Niall's distinctiveness of character, his good sense and judgement. While Brian saved the chariots from the fire, Ailill a shield and a sword, Fiachna the old forge trough and Fergus only a bundle of firewood, Niall carried out the bellows, the sledges, the anvil and anvil block - thereby saving the soul of the forge and the smithy from ruin. Then his father said 'it is Niall who should succeed me as Ard Riogh na h-Eireann'. 57 What is most striking about this legend is its utter dissimilarity to the description given by Otto Rank in his myth of the birth of the Hero. Rank's account is as follows: The hero is the child of most distinguished parents usually the son of a King, His origin is preceded by difficulties, such as continence, or prolonged barrenness, or secret intercourse of the parents due to external prohibition or obstacles. During or before the pregnancy, there is a prophecy in the form of a dream or oracle, cautioning against his birth and usually threatening danger to the father (or his representative). As rule, he is surrendered to the water, in a box. He is then saved by animals, or by lowly people (shepherds) and is suckled by a female animal or by a humble woman. After he has grown he finds his distinguished parents, in a highly versatile fashion. He takes his revenge on his father on the one hand, and is acknowledged on the other. Finally, he achieves rank and honours.51 Niall, as in Rank's account, is indeed the son of a king but there the analogy ends. Niall was not brought up by 'lowly' people but by a distinguished poet, who adopted him and reared him as his own. This custom, which is typical of Irish legends according to Clemence Ramnoux, 'represents a semi instinctive defense of primitive man against the dangers felt from relationships between men and women of the same blood within a closed family group'.52 Rank points out: 'it is noteworthy in the first place that the hostile attitude of the hero towards his parents concerns 51 O. Rarik. The Myth of the Birih of the Hero, and other nmtings. P. Freund (Ed), New York, Vintage Books. Random House, 1932. p. 65 52 C. Ramnoux. 'La rivalité entre père et fils dan la legende Irlandaise' in Psyché Revue Internationale de Psychanalyse et des sciences de l'homme. Numéro 13-14 Paris 1977 p.1357 (my translation). especially the father'.53 This is not the issue in Niall's case. The cause of the problem is a woman but she is not Niall's mother. Here, the Oedipal threat is kept at a distance - is in fact foreclosed. As Ramnoux says (speaking about Irish legends in general) 'There is no equivalent of an Oedipal legend which brings in all the dramas and all the horrors'.54 This has far reaching implications for psychoanalysis. After all, if Oedipus has never entered fully into Irish legend does this not imply that at some fundamental level the mother remains all powerful, untouchable, and on the other hand reviled? Does this mean that the incestuous wish is so strong that it cannot be talked about, and yet woman (always the other woman) is dangerous and evil? If we regard the sacred marriage between the King and his country as important, we must not also forget that Irish myth has always insisted that the woman is the body of Ireland. It is interesting to note that the worship of Mionnfionn persisted right down through the centuries and is still preserved today in Gaeltacht na Rinne, where at Halloween children say as they knock on each door: Anocht oiche Shamhrta Muingfinne banda (tonight is Halloween, we are of blondly haired feminine Mionnfionn.) But all this was not proof enough of Niall's claim to the Kingdom. He had to prove himself yet again. Another legend tells us how he did this. One day, the five sons went hunting and they lost their way in the forest and were enclosed on every side. They lit a fire and cooked some of their game and ate till they were satisfied. They wanted water and Fergus set out in search of it. He found a well but there was an old woman guarding it. 1A mouth she had into which a hound would fit, her spiked tooth-fence about her jaws, was more hideous than all the goblins of Erin'. 53 Rank, op.cit. p.77 54 ibid. p. 1371.1 am indebted to Dr. SeAn O'Dumn Lecturer Un Lean Diichais, University of Limerick who adds that at the present state of research we can say that there is no direct Oedipal story within the Irish tradition, but that the legend of Lughaidh Riamh Dearg comes close enough to it, while not containing all the Oedipal elements. 59 She asked Fergus to kiss her but ’fear and terror lay hold of him, he returned to the others and said he had found no font, that Erin's water was hidden from him'. Two of the other brothers (Fiachna and Ailill) went to win a triumph over Fergus, but they came back without a single drop. The brothers then bade Niall go, 'out of hatred to his mother - in hopes they were of some fell assault’. As soon as he reached the stream ... ... he beheld her there, that hideous shape, thin-shanked, grey headed, bushy-browed. When the hag asked him for a kiss, around her he closed his arms, he strained her to his breast and bosom as she were forever his own spouse. When he looked up - blooming her countenance in hue as the crimson lichen of Leinster crags, clear like crystal was her throat, her locks were like Bregon’s buttercups. Arise O'Niall, said she, then thou art the princely heir of Tara; who are you, said Niall. King of Tara, I am Sovranty. I shall tell you its virtue. Your seed shall be over every clan. The legend may have a 'clear political aim'55 as Brendan O'Buachalla attests, and it may be ’Ui Neill dynastic propaganda',56 but at a psychoanalytical level it displays, once again the unconscious relationship between men and women. The guardian of the well may be an ugly woman but she is also ’Flaitheas na Riogh' - the Kingdom of Kings. She is the heavenly Queen - the Goddess - her power is great in that not only can she grant the High Kingship of Ireland to Niall but she also can withhold the source of life from him. Therefore she is mOther. And his part in all of this? He has to be desirous enough and fearless and so unlike his brothers as to kiss her on the mouth, - to break the taboo; but he can only 55 B. O'Buachalla, op.cit., p.372. (my translation) 56 ibid, p.472 60 do that on condition that she becomes something Other - a beautiful young maiden. So, once again the Oedipal motif is kept at a distance. Niall's father Eochti, high King though he may have been, seems impotent in the face of such a woman and yet she is revered. This leads us to ask what is the paternal function or more precisely where is it? Of course sibling rivalry is also at work in this legend but once again it is removed; it is not between the same 'clan' but against the 'foreign one/ in their midst, Niall. Adoption is highly valued in this legend. Toma was not a humble person but a distinguished poet who brought Niall up wisely and well. Did our adoption laws seek to incarnate something of that aspiration, down through the years? We note also that Caireann Casdubh, she of the lovely black hair, is a foreigner, and this allows the others to be cruel to her. The incestuous wish towards woman takes not the form of wishing to be close to her, but to kill her - the foreigner. And so it goes on - perhaps even more so today in a country where the foreigner is still villified - where the Department of Justice has rejected 'approximately 85% of the 655 asylum applications processed to the end of August this year'57and in a Europe which is rapidly closing it ranks to the idea of the stranger and where the possibility of 'plurabilities1is in danger of ending with a single European ... it is no accident that the name Gallagher signifies 'of foreign help1. (Gall-Chobhair) When he came back from Paris in 1974, Cormac Gallagher brought something of the foreigner back with him, not as a 'hostage1 but as a permanent call to wake up from the bonds of servitude in its myriad forms. The father always carries something of the foreigner with him. Address for correspondence: The Milltown Institute of Theology and Philosophy Milltown Park Dublin 6 57Magill Magazine. Ed. Vincent Browne. October. Dublin, 1998. p.42 61 SYMPTOME, ETHIQUE ET DESIR D'ANALYSTE Claude Dumézil J'évoquerai la boutade de Lacan: 'La Psychanalyse, c'est le traitement que l'on attend d'un psychanalyste'. D’une telle formulation se dévoile une conception de la psychanalyse comme structure, celle de la cure. Ce point est déterminant dans l'abord de la question du symptôme, aussi bien en clinique que dans ce que peut dire le psychanalyste du malaise, celui de la psychanalyse ou celui de la civilisation. Le psychanalyste incarne une fonction, presque au sens mathématique du terme (et non au sens d'un fonctionnaire). L'opératoire de cette fonction dans la cure s'éclaire en considérant celle-ci comme une structure dynamique résultant de la rencontre, dans un espace transférentiel donné, de la structure initiale d'un patient avec un désir d'analyste. Certaines analyses didactiques ou certaines 'passes' soulignent une ’symptômatisation' de ce désir dans son devenir et ses effectuations les moins discutables. Rappelons que Lacan formalisait la réalité psychique et le complexe d’Oedipe dans le symptôme comme quatrième élément nécessaire pour faire tenir l'enchaînement borroméen des trois registres Réel, Symbolique et Imaginaire dont on connaît l’incidence dans le rapport au social et dans les variations de la clinique. La psychanalyse, une cure analytique, ne sont en rien la reproduction d'un modèle relationnel, social habituel. L'altérité dont a à connaître la psychanalyse passe par la parole et rencontre la réalité de l'inconscient comme effet du langage. Dans ce champ de l'altérité, toute opposition entre réalité et discours est aussi partiale et idéalogique que ne le serait une opposition entre Science, dans ses prémices et ses réalisations, et Inconscient, dans ses formations. L'inconscient existait bien sûr avant la découverte de la psychanalyse: il n'y a pas d'antériorité de la réalité sur la représentation mais combinatoire. Un savoir sur l'inconscient estampille cette combinatoire. Il en va de même de la notion de 'réel', disjoint du concept de réalité. Ce registre n'est pas spécifique à la psychanalyse mais celle-ci en a une pratique clinique spécifique: le réel c'est ce qui échappe au sujet, ce qui est au-delà de l'image et de la lettre, ce qui n'est pas spécularisable, ce qui est impossible à supporter. L'enseignement de J. Lacan en a formalisé la place dans la structure par rapport à l'imaginaire et au symbolique. Ce qui ne peut être symbolisé apparaît dans le réel, d'où les relations priviligiées entre le réel, le refoulé et l'inconscient. C'est en tout cas d'être référé à ce réel et non à un idéal, que se spécifie l'éthique de la psychanalyse. Si un discours fait lien social, l'éthique en est davantage la conséquence que la cause. Peut-être est-ce ce qui fonde le psychanalyste à proposer d ’ajouter aux autres éthiques son éthique de déliaison, référée au réel de la structure. Que la déliaison concerne bien l'inconscient, il me semble qu'on le repère dans la pratique théorique, de Freud à Lacan, des psychanalystes confrontés, dans la structure dynamique des cures qu'ils conduisent, à une problématique de perte et de deuil. Le recours de Lacan aux mathèmes, comme outils d'un intégralement transmissible atteste bien d’une matière qui échappe au sens, comme la nouvelle approche du statut du symptôme par la topologie des noeuds. La structure de la cure renvoit donc au désir d'analyste qui en assure le cap. Elle requiert une éthique autre, décalée d'un lien social courant. Que la déliaison ait bien sa place dans le discours, c'est ce qu'indique l'observation à l'état brut, dans le jeu de Yeinfall, des éléments essentiels de la pensée comme le désir, la pulsion de mort ou la limite à toute complétude existentielle ou relationnelle. Le sujet de la science procède de cette limite d'ou il suit les contours du sujet de l'inconscient. Humaines ou exactes, les sciences rencontrent la question du refoulement. Mais c'est pour l'ignorer ou tendre à l'effacer. Cette polarité naturelle des sciences vers le conscient et la réalité et non vers le réel et Vinconscient au sens de la psychanalyse, rend à la fois celle-ci hétérogène aux autres champs de la connaissance en même temps qu'elle lui assigne une place à part dans une réflexion éthique. On ne peut que déplorer l'absence de psychanalystes au sein des comités d'éthique ayant à connaître des mutations que la science apporte à notre société, même si la vocation de la psychanalyse n'est pas d'expliquer le monde, de conseiller des experts ou d'en produire. Certes les savants et les autorités morales produisent un discours propre à dépasser une réalité d'expérience mais la psychanalyse est la seule expérience qui produise un discours qui importe dans le réel entre la science et la vérité, la parole et le corps sexué et mortel. Ces remarques indiquent une direction aux sociétés ou associations de psychanalyse dans leurs rapports aux développements des savoirs. C'est la pratique de l'inconscient qui permet d'aborder ces questions avec beaucoup plus de 'déliaison' que n'en permettent les discours de maîtrise qui se tiennent en amont ou en aval du culturel, de l'institué et du politique, notamment dans les regroupements dont la psychanalyse est l'objet. C'est de la mise en perspective et en tension de ces deux concepts pivots de désir d’analyste et d'éthique de la déliaison que l'on parviendra peut-être, entre les aléas des innovations, la clôture d'une orthodoxie ou la complaisance d'un ancrage psychosociologique dans la 'culture', à préserver la psychanalyse elle-même du refoulement. Adâress fo r correspondence: Analyse Freudienne 41 Rue de Vaugirard 75006 Paris France A REVIEW OF FREUD'S EARLY REMARKS ON ADDICTION: FROM AN IDEAL TO MASTURBATION Rik Loose 1...why isn 1t everyone a drinker?' de Mijolla and Shentoub Introduction It is a remarkable fact that there is no real substantial psychoanalytic theory of addiction, especially given that Freud had clinical experience of working with addicts.1 This fact is even more remarkable when you know that one of Freud's first attempts to cure someone was his clinical intervention with his friend and colleague, Ernst von Fleischl-Marxov. Freud had hoped that cocaine could help his friend to get rid of an addiction to morphine. This attempt failed and eventually von Fleischl-Marxov died from a cocaine addiction.2 Surely these clinical 1 In Peter Gay's biography of Freud we can read the following: 'From 1912 on, Freud analysed Jones' attractive mistress Loe Kann, a morphine addict, whom everyone, including Freud, referred to as Jones' wife. Setting aside the sacred rule of confidentiality, he reported to Jones about her progress on the couch and the decreasing doses of morphine she was learning to live with'. P. Gay, Freud: A life for Our Time, London, Macmillan, 1988, pp.186-187. Also the famous analyst Ruth Mack Brunswick was addicted to morphine and a whole series of other drugs. Freud had understood that her addiction should be treated. She was in analysis with him, with interruptions, from 1922 to 1938. She worked as an analyst for most of her life and was very well respected by Freud and other analysts. Eventually she moved to America where she died in 1946 from medical complications as the result of an accidental fall which happened whilst she was under the influence of a combination of drugs. 2 Freud's associate, von Fleischl-Marxov had become addicted to morphine which he used to lessen the chronic pain of an infection in his thumb. In this period Freud had become extremely interested in the 'magical' properties of cocaine. His desire to help his friend out of his agony, in combination with his enthusiasm for cocaine, led Freud, who assisted encounters must have aroused Freud's interest in the problem of addiction and provoked questions regarding its metapsychology? Freud had a curious mind and his theory and metapsychology was always developed on the basis of his clinical work with patients. There are numerous references to addiction in his writings, ranging from his pre-analytical period to the end of his life, which are interesting and important but it is nonetheless strange that he never wrote an article dealing exclusively with addiction. Despite the many references, we can still speak of a relative silence in Freud's work with regards to this clinical problem. Freud has developed elaborate theories on neurosis, perversion and psychosis. Why is there no such elaborate theory on addiction in his work? Are there any deep-rooted psychological motives in Freud that contributed to this neglect? These questions have been taken up by some authors and we do not propose to deal with them here.3 It is well known that Freud's Breuer in the treatment of von Fleischl-Marxov, to giving him the drug thinking that it could be a harmless substitute for morphine. Unfortunately von Fleischl-Marxov developed an addiction to cocaine and he died in miserable circumstances. Apparently he subcutaneously injected the cocaine which resulted in 'undesirable side effects'. Peter Gay writes in a footnote to his biography of Freud that ’this is a complicated issue: FleischlMarxov injected himself with cocaine, and Freud did not at the time object to this procedure. Later Freud turned away from it, and denied that he had ever advocated it.' P. Gay, Freud: A Time for Our Life, o.c. p.45. 3 In an article from 1995 Ali Magoudi argues that factors and events which contributed to Freud's cocaine episode, as Jones called it, resulted in a theoretical position which led to a tendency in Freud and psychoanalysts after him, to exclude addicts from psychoanalytic treatment. Magoudi highlights the blind spots in Freud's self analysis and theory in order to show how they functioned as obstacles to analysis of addicts and addictions. A. Magoudi, Freud: de la cocaine au complexe d'Oedipe; Cliniques mediterranees, nr 47-48, Clinicjues des toxicomanes, Aix-en-Provence, Centre National du Livre et L'Universite de Provence, 1995, pp. 107-119. See further Peter Gay: 'We know that he admitted being addicted to cigars (...) Plainly there were depths to his mind that his self analysis had never reached, conflicts it had never been able to resolve. Freud's inability to give up smoking vividly underscores the truth in his observation of an all-too-human disposition he called knowing-and-not-knowing, a state of rational apprehension that does not result in appropriate action,' P.Gay, Freud: A Life for Our Time, o.c. p. 427. See also a section called L'episode de la cocaine (1884-1885) et le probleme de la <toxicomanie> de Freud in Didier Anzieu's book on Freud's self-analysis. D. Anzieu, V Auto-Analyse de Freud et la Decouverte 66 relationship to drugs was ambiguous. When Freud came across cocaine in 1884 he was immediately fascinated with it, particularly its therapeutic properties and he used it himself for a period of about ten years. He wasn’t really interested in alcohol and only occasionally drank some wine. Addiction problems in his practice and social environment irritated him. He was hopelessly addicted to smoking and nicotine. He smoked about twenty cigars a day. He needed cigars to work and lack of nicotine plunged him into a bad mood. When he was diagnosed as having cancer of the mouth he was informed that his smoking habit would kill him and on several occasions he was strongly advised by his physicians to stop smoking but he was unable to stop despite this medical advice.4 From Freud's biographer Ernest Jones we know that for a long time Freud refused to take analgesics against the excruciating pain produced by the cancerous growth in his mouth. He likened taking drugs to the embracement of death. Freud's personal and professional ambiguities toward addiction perhaps contributed to the fact that there is no proper de la Psychanalyse, Tome 1, Paris, P.U.F. 1975, pp. 71-78. There we can read among other things the following remarks (our translation): ’Whilst Freud elaborated bit by bit the psychoanalytic comprehension of most of the psychopathological manifestations, toxicomania remained an unexplored terrain for him, sign of a ’resistance’ which is locked into a personal flaw1(P. 75). 'One encounters in fact in Freud certain characteristics which H. Rosenfeld (1960) showed in addicts: idealisation of the breast with which the subject proves the need to feel united or identified (Freud became partially conscious of this), the search for a means of artificially producing the hallucination of that ideal breast, the return of the good reconstituting drug as bad harmful substance (Freud came close to the recognition of this process with the discovery of ambivalence.), the disavowal of frustration and persecutary anxiety (Freud was not conscious of this anxiety nor of his defence against it), the identification with a sick object or death (here, in this case, grand father Schlomo and then the younger brother Julius) (P. 78). 4 Gay writes: 'Still, from 1923 on, Freud repeatedly developed benign or precancerous leukoplakias, which had to be treated or excised. Pichler was skilful and kind, but the thirty or more operations he performed - some not so minor - to say nothing of the scores of fittings, cleanings, and refittings of Freud's prothesis, were invasive and irksome procedures. Often they hurt him very much. The pleasure that continued smoking gave Freud, or, rather, his incurable need for it, must have been irresistible. After all, every cigar was another irritant, a little step toward another painful intervention.' P. Gay, Ibid. pp. 426-427. 67 theoretical development in relation to addiction in his work. One can therefore not depend on a coherent theoretical foundation in Freud in order to construct a psychoanalytic theory and clinic of addiction. Nevertheless an exploration of remarks on and references to addiction throughout Freud's work show that there is a lot of material to work with and on which to reflect. For this paper we propose to concentrate on his pre-analytical period in order to show that this was a very interesting period of Freud's work, especially in relation to addiction. We will not include his papers on cocaine here as, in our opinion, they are so central to the development of his work and important for an understanding of a psychoanalytic approach to addiction that they warrant a separate exploration. Despite the lack of a substantial psychoanalytic theory on addiction an enormous amount of articles and books have been written about addiction from a psychoanalytic perspective. Excellent surveys and reviews of the literature have been written by Crowley (1939), Rosenfeld (1964), Yorke (1970), de Mijolla and Shentoub (1973), Limentani (1986) and Magoudi (1986).5 This paper is to some degree based on the chapter by de Mijolla and Shentoub which deals with Freud's pre-analytical period. This work was chosen for its detailed description, its clarity and above all its wide range of references. Freud’s Cocaine Papers and remarks on addiction from his preanalytical period already show an indication of the problem with the questions of diagnosis. What is addiction? What are the differences between normal and abnormal usage of drugs? Are there different kinds 5 R. M. Crowley, Psychoanalytic literature on drug addiction and alcoholism, Psychoanalytic Review, 26, pp. 39-54. H. A. Rosenfeld (1964), 'The Psychopathology of Drug Addiction and Alcoholism: a Critical Review of the Psycho-Analytic Literature' in Psychotic states, London, Hogarth Press, pp. 217-252, 1965. C. Yorke, 'A Critical Review of Some Psychoanalytical Literature on Drug Addiction' in Brit J. Med. Psychol, 1970,43, pp. 141-159. A. De Mijolla et S. Shentoub, Pour une Psychanalyse de VAlcoholisme; Paris, pb Payot, 1973, pp. 15-100. A. Limentani, ’On the Psychodynamics of Drug Dependence1in Between Freud and Klein, London, Free Association Books, 1986, pp. 48-65. A. Magoudi, 'Revue de la littérature psychanalytique sur les toxicomanies' in Approche Psychanalytique des Toxicomanes (eds. C. Ferbos et A. Magoudi), Paris, Presse Universitaires de France, 1986, pp. 7-43. 68 of addictions and on what are these differences based? Should a diagnosis be based on different drugs and their effects? It is very difficult to define what precisely a drug is. A common definition of a drug is of a substance which when incorporated, is capable of producing alterations of the mind and the body. This definition makes sense at first, but on reflection it has no theoretical or even explanatory value. A lot of things that can be incorporated can be a drug or act like one. It is sometimes difficult to distinguish between what is a drug, a poison or a food. Drugs (including alcohol) taken in large amounts can become poisons, but in limited amounts they can function as remedies. If it is difficult to define what a drug is, then it is even more difficult to define what constitutes an addiction to drugs. A definition of addiction should be able to distinguish between normal use and abnormal abuse. These difficulties are compounded by the facts that the same drugs and similar quantities of drugs do not affect people in the same way. These different effects of drugs are more than likely related to psychological features of people and there is no doubt an extremely complex cause and effect dynamic between the former and the latter. If drugs affect people in different ways, then to distinguish between addictions on the basis of the kind of drug used might not be at all valid, unless a clear and unambiguous relationship exists between certain psychological features and particular sought after drug effects. Demonstrating the existence of such a relationship has proven to be extremely difficult. We certainly will not be able to answer all of these questions, but we would hope at least to be able to show that there is the foundation in Freud's pre-analytical period for the formulation of an answer to them. From an ideal material object to the disappointment of fantasy In 1888, the year after Freud wrote his last paper on cocaine, he published an article called Hysteria. He writes: As factors which produce outbreaks of acute hysterical illness may be adduced: trauma, intoxication (lead, alcohol), grief, emotion, exhausting illness - anything, in short, which is able to exercise a powerful effect of a detrimental kind.6 Alcohol and other intoxicants are here considered by Freud to be potentially dangerous substances or 'foreign agents' which can harm the psyche of the subject. Drugs are only one of a number of external factors which can cause hysteria. Five pages later he writes in the same article: To begin with, internal medication is to be disrecommended here and narcotic drugs are to be warned against. To prescribe a narcotic drug in an acute hysteria in nothing less than a serious technical mistake.7 Four years previously Freud thought he had found a narcotic drug which could function as an ’universal panacea* against human suffering. His investigations in relation to the drug cocaine led him to the conclusion that such a panacea is an illusion. Here he warns against using any kind of drug as a cure for hysteria. Nothing in this article refers directly to addiction. In a text from 1890 called Psychical (or mental) Treatment Freud deals with the question of hypnotic treatment. He writes that hypnosis should not be employed as a last resort measure, but can be employed to all nervous diseases and morbid habits such as alcoholism, morphine addiction, and sexual aberrations.8 In his text Hypnosis from 1891, Freud writes that hypnosis should only be used for ... ... purely functional, nervous disorders, for ailments of psychical origin and for toxic as well as other addictions and that in general it should be avoided for symptoms with an organic cause.9 6S. Freud. Hysteria (18881)), S.E., vol. I, London, The Hogarth Press, p. 50. 7 ibid., p.55. 8 S. Freud. Psychical (or Mental) Treatment (1905a), S.E., vol. VII, p. 299. 9 S. Freud. Hypnosis (1891d), S.E., vol. I, p.106. This is interesting as it seems to suggest that for Freud the addictions belong to those symptoms which do not have an organic cause. In a letter to Fliess from 1895 on Paranoia and known as draft H, Freud writes the following: The alcoholic will never admit to himself that he has become impotent through drink. However much alcohol he can tolerate, he cannot tolerate this insight. So his wife is to blame - delusions of jealousy and so on.10 Here we see a first association between alcoholism and sexuality in Freud's thinking. Another interesting aspect of this brief passage is the mechanism of denial in the alcoholic ('my sexual problem has nothing to do with drink.') and its associated mechanism of not taking responsibility by blaming others ('my sexual problem has nothing to do with me; my wife is to blame.'). It is important to note that Freud here refers to alcoholism in the context of paranoia. He will come back to the delusion of jealousy in the alcoholic in his text on Schreber. In a letter to Fliess from 1896, draft K, Freud refers to drinking (dipsomania) as a secondary symptom which can arise if the compulsions of obsessional neurosis are transferred to motor impulses against the obsession.11 This remark is not unimportant as drinking is considered here by Freud as a (secondary) symptom related to obsessional neurosis. It is interesting that according to Freud this can only happen if something of the ideational aspect of the obsessional neurosis is translated into a motor impulse. He seems to suggest that these motor impulses are ritual actions, protective behaviours, brooding and so on. In other words drinking is something other than purely ideational, or as we could say drinking is not a symbolically structured formation of the unconscious. In Further Remarks on the Neuro-Psychoses of Defence from 1896, Freud considers dipsomania to be a numbing of the mind as a protective measure against obsessional 10 S. Freud. Draft H. Paranoia (1895), The complete letters of Sigmund Freud to Wilhelm Fliess, (tranl. and ed. J.F. Masson), Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1985, p.110. 11 S. Freud. Draft K. The Neuroses of Defence (1896), op.cit, p. 166. 71 affects. Here again he places drinking amongst the secondary symptoms in obsessional neurosis where it functions as an anaesthetic.12In a letter to Fliess from 11 January 1897, Freud refers to a case of dipsomania about which he says that 'dipsomania arises through the intensification or, better, substitution of the one impulse for the associated sexual one'.13 He also writes there that the same idea applies to the gambling mania of another patient. This is the first time Freud suggests that addictions like toxicomania or gambling can be substitutions of repressed sexual impulses. It is only thirty one years later in his paper on Dostoyevsky that Freud will come back to his idea of gambling as a substitute satisfaction for unsatisfied sexual impulses. In this paper he will link the addiction to gambling to masturbation. This is not the first time that Freud establishes a connection between addiction and masturbation. The first time Freud writes about masturbation in the context of addicition is towards the end of 1897, a year in which he made some of the most important discoveries in psychoanalysis on foot of his self-analysis, such as unconscious fantasies as falsification of the truth. Important discoveries In order to illustrate the importance of this crucial period in Freud's thinking it might be helpful to provide this year with a brief historical context.14 . During his 'cocaine period* (1884-1887) Freud had become interested in hysteria. He greatly admired the famous physician and expert on hysteria, Charcot, and visited him in Paris in 1885. In 1893, Freud breaks away from Charcot's thinking. In that year he writes an article called: Some Points for a Comparative Study of Organic and Hysterical 12S. Freud. Further Remarks on the Neuro-psychoses of Defence (1896b), S.E., vol. HI, p.173. 13 S. Freud. The Complete Letters of Sigmund Freud to Wilhelm Fliess, op.cit., p.222. 14 Paul Verhaeghe's book, Does the Woman Exist?, has been of great help as a guide in our exploration of this brief historical context. P. Verhaeghe, Does the Woman exist? (translated by Marc Dury), London, Rebus Press, 1997, pp. 10-29. 72 Motor P a r a l y s i s In this article, Freud came to the conclusions that hysterical paralyses are not the same as organically caused paralyses and that hysterical symptoms of paralyses do not follow the laws of anatomy. In that same year, Freud and Breuer wrote their Preliminary Communication as an introduction to what later would become their famous Studies on Hysteria.16 This is the moment the trauma theory is bom. Hysterics have experienced some traumatic events and the representations of these events have a pathological effect because they cannot be abreacted. What cannot be abreacted? The affect or energy that is contained within these representations. Why can this not be abreacted? Because there is a 'splitting of consciousness', a dissociation between the group which forms the pathological representations of the traumatic events and the rest of the psyche which defends itself against these representations. The result of this split is that the affect or energy cannot be wom-away or abreacted via the ego or what perhaps should be called here the rest of the 'normal' conscious associations. What is this affect or energy? It is a quantity of something and Freud defines it, in 1894, in what is known as the Qhypothesis: I refer to the concept that in mental functions something is to be distinguished - a quota of affect or sum of excitation which possesses all the characteristics of a quantity (though we have no means of measuring it), which is capable of increase, diminution, displacement and abreaction, and which is spread over the memory-traces of ideas somewhat as an electric charge is spread over the surface of a body.17 15 S. Freud. Some Points for a Comparative Study of Organic and Hysterical Motor Paralyses (1893c), S.E., vol. 1, pp. 160-172. 16 S. Freud. On the Psychical Mechanism of Hysterical Phenomena: Preliminary Communication (1893a), S.E., vol. H, pp. 3-17. 17 S. Freud. The Neuro-Psychoses of Defence. An Attempt at a Psychological Theory of Acquired Hysteria, of many Phobias and Obsessions and of certain Hallucinatory Psychoses (1894a), S.E., vol. ID, p. 60. 73 Freud's concept of quantity here is important. This quantity is something that cannot be measured but it can be changed and distributed. It is something that can be related to ideas or representations. It is clearly something that, according to Freud, can be harmful when it exists in isolated form or when it accumulates. Freud's psychotherapy of hysteria is an attempt to set this energy or quantity free from the clutches of the isolated/ repressed group of representations by establishing a link between this group and the rest of the psyche and by allowing this energy to be wom-away via associations. Freud's idea of how this quantity functions is based on the constancy-principle from nineteenth century energetics. This will form a framework for much of his thinking (at least till 1920) and it forms the justification for his concept of the pleasureprinciple, which, in simplified form, says that the accumulation of energy causes pain and its reduction leads to pleasure. Freud was confronted with the problem of quantity for the first time in his work on cocaine, where he tried to understand the peculiar relationship between the effect of cocaine and a quantity of energy contained within the body. In 1895, Freud's Q-hypothesis helps him to to establish the beginnings of a differential diagnosis. In an article on anxiety neurosis he explores the relationship between anxiety and sexuality in terms of the dynamic between the psyche, the soma and quantities of energy.18 Normally a quantity of energy which originates from the soma reaches a certain treshold of intensity with the result that it can be ’picked up' and processed by the psyche in such a way that it is properly abreacted. This process can go wrong in three different ways which will lead to three different pathologies: 1) There is a conflict in the psyche with the result that the energy, after having been processed, cannot be adequately abreacted and is therefore sent back to the soma where it leads to conversion symptoms; 2) there is a 'psychical insufficiency' through which accumulated somatic energy cannot be psychically processed; it remains, therefore, somatic and subsequently becomes harmful; 3) there is an 18 S. Freud. On the Grounds for Detaching a Particular Syndrome from Neurasthenia under the Description 'Anxiety Neurosis* (1895b), S.E., vol. Ill, pp. 90-115. 'inadequate disburdening' of the somatic impulse, through for instance masturbation, with the result that a proper abreaction of the energy has become impossible and again becomes harmful. The first possibility indicates the mechanism at work in the psychoneuroses, whilst the second and third possibilities refer to anxiety neurosis and neurasthenia respectively, which belong to the category of the actual neuroses. This third possibility in particular is interesting for us here because Freud, as we said, would establish a connection between masturbation and addiction for the first time towards the end of 1897. But before we continue this exploration of Freud's references to addiction with this comment about masturbation in relation to addiction, we need to complete our exploration of the historical context of that crucial year in Freud's pre-analytical period. We can infer from what Freud writes about quantity of energy in his article on anxiety neurosis that this quantity exists in somatic form and in a psychic form. The latter is the result of a psychic processing of the somatic form and is called sexual libido. The originally somatic or material form of energy is turned into a psychic or non-material kind of energy. Libido is the result of the transformation of somatic energy into a form of psychic excitation which becomes attached to psychosexual representations. Freud subsequently discovers that this quantum of psychic energy can be displaced over these representations. Displacement will later become one of the mechanisms of the primary process of the unconscious. But before this Freud was beginning to realise that this displacement of energy often concerns a wish or a psychosexual desire about which hysterics don't want to know anything and against which they vigorously defend themselves with symptoms. Paul Verhaeghe considers this discovery of Freud to be the true point of departure for psychoanalysis. He writes: From that point on, hysteria was no longer determined by some mysterious trauma, but by an inarticulable desire that kept on being displaced. On 27 October 1897, Freud generalised this point and made it the most fundamental characteristic of hysteria: 'Longing is the main character-trait of hysteria, just as a current anaesthesia (even though only potential) is its main symptom.'19 Here we find an important argument for considering 1897 as a crucial year for Freud. In order to be able to put this argument into its proper context we will need to go back a couple of years. In Studies on Hysteria (1895) Freud argues that certain psychological experiences cannot be adequately abreacted, mainly because the patient represses certain painful ideas. The result of this repression is that this group of ideas is cut-off from the rest of the psyche and abreaction of the painful affect or energy via the rest of the psyche has become impossible. This strangulated affect becomes pathological. The unconscious group of ideas forms, as it were, a disturbing 'foreign body' within die psyche against which the patients need to defend themselves and which becomes the object of therapeutic effort. Is there no connection at all between this repressed group of ideas and the rest of the psyche? There are connections. Patients suffer symptoms and these symptoms are determined by this unconscious group of ideas or representations. Freud says that an unconscious representation is wrongly related to a conscious representation and he calls this displacement a 'false connection'.20 In other words, symptoms are false connections between unconscious and conscious representations. The patient has no knowledge of this connection because of the displacement that has taken place. Freud mentions another connection between the unconscious and the rest of the psyche. He writes: 'The psychical material in such cases of hysteria presents itself as a structure in several dimensions which is stratified in at least three different ways'.21 This is how Freud begins his discussion of the threefold order arrangement of mnemic material in hysteria.22 There is a traumatic nucleus in which 'the pathogenic idea has found its purest manifestation'. Around this nucleus 19P. Verhaeghe, op.cit., pp. 15-16. 20S. Freud. Studies on Hysteria (1895d), S.E„, vol. II, p. 67, footnote. 21 ibid., p. 288. 22 ibid., pp. 288-289. 76 we find the different layers of mnemic material. The first layer is of a chronological order. The most recent memories lead to earlier ones and eventually the train of associations will end up with the most traumatic ones with which the series began. Similar memories constitute themes and these themes form a second kind of arrangement; they are concentrically arranged around the pathological nucleus. Each stratum is characterised by a similar kind of resistance against penetration of the traumatic nucleus and the closer you get to it, the higher the resistance. Freud indicates that the third kind of arrangement is the most important one but also the most problematic one to comprehend. It is an arrangement according to thought-content and the connections are made by logical links which take irregular and twisting paths to the nucleus and back to the surface. He writes: It contains nodal points at which two or more threads meet and thereafter proceed as one; and as a rule several threads which run independently, or which are connected at various points by side-paths, debouch into the nucleus. To put this in other words, it is very remarkable how often a symptom is determined in several ways, is 'overdetermined1.23 What Freud's discussion of hysteria shows here is that the unconscious and symptoms are structured and that this structure is situated in relation to a point which remains outside it or, rather, is excluded from within it. This nucleus is the point to where all threads of associations ultimately lead, but it is also the point where they cease to exist. As if nothing can be said anymore beyond this border around the nucleus. In The Interpretation of Dreams Freud calls this point 'the navel of the dream'. It is the point where all associations in relation to the dream elements come to a halt. Here language has no say. It is something at the core of our being which is excluded from the Symbolic and it is what Lacan called the Real which he conceptualised as that which cannot be grasped by the signifier. 23 ibid., p. 289. 77 Freud's hope was to find a way of trying to get his patients to articulate something of this nucleus. He wanted his patients to penetrate this point in order to wear away, via chains of associations, the strangulated and therefore disturbing 'quantity of energy1 or affect imprisoned in this nucleus. This hope was not crushed despite his therapeutic failures. Freud’s patients did not seem to want to give up their traumatic memories and when they did appear to have articulated some of the original trauma, they began to produce other disturbing memories. In other words, the cathartic method with its ideal of a complete and final solution did not work and Freud finds himself confronted with a constant displacement of traumas, affects and memories. This is not to say that abreaction as a phenomenon does not exist. It is in fact used by modem therapeutic interventions, such as scream-therapy, gestalt-therapy and even some drug-based therapies, as their raison d'etre and therapeutic aim. The therapeutic iaHures which resulted from the cathartic method did not change Freud's hope for a complete therapeutic solution to the hysterical and neurotic problems of his patients. It did however change something else! He abandoned his dependence on the trauma or seduction theory by introducing the theory of fantasy and infantile sexuality. This aspect of Freud's work is so well known and so thoroughly documented that a few words should suffice. Before 1897 Freud believed that hysteria or neurosis was caused by a scene of sexual seduction in childhood which he considered to be traumatic for the infant. The infant could not comprehend this scene and the trauma remained an inactive part of the psyche of the child until a second scene experienced in or around puberty activated this dormant part of the psyche with a deferred effect. Slowly, but surely, Freud begins to realise that the hysterical symptoms contain an element of pleasure. This made him think that the first traumatic scenes perhaps might have been somewhat pleasurable for the infant. Freud has stumbled upon elements of infantile sexuality. The infant must have experienced a conflict between the pain of trauma and something pleasurable. This is the moment when the cathartic method of abreaction begins to disappear because the contradictory forces of conflict invalidate the idea of an unproblematic purging of a 'toxic' quantity of energy. Verhaeghe writes: Or as Paul The failure of hysterical defence was not due to a failure of the process of discharging the memory of an external trauma. Hysterical defence fails because it has to make a compromise between a desire and the repression of this desire.24 In a letter to Fliess from 6 April 1897, Freud mentions for the first time that hysteria is caused by fantasies which are made up of things that children have heard at a very early age and were only understood later in life.25 Freud's letter to Fliess from 2 May 1897 is a very important one. Here Freud indicates that the cause of hysteria is to be sought in fantasies which are related to infantile impulses and whose origins might also stem from masturbatory activity. In the first place, I have gained a sure inkling of the structure of hysteria. Everything goes back to the reproduction of scenes. Some can be obtained directly, others always by way of fantasies set up in front of them. The fantasies stem from things that have been heard, but understood subsequently, and all their material is of course genuine. They are protective structures, sublimations of the facts, embellish ments of them, and at the same time serve for self-relief. Their accidental origin is perhaps from masturbation fantasies. A second important piece of insight tells me that the psychic structures which, in hysteria, are affected by repression are not in reality memories - since no one indulges in memory activity without a motive - but impulses that derive from primal scenes.26 24 P. Verhaeghe, op.cit., p. 25. 25 S. Freud. The Complete Letters of Sigmund Freud to Wilhelm Fliess, op.cit, p. 234. 26 ibid., p. 239. 79 Freud's remarks here about self-relief and masturbation are not unimportant because they clearly hint at the possible connection between an ’artificial’ production of pleasure and something unpleasant or dangerous against which this pleasure forms a protection. The interesting aspect of this connection is that masturbatory sexual pleasure can be used against frightening sexual impulses. This is crucial for the development of a psychoanalytic theory of addiction and we will come back to it with Freud's remark about masturbation and addiction later in that year. From here on Freud will elaborate his idea that something painful or traumatic needs to be processed psychically by for instance fantasies. The letter to Fliess from 7 July 1897 is interesting not only because Freud feels on the verge of something new, but also because he appears to be making progress in his own self-analysis. His understanding of his own neurosis seems to coincide with his idea that memories and fantasies can be falsifications of the past (and the latter also of the future.).27 The letter from 21 September 1897 is a crucial one. This is generally considered to be the letter in which Freud abandons the trauma theory. He writes to Fliess that in the unconscious 'there are no indications of reality' and he suggests that in the unconscious it is perhaps not possible to distinguish between truth and fiction.28 Freud does not believe in his 'neurotica' anymore. In the very same letter, Freud writes in brackets the following remark: '...there would remain the solution that the sexual fantasy invariably seizes upon the theme of the parents'.29 Indeed it is four letters later (15 October) that Freud writes to Fliess (and again in the context of his self-analysis) about the Oedipus Complex as 'a universal event in early childhood'.30 In another famous letter to Fliess, from 14 November 1897, Freud writes that fantasies and the repression of these fantasies have something to do with 'sexual zones'.31 This is Freud's first elaboration of a theory on infantile 27 ibid., p. 255. 28 ibid., p. 264. 29 ibid., pp. 264-265. 30 ibid., p. 272. sexuality, a theory which he so far had only hinted at. Almost hidden in the letter, Freud makes a throw-away remark which should arouse our interest. He writes: ... and the final outcome is consequently that a quota of libido is not able, as is ordinarily the case, to force its way through to action or translation into psychic terms, but is obliged to proceed in a regressive direction (as happens in dreams). In other words, a certain quantity of energy for some reason cannot be psychically processed and, therefore, it becomes disturbing. Something is excluded from language and has a traumatic effect. In the year 1898 Freud mainly concentrates on his analyses of dreams and, in doing so, he is very much relying on linguistic analyses. In his first letter from the next year (3 January 1899) Freud comes back to fantasies and infantile sexuality but this time he includes the linguistic connection between them. He writes: In the first place, a small bit of my self-analysis has forced its way through and confirmed that fantasies are products of later periods and are projected back from what was then the present into earliest childhood; the manner in which this occurs also emerged - once again by verbal link. To the question 'What happened in earliest childhood?' the answer is, 'Nothing, but the germ of a sexual impulse existed.' (...). In the second place, I have grasped the meaning of a new psychic element which I conceive to be of general significance and a preliminary stage of symptoms (even before fantasy).32 The new psychic element is the unsymbolised aspect of the sexual impulse and Freud considers it to be a first stage in the formation of symptoms. 32 ibid., p. 338. 81 Nothing needs to have happened. These impulses (in unprocessed form) are enough in themselves to cause trauma. It is only sometime later that these impulses are retroactively understood with the help of fantasies which take shape with what Freud calls 'verbal links" and which are what we can call elements of language. It is in this latter stage that the formation of symptoms takes place on the basis of these elements of language. For Freud, symptoms are therefore structured like a language and contain the 'germ of a sexual impulse'. This 'germ' is something that is only retroactively and falsely understood later on. In other words all symptoms ultimately relate to a disturbing element of pleasure (or satisfaction). These last couple of years have been very fruitful for Freud. He has discovered fantasy, infantile sexuality, the structuring effect of the Oedipus Complex and the importance of language for our understanding of the psyche. Above all, he has discovered that human suffering is not caused in the first place by a clearly locatable external trauma but by a disturbing element within the psychic economy of the subject which ex ists like an unprocessed remainder. Neurotics are no longer innocent victims of an external cause; something disturbs them from within. Let us now return to the end of that important year of 1897 when Freud remarked on the connection between masturbation and addiction. Masturbation and addiction: From disappointment to the quest for something more On 22 December 1897, he writes the following to Fliess: The insight has dawned on me that masturbation is the one major habit, 'the primary addiction', and it is only as a substitute and replacement for it that the other addictions to alcohol, morphine, tobacco, and the like come into existence. The role played by this addiction in hysteria is enormous; and it is perhaps there that my major, still outstanding obstacle is to be found, wholly or in part. And here, of course doubt arises about whether an addiction of this kind is curable, or whether analysis and therapy must come to a halt at this point and content themselves with transforming hysteria in neurasthenia.33 In this passage, Freud relates the addictions to drugs, alcohol and other substances to neurasthenia via the 'primary' addiction to masturbation. We wrote before that, according to Freud, the 'inadequate disburdening' of the somatic impulse through masturbation can lead to a lack of proper abreaction of the somatic energy and ultimately will result in a harmful effect. What is an inadequate disburdening and what is a lack of proper abreaction? The former meant for Freud (at that time) that the absence of 'normal' sexual activity could result in an inadequate release of sexual tension or energy. The latter meant that, therefore, a certain amount of this energy could not be properly processed and worn away by the psyche as a result of which this somatic energy became harmful or toxic and caused neurasthenia. If the other addictions are substitutes for masturbation then it seems that Freud considered addiction to be related to an actual neurosis. This must surely be the beginning of the possibility of a differential diagnosis for addiction because Freud had earlier on related some of the addictions to other neuroses and mental problems. That here perhaps he encounters the limitations of his technique is of crucial importance and something that needs to be explored and questioned separately. Freud's final comparatively extensive remarks before the turn of the century on addiction and again masturbation stem from an article from 1898 called Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses. Here he is predominantly concerned with the related questions of how to break addictive habits and what it is that causes them. He writes: To break the patient of the habit of masturbating is only one of the new therapeutic tasks which are imposed on the physician who takes the sexual aetiology of the neurosis into 33 ibid., p. 187. 83 account; and it seems that precisely this task, like the cure of any other addiction, can only be carried out in an institution under medical supervision. Left to himself, the masturbator is accustomed, whenever something happens that depresses him, to return to his convenient form of satisfaction. Medical treatment, in this instance, can have no other aim then to lead the neurasthenic, who has now recovered his strength, back to normal sexual intercourse. For sexual need, when once it has been aroused and has been satisfied for any length of time, can no longer be silenced; it can only be displaced along another path. Incidentally, the same thing applies to all treatments for breaking an addiction. Their success will only be an apparent one, so long as the physician contents himself with withdrawing the narcotic substance from his patients, without troubling about the source from which their imperative need for it springs. 'Habit' is a mere form of words, without any explanatory value. Not everyone who has occasion to take morphia, cocaine, chloralhydrate, and so on, for a period, acquires in this way an 'addiction’ to them. Closer enquiry usually shows that these narcotics are meant to serve - directly or indirectly * as a substitute for a lack of sexual satisfaction; and whenever normal sexual life can no longer be re established, we can count with certainty on the patient's relapse.34 It strikes us as funny when Freud proposes to treat masturbators (like other addicts) in an institutional setting under medical supervision. We are less concerned today with masturbation but we are in a moral panic about addiction. Whatever image an institution full of masturbators under medical supervision conjures up for you, do not let yourself be distracted by it and do not ignore what is really at stake here. 34S. Freud. Sexuality in the Aetiology of the Neuroses (1898), S.E., vol. Ill, pp. 275-276. Masturbation and addiction have in common the fact that both activities are able to produce a pleasure which is completely independent of others. The encounter with others always implies an element of risk, of anxiety and above all of unpredictability. To be part of human culture and to take part in the social bond always implies the paying of a price. This price is total pleasure which is lost when castration cuts the child out of the unity with the mother and replaces it with an ordinary or limited kind of pleasure. Addiction creates the illusion that this total pleasure is attainable again and masturbation creates the illusion for the other that the masturbator might have access to this pleasure. The masturbator knows only too well how limiting an orgasm is. This 'knowledge' of the masturbating subject is probably the reason why masturbation is less of a threat to culture than addiction and why these days we have treatment centres for addicts and not for masturbators. When do we find masturbators in treatment centres? When the limited effects of their activities do not suffice anymore and are supplanted with for-instance drugs or alcohol. When Freud makes the connection between masturbation and neurasthenia, he does not take his place in an age-long cultural tradition of frightening people away from such an un(re)productive activity, as masturbation by linking it with all kinds of imaginary diseases and ailments. When Freud posits that one of the causes of neurathenia can be masturbation, he is more concerned with an inherent problem in human sexuality. His concern is the possibility that some aspect of our sexuality cannot be symbolised or psychically processed and that this lack can lead to all kinds of disturbances such as neurasthenia or as he suggests in the above quote, depression. He writes that whenever something happens to the masturbator that depresses him, he might relapse into his convenient form of satisfaction. So perhaps the 'primary addiction' is related to depression or neurasthenia in a much more problematic way than we thought. Depression and neurasthenia can cause this 'primary addiction' rather than just the other way around. In other words, Freud is here opening up the possibility that addiction and masturbation as pleasure producing activities can be related to mental pain as the cause of these activities. This idea is substantiated by the rest 85 of the quote. He writes that 'habit' has no explanatory value and that not all people who take morphine or cocaine become addicts. In fact he relates the cause of addictions to a 'lack of sexual satisfaction’ by positing addiction as a substitute satisfaction. He even goes so far as to suggest that abstention from drugs and alcohol in itself will never be sufficient to cure a patient but that one needs to look at the cause of the addiction which is situated within the subject. In this sense, Freud was already way ahead of most modem addiction treatment ideologies which proclaim that there are no causes of addictions and that this preoccupation with causes only diverts attention away from what should be the only and true therapeutic aim: abstention. The problem for Freud in 1898 is that the therapeutic solution he comes up with is a 'normal sexual relationship1. His blind hope for a complete solution in the form of a normal sexuality hides his inkling that something-is-up in the domain of human sexuality. With this blind hope of a normal sexuality, Freud is precisely at the same level as those modem treatment ideologies which proclaim abstinence as their aim and happiness as their object. Address fo r correspondence: Centre fo r Psychoana lytic Studies LSB College 6-9 Balfe Street Dublin 2 TRAUMA AND HYSTERIA WITHIN FREUD AND LACAN Paul Verhaeghe I want to start this paper with a question: why is it proving necessary to reopen the dossier on trauma in general and Freud's vision on it in particular? An obvious answer is that today we are confronted much more with this pathology than we used to be, and not only in Belgium, for that matter. The signifier of 'posttraumatic stress disorder' is virtually everywhere. Of course, it is very difficult to prove or disprove the hypothesis that traumatic experiences are actually more frequent than they used to be. Anyhow, it is obvious that the recent hype concerning 'recovered memory therapy’has endorsed the whole question. In itself, this discussion is already a retake, albeit in a changed form, of the discussion around Masson, who in the early eighties tried to prove how wrong Freud was in matters of trauma.1 Such hypes have even received a name on their own, it is called 'Freud bashing'. The most interesting question from a clinical point of view is why a number of people think it necessary to bash daddy Freud, or, at the other end, think it necessary to justify daddy Freud. But this would lead us into a discussion of the oedipal complex, which is not on the agenda today ... One of the remarkable things about these discussions is their extreme character, which is such that even the 'normal' press talks about it, both at the time of Masson and today. One does not need that much clinical experience in order to acknowledge the fact that this extreme character betrays a hidden issue. From a clinical point of view, it is very important to unravel this hidden wager, in order to discuss it openly. The thing at stake is none other than an underlying value judgement which divides clinical 1J. Masson. 1The assault on truth: Freud's suppression of the seduction theory'. London, Fontana, 1992. 87 practice arbitrarily into two different parts. On the one hand, we find the hysterical patients with their merely fantasmatic aetiology, that is, an imaginary, early-infantile traumatic seduction. This has to be read as follows: imaginary means, no real aetiology, hence they are not real patients either. Furthermore: they are nothing but simulators who play false with the laws of science. Historically, the starting-point of this apprehension starts with Babinsky, one of the founding fathers of neurology who trained his assistants in differential diagnostics in such a way that they would be able to sort the real patients from the fake ones, that is, the hysterical ones.2 Indeed, the conversion symptoms of these hysterical patients did not tally with the objective laws of science, thus they had to be frauds. At the other side of the opposition, one finds at last the real patients, which means, from this point of view, those who have been subjected to real traumatic situations and whose pathology is a direct consequence of these situations. Thus, besides being a patient, they are also victims and they deserve not only our counselling, but also our sympathy and even our pity. The most remarkable thing about this binary categorisation is that the first category tends to become smaller and smaller, whilst the second one keeps growing. Nowadays, there are almost no patients left, there are only victims who are in no way whatsoever implied in their situation. Historically speaking, this value judgement was greatly endorsed by the feminist movement. Indeed the patients or victims were almost always women, the sexual offenders were almost always men. From that time onwards, a Newspeak denomination started being widely used: one does not say 'patient1, not even 'victim1, the correct signifier is: 'survivor1. For example, even someone like J. Herman falls into this kind of trap, in her book on Trauma and Recovery. The obligation for 'political correctness' must be quite heavy. Ironically enough, in the same book she herself demonstrates the fact that the historical discussion about hysteria and trauma is actually taken up again under new signifiers, in which borderline 2 P. Bercherie. 'Lesfondements de ia clinique'. Histoire et structure du savoir psychiatrique. Paris, Seuil-Navarin, 1980. 88 disorders stands for hysteria and posttraumatic stress disorder for traumatic neurosis. 'L'histoire se répète', history repeats itself, especially in matters of traum a... A second historical factor that enhanced the discussion further, has everything to do with a typically American situation, that is, their insurance system and their judicial system. Without going into details, we can state that in the U.S. the proof of a ’genuine', that is, a reality-based psychopathology, is necessary in order to get hold (gold!) of the insurance payment. Moreover, a certain kind of lawyer specialises in suing for malpractice, and in this case they only have to take their pick: either they sue the alleged sexual offender, or they sue the therapist... As yet, we don't have this kind of situation in Europe. As we can keep our distance, it is easier for us to detect and formulate the essential ethical question that lies at the base of this discussion, together with its answers, which trace definite lines. The question bears on the position of the patient towards the traumatic situation. Either one considers the patient as a mere victim of an external agent, which means that he or she is entitled to help and support; or one considers the patient not solely as a victim but as someone with an impact of his or her own, even with a limited form of choice. The difference between these two answers can be understood as the difference between a master discourse and a psychoanalytic one.3 If this discussion takes place within a 'political' context, more often than not, the patients will be considered as victims and survivors. Within a clinical context, on the contrary, clinicians tend to choose the second approach. For example, both Judith Herman and James Chu stress the necessity for emotional distance, that is,, for taking your distance from the all too supporting role. Herman considers the taking away of responsibility from the patient, as one of the major therapeutical mistakes.4 Chu tunes in when he states that it remains the patient's responsibility to understand what and how things have happened to him or her, and he also stresses the 3 P. Verhaeghe. 1Klinische psychodiagnostiek vanuit Lacans discourstheorie'. Gent, Ides^a, 1994. 4 J.L. Herman. 1Trauma and recovery'. Glasgow, Harper and Collins, 1992. 89 element of choice.5 These ideas echo the original Freudian ideas on the socalled 'NeurosetiioahV, the choice of neurosis. This is no coincidence, because it is precisely this factor that makes psychotherapy possible. If one sticks to the first answer, then one ends with a complete determinism and thus with therapeutic pessimism, even fatalism: the patient has become what he had to become, due to his or her traumatic experiences. If one chooses the second answer, then there is a minimal element of choice and implication of the subject, which is precisely the minimal condition for change. Hence the fact that Lacan stresses the ’future anterior' in contrast to the 'past tense': ’I will be what I am now through my choice', instead of: 'I am what I already was'. Choices made now will determine the future of the subject. So far for my introduction, as an attempt to bring into the open the underlying ethical wager in the recent trauma debate. Freud's theory is in this respect both more subtle and clinical than appears from this recent hype. In the rest of this paper, I want to elaborate this theory from a Lacanian point of view. First of all, it is important to note that it is impossible to study Freud's theory on trauma in an isolated way. One has to take at least three different subjects into account. The first one concerns indeed the discussion on trauma versus fantasy, but this has to be linked to Freud's theory on aetiology. The second subject relates to psychological functioning in general and the memory function in particular, which leads us into the heart of Freudian metapsychology. The third subject implies the goal of all this, that is, the question of the treatment and its aims. If one studies the Freudian theory on trauma from this threefold point of view - aetiology, metapsychology and aim of the treatment - then it soon becomes obvious that Freud’s theory evolved almost constantly. There are only three ideas that remain unchanged. First of all, the most obvious clinical characteristic of a trauma resides with the fact that it cannot be put into words, the patient doesn't succeed in verbalising it. Secondly, the 5 H. Snijders. 'James Chu's visie op dissociatieve stocmissen' in Tijdsckrift voor Psychotherapie. 22(4), p. 282-286,1996. trauma is always of a sexual nature, although the signifier 'sexual' has to be understood as 'related to the drive', 'pulsional', based on the Freudian idea of 'Trieb', drive. Thirdly, from a Freudian point of view, a trauma has always to do with a conflict, and thus with a defence, more particularly, an inner defence within the subject. As I have already said, Freudian theory is a lot more complicated than is usually thought. If one sticks to one isolated sentence from a letter to Fliess, dating from September 1997, then one could assume that Freud stopped believing altogether in the traumatic aetiology. The sentence runs as follows: 'Ich glaube an meine Neurotica nicht mekr', I no longer believe in my neurotica. If one takes the larger theory into account, then things become more complicated. I will demonstrate that Freud will surpass the initial question of whether the traumatic event did really happen or not; he will elaborate a theory in which the very idea of trauma receives a structural position in the coming-into-being of every human being. It is obvious that the meaning of trauma has changed in this new theory. This will become all the more clear, if we study it from a Lacanian point of view, with the category of the Real. Let us retrace Freud's steps. Before 1900, the question of whether a traumatic event really happened or not does not bother Freud. His main focus is directed to the different ways in which the psychical apparatus treats this trauma. His first theory is based on the academic psychology of his time with Herbart and Wundt as the main characters. Based on their theories, he will define the traumatic factor as an Erregungszuwachs, an increase in excitation which cannot be adequately discharged by the neuronal system. The fact that it cannot be discharged is caused by the typical way in which the trauma is psychologically represented, that is: by a so-called 'anti-thetical representation', which is a representation that the patient tries to keep out of his or her consciousness; if the patient succeeds in doing so, then the representation cannot be verbalised nor discharged and becomes pathogenic.6 In his Studies on Hysteria, Freud will conclude 6 S. Freud. 1A case of successful treatment by hypnotism with some remarks on the origin of 91 that these bewustseinsunfahige Vorstellungen, these representations which are incapable of becoming conscious, they form the nucleus of the pathological complex.7 The important point in this line of thought is the idea of conflict: a trauma installs a conflictual division within the psyche; it is this idea of division or dissociation that leads Freud to the idea of a division between a Conscious and an Unconscious system. The therapeutic goal at that time is, for both Freud and Breuer, so-called catharsis. By making use of the hypnocathartic method, the patient is induced to reproduce the antithetic unconscious representational complex. If this succeeds, then the assumption is that the accompanying affect will be liberated and discharged, the effect of which is that unconscious representations will be integrated into normal conscious associations. These unconscious representations reveal themselves most of the time as having a visual character, which brings Freud to the idea that the treatment amounts to the verbalisation of something that is obviously not verbal. Hence his frequent use, during the case studies of that time, of expressions such as Absprechen, Aussprechen, literally, ’to speak out’. As said before, at that time, Freud does not have any doubts about the genuineness of the trauma. His main preoccupation concerns the fact that the memory traces of the trauma cannot be verbalised. He doesn't doubt the possibility of this verbalisation as such; indeed, the experiments with hypnosis convince him of the fact that both a complete remembering and verbalisation must be possible. However, in his clinical practice he just can't get hold of the last words; instead of producing the ultimate verbalisation, his patients keep producing new associative chains, leading to ever earlier traumata. Moreover, these trauma's are of a sexual nature, which was rather shocking at the end of the previous century. hysterical symptoms through counterwilV. S.E., I, pp. 122-123. S. Freud. ’Preface and footnotes to the translation of Charcot's Leçons du mardi de la Salpêtrière'. S.E.,I,p. 137. 7S.Freud. Studies on Hysteria (1895d). S.E., H, pp. 286-87 and p.289. 92 In 1895, Freud states that every hysteria is based on a sexual seduction at the time of early childhood, to which the child reacted with what he denominates as a 'pre-sexual sexual fright'. Freud does not stick to moral indignation, but tries to understand how die psyche reacts to this situation. He assumes that the seduced child does not understand what happens at the time of the scene itself, because it does not dispose of the correct words for it. Hence his strange formulation: a pre-sexual sexual fright. The fact that the words were lacking at the time of the trauma explains the difficulties in the process of remembering and the ensuing impossibility of discharge.8 Moreover, during his clinical practice, Freud meets with an unexpected element which opens a totally new dimension, that is, the fantasies of his patients. Initially, he considers these fantasies as a hindrance, something that stands in the way, because he wants to uncover the real memories of the real thing. Soon enough, he discovers their defensive function: fantasies are attempts of the child to understand what it could not grasp, they are defensive coping constructions. To quote Freud: 'Such fantasies regularly, as it seems to me, go back to things heard by children at an early age and only understood later’. This quote comes from a letter to Flies, dated April 6,1897. On the second of May, he writes: ’The fantasies are derived from things that have been heard but understood subsequently and all their material is, of course, genuine. They are protective structures From these quotes, it becomes clear that at the time, Freud does not think in terms of 'either-or', either real or just imaginary. Even more so: the two of them, the real and the imaginary, stand in a vexy peculiar relationship. It is the discovery of this relationship that will get lost in the later, rather naive discussion in terms of 'either-or1: the fantasy is an attempt to give meaning to a part of the Real that resists to the Symbolic. At that time, that part of the Real is understood by Freud as a seduction scene, and 8 S. Freud. 'Heredity and the aetiology of the neuroses'. S.E., HI, p. 152. See also his letters to Fliess, dating from 15.10.95 and 16.10.95. 93 it is precisely this interpretation he will doubt later on. Nevertheless, he will never be in doubt about the said relationship. The only thing he will change his opinion about is the way in which he understands the original scene. In other words, if one argues that Freud has abandoned his theory on trauma, this is not only wrong, it is also a forgery of the history, which gave the discussion in these matters a completely different direction. Indeed, this false interpretation obliterated Freud's interest in the relationship between fantasy on the one hand and a certain reality on the other. It is much more interesting to ask oneself the question why Freud, at a given moment, starts to have doubts about the content of this reality. I use the word ’doubt' explicitly, because he will never abandon the trauma theory as such. On the contrary, his struggle with it will continue through his whole work; at the end and as a result of this struggle, he will reformulate the problem on another level. One of the reasons why he stays in doubt, has to do with his changed views on the functioning of the psyche and the associations produced by the patient. To be more specific: he discovers the fact that it is impossible to make a differentiation between reality and fantasy in the story of the patient. This discovery will have its effects on his theory on memory. For example, as early as 1899, he questions the idea of whether we are ever able to really remember something, because, he says, memories of childhood are always constructed at a later date, when other things have become more important in comparison to the things important at that early age.9 A second reason for his doubts has to do with his discovery of the infantile sexuality and the possibility of sexual pleasure for the child itself. There must be some link with the trauma and or the fantasy, but for the time being, he can't grasp it. He returns to this question in his Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality. When he elaborates the way in which the drive operates in children, he produces a very interesting definition of the drive: ’a drive is to be regarded as a measure of the demand made upon the mind to work'.10 Freud interprets the effect of the drive as a rise in excitation and 9 S. Freud. 'Screen memories'. S.E., III, p. 303. 20S. Freud. 'Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality'. S.E., VII, p.168. 94 pressure which threatens to overwhelm the ego if this psychological elaboration does not take place. Now, this description is not new and tallies perfectly with another description, namely the one Freud formulated in 1916 on the very idea of trauma. I quote: We apply the term 'traumatic' to an experience which within a short period of time presents the mind with an increase of stimulus too powerful to be dealt with or worked off in the normal way, and this must result in permanent disturbances of the manner in which the energy operates.11 If we compare these two definitions, we find a remarkable analogy between the drive and the Freudian concept of trauma. That is, between the effects on the psyche of an internal agency, the trauma, and a supposedly external one, the trauma. Moreover, in his correspondence with Flies, more particularly in Draft K, Freud had already described the onset of hysteria in terms of overwhelment, albeit that in that case, the source of overwhelment was considered to be only external, that is, again the trauma. In both cases, trauma and drive, there is a so-called Erregungszuwachs, an increase in energetical tension, which has to be discharged. The therapeutical manner of discharge is the verbalisation, being the most apt psychological way of discharge. The lack of such a verbalisation gives rise to anxiety in particular and psychopathology in general. In both cases, one finds a situation of conflict. It is within this conflict that one can discern two different kinds, with a possible interaction afterwards. The first one is general and thus structural, the second one is particular and thus accidental. The accidental concerns the trauma in the normal sense of the word, by which the subject comes into conflict with something or rather, someone, from the external world. This trauma and the ensuing conflict is accidental, because it did not 11 S. Freud. 'General Theory of the Neuroses - Fixation to Traumas - the Unconscious'. S.E., XVI, p. have to happen. The general one concerns the drive, by which an internal conflict takes place, which is in itself inescapable, because it has everything to do with the essence of human nature and culture. This brings us to a very important idea, namely the idea that human sexuality contains potentially the same effect for the subject as an external trauma, and this even in the absence of any external element whatsoever. It is this that Freud formulates in one of his drafts addressed to Fliess, where he states that, I quote ’In my opinion there must be an independent source for the release of unpleasure in sexual life: once that source is present, it can activate sensations of disgust, lend force to morality, and so on1.12 Later on, he will return to this idea in his essay on Civilisation and its Discontents. Even today, this is a rather surprising statement which has never been understood by the advocates of total sexual freedom. Freud himself also struggles with this idea, and it will take him some twenty years before he will be able to study this independent source of unpleasure. And it is no coincidence that this study leads him back to the very idea of trauma and traumatic neurosis. The title of the ensuing paper speaks for itself: Beyond the Pleasure Principle. The effect of this study is that the trauma-fantasy controversy will be reconsidered on a different level. Ifd like to summarise it as follows. Drive in itself, independent of any externally determined trauma, has a potentially traumatising effect, to which the psyche has to come up with an answer, that is, with a psychological elaboration. This elaboration takes place in and through the fantasy, which receives in this way a very important function. In this sense, there exists a perfect analogy between the night dream and the day dream, not so much because both of them contain a wish-fulfilment, but because both of them try to provide a representational elaboration of something that is very difficult to represent In The Interpretation of Dreams, Freud had already concluded that the nucleus of the dream contains something that can never be adequately represented, and he considers this 12S. Freud. 'Extractsfrom the Fliess Papers - The Neuroses of Defence - Draft K'., S.E., I, p. 222 96 nucleus as the very core of our being. This is the explanation of the hysterical neurosis. Besides this structurally determined trauma, which goes for every human being, there is the accidental real trauma, caused by an external agency. This trauma will inevitably come into interaction with the structural trauma caused by the subject's own drive. Here, hysteria turns into traumatic neurosis, but the function of the fantasy remains the same, namely elaborating in the Imaginary what could not find an adequate answer in the Symbolic. In case of the accidental trauma, this elaboration is not enough, the real aetiology of the traumatic neurosis also causes symptoms in the real, psychosomatic phenomena and automutilation being the two most well-known. The intervention of a real trauma on top of the structural trauma caused by the subject's own drive, opens the possibility of a particular line of defence, namely: that the originally internal conflict is at least partly exteriorised, projected. This can be generalised: every subject will try to project this internal conflict even where there is no external trauma. Indeed, one cannot flee from an internal conflict situation, and that is the reason for its projection. This is the mechanism that lies at the base of a phobia for example. This explains our initial ideas about the underlying value judgement and the difficulties of recognising one's own implication in matters of psychopathology. Guilt and anxiety have to be avoided.13 Anyhow, from here onwards, we are confronted with a double question. First of all, how does this defensive function of the fantasy operate? Secondly, how is it that the drive, which has everything to do with pleasure and satisfaction, implies an intrinsic traumatic factor? In his elaboration of these two questions, Freud's attention to the externally determined trauma will become smaller and smaller, and, inversely, his focus on the internal conflict will become more and more important. The way in which he develops this theory, will imply a new conception of the end and goal of the treatment. In the previous period, the 13S. Freud. 'Studies on Hysteria - The Psychotherapy of Hysteria', S.E., H, p. 290. 97 goal was relatively simple: the patient had to put his traumatic history into words, especially those parts that were forgotten, that is, repressed due to the operation of defensive mechanisms. This process of remembering had to be as complete as possible, the last word being the final goal. Nevertheless, after Freud's discovery of infantile sexuality and the accompanying fantasies, this conception is no longer tenable. The change in relation to the goal of the treatment becomes obvious in a famous paper of 1914, entitled: Remembering, Repeating and Working-through. This paper undermines the psychoanalytic importance of the process of forgetting almost completely, with the result that the idea of remembering as an important therapeutic goal, disappears at the same time. Instead of that, the analytic cure aims at the consciousness-raising of matters which have always been unconscious, and thus which could never have been forgotten in the first place. In this paper, Freud denominates this factor as the unconscious fantasies which determine obviously the kernel of someone’s neurosis. Moreover, he adds that this consciousness-raising is not enough as a therapeutic goal, it has to be followed by a process of socalled Durcharbeiten, working-through, which provides the treatment with a completely different goal. Half a century later, Lacan will reformulate the same ideas with his 'traversing of the fantasy1, as the basic goal of the analytic treatment. It is no coincidence that Freud discovers in the very same paper the idea of the compulsion to repeat, the Wiederkolungszwang, which differs from 'normal1repetition. The elaboration will follow some six years later. From this point onwards, fantasy becomes the core of the treatment. The initial question - whether the aetiology was real or not - has disappeared, and instead of that, the idea of fantasy has to be understood as the most characteristic feature of the subject. Indeed, it determines the way in which the subject models, represents and thus copes with the drive. In the meantime, fantasy has become a concept, denoting a typical complex of representational constructs that determine the psychological reality of the subject. From a Lacanian point of view, the fantasy is not so much the counterpart of reality, on the contrary, it is precisely what models the Real. 98 This theory can already be read in Freud, although it is only with Lacan that it finds its final form. Summarised, this Lacanian theory runs as follows: the drive is traumatic-Real at those points where the subject does not dispose of the adequate signifiers to treat the impulses. From a structural point of view, this is the case for every subject, because the Symbolic Order, being a system based on the phallic signifier, lacks the signifiers for three aspects of the Real. These three aspects concern femininity, fatherhood, and the sexual rapport. Traditionally, these are expressed by a number of winged words, for example, Das ewig Weibliche, the eternal feminine; Pater semper incertuus estf fatherhood is never certain, and Post coitum omne animal tristum est, after mating every animal is depressed. In these matters, the symbolic order does not provide us with adequate answers, which means that every subject has to tinker with them in the Imaginary Order. These imaginary answers will determine the way in which the subject copes with the ever problematic questions concerning sexual identity and the sexual rapport. To put it differently: the fantasies of the subject, being those imaginary answers - will determine the way in which someone enters, even constructs his intersubjective world. This structural Lacanian theory has conquered the analytic world with a number of slogans. The three aspects of the Real to which the Symbolic Order does not provide an adequate answer, were promoted by catchwords or catchphrases, like: La Femme n'existe pas, The woman does not exist, VAutre de VAutre n'existe pas, The Other of the Other does not exist, II n'y a pas de rapport sexuel, The sexual rapport does not exist. The ensuing hype or hysteria - there was, for example, an Italian newspaper announcing that women did not exist for Lacan - obliterated both the structural context and the fact that the same reasoning can be studied in Freud's theory. For example, Freud writes that every child, driven by its own sexual development, becomes confronted with three inescapable questions: the gender of its mother and thus of women in general, the role of the father and the sexual rapport between his parents. Every child will construct answers of his own, which give rise to very particular 99 constructions, the so-called infantile sexual theories, in which time and again imaginary, pre-genital contents are produced, focusing on the phallic or the castrated mother, the primal father and the primal scene. These socalled 'theories1are considered by Freud as the fore-runners of something else, something that comes more and more into Freud's focus, both from a conceptual and a therapeutic point of view. These are the primal fantasies, being necessary constructions for every subject as an answer to those three mysterious aspects of the real. For Freud, these constructions determine the particular form of someone’s neurosis. Until this moment, I have stressed the resemblances between Freudian and Lacanian theory in these matters, the Lacanian roots in Freudian theory. The major difference lies in the fact that, as long as one sticks to Freud, one can have the idea, the illusion rather, that there exists one correct answer, one correct construction. The therapeutic goal then is to analyse the wrong answer and replace it by the correct ones. With Lacan, there is no such answer, the confrontation with gender, drive and sexuality is considered by him as une rencontre toujours manquee, an always missed encounter. This has everything to do with the very difficult question of the drive and the experience of satisfaction, and it is to these subjects that we turn our attention now. Roughly speaking, until 1915 Freud conceives a pleasure principle which is very one-dimensional. Pleasure and satisfaction which can be obtained from a drive, are caused by a process of discharge. In order to make this possible, there is a typical condition: the sexual energy has to be linked to representational complexes, that is, to signifiers. This connection to words is very important for Freud, because it provides the pathway along which psychological elaboration becomes possible. In the case where this connection is lacking and the psychological elaboration fails, the patient develops a so-called 'actual neurosis', with anxiety as the central symptom. Psychopathology in general and hysteria in particular have to do with a wrong connection, what Freud denominates as a falsche Verknüpfung - just think of a phobia - caused by the conflict between desire and prohibition. Due to this false connection, both the discharge and the experience of 100 satisfaction become impossible, and the patient develops a psychoneurosis, following the initial actual neurosis. Treatment has to repair the right connection, by making use of the free association and the process of interpretation, through which verbalisation and discharge become possible again. This theory and the ensuing treatment are quite coherent; there is only one flaw to it: it doesn't work. The final verbalisation, the last word remains lacking with his hysterical patients, as if they have to go on producing signifiers circling around a nucleus that can never be fully expressed in words. Hence, the pleasure principle always fails in the end. Moreover, in his clinical practice, Freud has to acknowledge the fact that a number of patients tend to repeat things which provide them with a lot of displeasure. After twenty years, he is again confronted with the traumatic neurosis, and then especially, with war neuroses. The main question, in the light of the pleasure principle, runs as follows: why is it that victims of traumatic neurosis have to repeat time and again their original trauma, albeit always in a fragmentary way? In Beyond the Pleasure Principle, Freud comes up with an explanation by making use of an older idea, the W&derholungszwang, the compulsion to repeat. This compulsion has to be understood as a persistent attempt by the psychological apparatus to bind the traumata to signifiers. This process of binding is necessary for the discharge and the ensuing catharsis. The particular feature of a trauma resides precisely in the absence of this connection to signifiers, which implies at the same time that its psychological elaboration remains impossible. At this point, we regain our operational definition of trauma from a Freudian point of view. A trauma is an element of the Real that cannot be put into words, thus causing the impossibility of a normal discharge. During his study of war neuroses, Freud adds another peculiarity: a trauma has less impact on someone who gets physically injured as well. It seems as though the injury functions as a physical analogy to the verbal discharge. The same mechanism can be found in a tragic way with patients who have a 101 traumatic history. Indeed, a number of them injure themselves, and their automutilation can be considered as an attempt at discharge of tension. If we accept this definition of trauma, we are confronted with the question where this impossibility of verbalisation comes from. From a therapeutical point of view, this is probably the most important question, because the answers to this question determine the way in which the treatment has to be conducted. There are several hypotheses possible, for example, the stimulus intensity of the trauma, its unexpected character that took the patient by surprise and thus unprepared. Or, in the case of children, the fact that the psychological apparatus is as yet underdeveloped, etc ... As I have already pointed out, Lacan will explain this from a structural point of view: something stays beyond the symbolic order, beyond the pleasure principle, because it is different, even alien. One of its most bizarre characteristics, besides its impossible verbalisation, resides in the fact that it produces a strange form of pleasure, strange because it differs from the phallic pleasure provided by the pleasure principle and the symbolic Order. At this point, Freud is obliged to rethink his one-dimensional pleasure principle and the accompanying theory on the drive.14 An intuitive flash from twenty-five years ago pops up again: there is a source of unpleasure within sexuality itself, there is an internal antinomy at work. It is here that we find Freud's difficult and never fully accepted theory on the death-drive, Thamtos, in opposition to Eros, the life drive. One drive follows the pleasure-principle, is connected to signifiers which means that it can be discharged; the other is situated in a non-verbal beyond, non-phallic, not dischargeable, literally operating in silence. It contains another form of pleasure - 'pleasure' is probably not the correct word - belonging to the order of the Real. In Freud's opinion, normally both drives operate together in what he calls the Triebmischung, the fusion of the drives. He considers 14 S. Freud. 'Beyond the Pleasure Principle'. S.E., XVIII, p.7. 102 this double drive to be an ontological fact which cannot be explained in itself, but which can be used as an explanatory axiom for clinical data.15 This theory will be taken up by Lacan in his seminar on Encore, in which he elaborates the contradiction between the phallic-symbolic pleasure principle and the accompanying pleasure on the one hand versus the nonphallic, other jouissance that lies beyond the scope of the signifier on the other hand16 Just like Freud, he will situate the first one on the masculine side. Indeed, for Freud, there is only masculine libido. The other, more mysterious one, is situated on the feminine side. In the meantime, masculinity and femininity can no longer be reduced to their biological interpretation. They must be understood as a position chosen by the subject towards the structurally determined lack. Needless to say this is a highly abstract theory. Nevertheless, there are some very important clinical repercussions, which I would like to end with. Both hysteria and traumatic neurosis are caused by a sudden, nondischargeable accumulation of tension. In hysteria, this accumulation comes from within, and is caused by the subject's own drive. In traumatic neurosis, the source is an external one, added to the previous, internal one. This implies that hysteria and traumatic neurosis stand in a certain relationship towards each other. Hysteria starts at a structurally determined lack of the psychological apparatus, because a certain jouissance (Lacan) coming from a certain drive (Freud) cannot be linked to signifiers and remains outside the symbolic, phallic order. Traumatic neurosis comes on top of that, and entails a strange interaction with the internal conflict; just think of phenomena like automutilation and repetition compulsion. This strangeness has everything to do with the fact that something within the patient enjoys it, and this against the conscious desire of the patient. This 15 I think that this theory on Eros and Thanatos is very important, especially within the actual gender discussion. I have elaborated this in the third essay of a forthcoming book: Paul Verhaeghe. Love in Times of Solitude, Three Essays on Driue and Desire. London, Rebuss press, spring 1999. 16 J. Lacan. Encore. Le Séminaire, Livre XX, 1972-73, texte établi par J.A.MiHer. Paris, Seuil, 1973. 103 enjoyment is situated beyond the pleasure principle and thus literally incomprehensible. The naive benevolent counsellor who wants to liberate his 'survivors' from their trauma, will meet this factor soon enough, and he will not know what to do with it. Generally speaking, nobody knows what to do with it, because even today, most theories are based on the pleasure principle, that is, on the idea that every human being functions in that way. Trauma demonstrates in a painful way that this is not the case, that there is a beyond. This is indeed the most uncanny thing about trauma, and probably also the most traumatising aspect of a trauma, namely the experience that something in the body enjoys the situation, a kind of enjoyment from which the subject shrinks back in horror. Moreover, by way of a mirroring effect, this enjoyment has some strange effects on the therapist also; just think of the relationship in Coppola's Apocalypse now (or Conrad's The Heart of Dar kness, if you prefer reading) between Kurt and his 'liberator'. The treatment, every treatment has the same aim as the repetition compulsion, and that is: to get hold of this inexpressible experience by putting words to it. There is one big difference with the repetition compulsion: during the treatment, this process of symbolisation takes place within the transference relationship. It is precisely this aspect that will decide the therapeutic effects. At the end of the day, we have to admit that we meet here with something which we do not understand. Instead of producing answers too fast - Gardez-vous de comprendre, beware of understanding I think it is much more interesting to formulate a number of questions. How is the fact that a discharge of tension through speaking and a discharge through an injury, result more or less in the same effect, to be understood? Clinical practice with war neuroses shows us that the injured soldier is less apt to develop a traumatic neurosis than his non-injured colleague. Clinical practice with post-traumatic stress disorders demonstrates that patients make use of this discharge method, by automutilating. Moreover, in both cases, the injury has to be a bleeding one, pain in itself is not enough. How is the remarkable effect of scansion, which can be found in a number of self-protective reactions in patients, for example, the typical rocking, the rhythmical movements, to be understood? Hie combination between these physical phenomena and the symbolic order, which is essentially a rhythmic, scanned order, can be found in a very remarkable fact. I mean the RAP-movement, whose roots go back to the black veterans of the Vietnam war, who elaborated their traumatic experiences in group sessions. It was this elaboration that gave rise to the birth of RAP, which comes down, for me, to a very special attempt at regulating puissance,; very special precisely because of the combination between the physical rhythm and the Symbolic order as such. How is the efficiency of groups in the treatment of traumatic neuroses, especially the efficiency of self-aid groups to be understood? Is this merely an effect of mutual recognition, or does it go further than that? Could it be that a group is needed in order to develop a symbolisation, because every language symbolisation needs the convention of a group? These questions are far more interesting than the naive discussion on trauma and fantasy of my introduction... Address for correspondence: University of Ghent Vakgroep voor psychoanalyse KDunantlaan 2 B9000 Ghent Belgium PSYCHOLOGY AND PSYCHOANALYSIS A SCIENTIFIC PARADIGM Tom McGiath In a world becoming increasing dominated by information technology it might appear to be the case that what was involved here was a kind of final frontier of science-inspired technology taking over and controlling the coding and transmission of that most human of commodities, namely information. It is after all something that is about people, and contained by people and something we seek from people however indirectly. That the word, information, should become to be so frequently associated with technology is a mark of the extent to which society has become increasingly objective and technical as science marches on, and impacts, apparently more and more, on all aspects of life mediating human interaction to an ever increasing extent. It raises the question about the threatened place of the human subject in such an increasingly technical world in a new way, and gives rise to common anxieties about the control of that world and the place of the individual perhaps unknowing - subject within it. It is perhaps true to say that a majority of individuals have little enough understanding of the technologies which increasingly influence their lives and options, and experience a degree of alienation and dependence hitherto unknown. It is as though their lives were being controlled and managed by forces which are beyond their understanding, forces to which they are subjected, and by which they are managed. It might be suggested that there is the domain of the personal and private, which is separated off from the influences of the modular technology-dominated world. There is the realm of the psyche which is removed from that and which operates according to its own laws, as studied and elaborated in the science of the psyche, namely psychology. But as one will be aware, here too technology comes to have an ever- expanding role. The monitor is everywhere and computers measure and manage - with an accuracy and precision unimaginable in less sophisticated days - many of the workings of the psyche. The language of psychology too is technical and specialised to a degree that makes it incomprehensible to the normal person. It is as though psychology itself has become part of a technocracy, and the reason for this is the direction in which main-stream. psychology has moved. But there is a peculiarity about the subject-matter of psychology which is not adequately reflected in the procedures of that main-stream psychology. The peculiarity to which I am referring is that the agent of the theory building in psychology is at the same time the object about which explanations or understandings are being sought. The subject of the study is at the same time the object of that study. It might be argued that this could be said of all of the human sciences such as economics, anthropology, sociology etc., but probably in no other scientific endeavour is the tension so marked. This is because the concern of the psychologist is the individual subject, and whatever emerges from that study is inescapably a matter for the individual psychologist at the same time. The question which arises here is about the implications of this fact for the scientific study of the human subject. Main-stream scientific psychology has, since its inception as an independent science more than a hundred years ago, opted in the main for a natural science methodology, inspired by the natural sciences of physics and biology etc. It has been concerned in so doing to separate itself off from its pre-history in theology and philosophy, on the one hand, and from all imaginary and intuitive preliminary understandings of itself in the domain of what might called common sense approaches to its subject matter. It has striven in this way to achieve a degree of respectability and acceptability by the other sciences, and has hoped in that way to be taken seriously and to have its findings and research results valued appropriately. There is an underlying unease among many practitioners of the science that it may have excluded large areas of what could be properly regarded as its subject matter in order to achieve this notional respectability.1 From the perspective of psychoanalysis it would be claimed that in opting for a natural science paradigm, psychology has in fact ceded what is its most essential set of concerns, namely the constitution of the human subject in its totality and in its basic nature. Psychology has largely adopted a methodology which doesn't allow it to pursue what should really be its proper object of study, namely the human subject with all the complexity that is involved in that subject. In a sense then, analysis would understand itself as a necessary adjunct to psychology, challenging it to dialogue, at least, and to extend its selfimposed limitations of methodology to take account of what was emerging from the work of psychoanalysis. But for this to be possible there would have to be some form of interrelationship between the operative paradigms within the two related areas of concern. It would be required that there be some possibility of communication between the disciplines or some elements at least of common language which would enable that dialogue to take place. The present considerations are offered towards that end. It will be helpful to outline some of what the concerns are of some psychologists about their own methodology. Secondly, it will be necessary to review some of the remaining questions about the scientific status of psychology itself. Thirdly, it will be attempted to touch briefly on the paradigms operative within psychoanalysis, and in the course of that to examine what the possibilities might be for a more real dialogue. Rethinking Psychological Methods In very recent years there has been lively discussion within main stream psychology about the usefulness of, and need for, what are referred to as qualitative methods, as distinct from the more traditional quantitative methods. What is envisaged here is the adoption of what is 1 A useful discussion of the issues arising here can be found in S. Frosch, Psychoanalysis and Psychology: Minding the Gap. Macmillan, 1989. 108 referred to as a more appropriate paradigm for psychology.2 In the words of one contribution; ... the concern for verstehen within the qualitative paradigm has shown ... there is need in human sciences research to be sensitive to people's own understanding as seen from their local frames of reference, or from inside their own socially situated phenomenal worlds.3 Research in this qualitative mode is said not to be so concerned with numbers and measurement in the narrow sense, but rather 'tends to involve the more open-ended and detailed analysis of verbal, or written material which has not been converted to points on numerical scales'.4 Common to the different concerns of psychologists who adopt a qualitative approach is the ... ... identification of participants subjectivities - whether in the form of experiences, phenomenological worlds or accounts as an integral, though not always uncomplicated - part of the research endeavour. These subjectivities are located within many different perspectives and different areas of psychological concern1. It is mentioned here that there is a notable gap in that the psychoanalytic perspective on unconscious subjectivity is not included. The whole matter is revisited again in a later issue of The Psychologist, in April 97. Here it is being suggested that the research psychologist must include some component of what is called 'reflexity1 in the work. This would involve a sense of the philosophical position and general appoach 2 See the issue of The Psychologist, March 95, Vol 8, N° 3, for a series of interesting articles on the whole issue of Qualitative Research Methods. Publisher is the British Psychological Society. 3 See Henwood and Pidgeon's article in The Psychologist, March 95, Vol 8, N° 3, p. 116. 4ibid, p. 109. of the researcher, with some attempt being made to consider the implications of that for the outcome of the research findings. An important difference with qualitative research is that it acknowledges the social insertion of research activity, that is, in giving the reasons for researching a particular topic, the researcher's own social stance toward the question, and accepts the challenge from other social groups as a legitimate part of psychological debate. The essential difference is that of allowing for the presence of subjectivity - in the sense of the presence of a subject and trying to take account of that in the articulation of whatever the findings of the research might be. It is clear at least here that there are some serious concerns being expressed about the adequacy of the traditional 'scientific1model for psychology. It is being argued that the subjectivity of the researcher has to be included somehow. There is of course a real difficulty here about the mode of such inclusion. How is the researcher involved, and how is the question of subjectivity to be dealt with? It is somewhat paradoxical that while some psychologists are trying to find ways out of the straight-jacket of what is referred to as scientific method, at the same time there is concern among psychoanalysts that their theories and findings should really be subject to more rigorous testing and examination. Rethinking Psychoanalytic Method In a recent conference on Science and Psychoanalysis, in March 1996, organised by the Freud Museum and the British journal of Psychotherapy, one paper raised the question about the future of an Empirical Psychoanalysis. Fonagy and Target are concerned about the state of psychoanalysis and suggest that there are indications that it is in decline.5 They find many indications for this suggested decline. There is no coherent set of principles that could define useful exchange between s P. Fonagy and M. Target. The Future of an Empirical Psychoanalysis. Unpublished lecture to a conference on 'Science' and Psychoanalysis given at the Anna Freud Centre, Saturday. March 16,1996. 110 the two approaches to knowledge, that is the approach of science in the strict sense and the approach of psychoanalysis. In contrast to the approach in science, there is no sense in which psychoanalysis could be seen as a singular treatment with the possibility of scientific replicability. They point out that from the beginning of its endeavours there was a marked heterogeneity in psychoanalytic technique, and this has continued to be the situation. In fact there are no more than some common elements of practice within psychoanalysis, namely that it was long-term and expensive, use of the couch and a strict regime of abstinence for both client and analyst. Those crucial elements of the technique have hardly changed since the time of Freud, and it is suggested that some such changes might have been expected with the increasing experience and the passage of time. Better techniques should have been evolved by this time. Apart from what is referred to as a superficial unity created by the basic elements of psychoanalytic technique, there exist deep schisms, and disagreements almost approaching fragmentation. The authors refer to the contempt with which many British analysts treat their North American colleagues, which is matched by the latter's views of Latin American analysts and the derision with which French colleagues treat the whole of the Anglo-Saxon tradition. It is suggested that it would be hard to imagine that respect or credibility would be accorded to some science like molecular biology, if it too were riddled with controversy concerning its fundamentals. Further evidence of the fragmentation is given by the authors in their discussions about what is referred to as 'the psychoanalytic clinical fact'. Celebrating its seventy-fifth anniversary in 1995, the International Journal of Psychoanalysis produced a special issue on that topic. On considering that particular issue, Fonagy saw cause for anxiety about the extent of the questions of a fundamental nature which were being raised. Alongside that there was a tendency simply to reaffirm the traditional attitude to clinical case reports. The sense was conveyed that all sides of the various controversies gave rise to a challenge to the sense of self worth of the authors. This was rooted in the lamentable current state of psychoanalysis. This was further indicated by the decreasing frequency with which the articles in analytic journals were being cited, not only by other analysts but by authors in related fields as well, such as psychiatry and social work. The Case Study - a critique Can it be that this problem is due to an over reliance on the clinical case study? It has been the standard method for advancing psychoanalytic knowledge from the beginning. As Griinbaum has pointed out this approach may be deeply flawed.6 Too often clinicians will choose selected highlights of their successful cases to show how useful their technique is. However helpful and useful this approach may be to illustrate the manner in which a technique operates, there are problems about using such highlights as ways of deriving theory or technique. In a sense the approach doesn't readily allow the inclusion of disconfirming evidence, if one is to borrow from Popper’s ’falsifiability’ canon of scientific procedure. It is possible, theoretically, to accumulate indefinitely, illustrations which lend credibility to a particular element of a theory, but unless it is possible to test that element of theory in the light of instances in clinical practice which contradict it, one remains in the realm of the merely plausible and one can hardly claim any verification to a desired extent. The implications of this are that it has to be acknowledged that possibly large numbers of what are regarded as accepted generalisations within analysis might be actually false. Elements of theory based on such anecdotal evidence can only be revised on the basis of disconfirming experience or data, and the tendency in the case study approach is for such contradictory evidence simply not to be seen, or to be denied. In the narrowly defined sciences such evidence has the possibility of coming to light because of the very nature of the scientific paradigm, or because of the general advance in scientific knowledge. Such advance requires that the scientist bring an element of scepticism to his own findings. In the case of the analyst, however, this is particularly difficult. 6 A. Griinbaum. The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique. California, University of California Press, 1984. The analyst may need to leave aside such analytical material which doesn't fit into his current understanding of the patient and his internal situation. It is probably psychologically impossible to hold in mind all the possible material which would suggest alternative formulations or understandings of the patient's current state. The integration of the clinical with the scientific approach is inherently difficult. How is the analyst to retain the distance from the clinical material - which often emerges from the intense atmosphere of the consulting room - which is necessary for an objective evaluation of such material? Fonagy opts for detailed outcome studies of particular cases. Interesting as the material offered here in his discussion of such studies is, it will probably not prove satisfactory to the analyst relying to a great extent on methods and measurement techniques not readily compatible with the peculiar analytic enterprise. His estimate of how positive the outcome was relies on standardised descriptions of subjects treated, and interviews of those involved. Clearly this method of evaluation of outcome relies to a very great extent on self-reports, and to some extent on the non-professional evaluations of people close to the subjects concerned, but it is clearly difficult to standardise these reports in such a way as would satisfy the requirements of psychoanalysts in specifying what was a successful outcome. It is clearly the case that there isn't agreement among analysts about what could be considered a successful outcome, or how such an outcome might be measured. As Fonagy says, despite the eighty-seven years which have passed since the publication of Little Hans, we have very little definite evidence about what we may expect to be the outcome of child psychoanalysis. The consequences of this situation could be unfortunate, and the challenge confronting child psychoanalysis is to be able to be specific about .the range and types of cases for which it is a suitable treatment, and also to demonstrate its effects in a form accessible to others. If this fails, it is suggested, the likely outcome is that child analysis will be discredited and disappear. Perhaps it is possible to think of a similar fate awaiting psychoanalysis in general unless it gets itself into a position where it can organise itself along the lines of a paradigm which will unify the research efforts and practice of analysts and offer a united and coherent picture to 113 those who call on the services of analysts. Perhaps it is too much to think in terms of paradigm, and one might think more specifically of a more coherent organisation of analytic theory and practice. Psychoanalysts need not be primarily concerned, according to Fonagy, about whether their activity is to be categorised as scientific in some sense, but must be concerned about the central issues of the nature of mental life, the processes of cure, and the efficacy of analysis as therapy. As to whether it can be linked in a clear conceptual way to the other enterprises which would be considered part of science is a wider question and perhaps need not be of central concern. It is suggested that we do not know enough about what psychoanalysis is to link it in that way. Perhaps it is sufficient to think of analysis as principally a clinical matter with some operative generalisations about technique and theory, or perhaps to regard it even more loosely as a body of knowledge which is applicable to some defined psychotherapeutic situations. What is now required is that the constructs of analysis be elaborated in a maimer which ensures that its findings will continue to be of interest to clinicians and psychologists, literary critics and art historians, anthropologists and sociologists, and all those concerned with human behaviour and motivation. What Fonagy is suggesting is that systematic methods as adjuncts to clinical case reports might lead to coherence and progress in the field of analysis. Broadening the data base and the accepted methodology of analysis would enrich the insights of analysts, clarify the confusions, separate the wheat from the chaff in analytic discourse and help to retain Hie pre-eminent position of analysis as a clinical as well as a psychological speciality. Desirable as this project and these very creative suggestions might be there is a radical question as to whether what would emerge would still be discernible as analysis. One might ask the question about the continuing place of the unconscious in these elaborations or amplifications of the analytic method. Is it possible to think of the unconscious as being a dynamic force which is invoked only in these situations where more accessible rational psychological explanations do not apply? That seems to be the assumption which is implied here. In this view, which seems also to be the view of Richard Wolheim, the unconscious is only invoked where 114 there is a question of explaining the irrational. This is hardly faithful to Freud's unconscious which is always understood to be operative in the human subject, also at those times when its impact on the mental processing of the subject is not obvious, as in the case of clearly rational functioning. It seems problematic in explanations of mental processing only then to invoke the unconscious when other avenues of explanation are found to be inadequate. What might be called for is a radical rethinking of the notion of the unconscious of the kind which Lacan suggests in order to rethink the psychoanalytic enterprise in a thorough going way. That would involve very far-reaching and fundamental re orientation of both analytic theory and technique. What I want to do here is take the more limited context of main-stream psychological science and look at ways in which its basic orientation might be re-interpreted in the light of the Lacardan criticism of analysis and the proper place of the unconscious in that enterprise. The Proper Study of Mankind. In the Thirteenth Society Lecture delivered before the Psychological Society of Ireland more than ten years ago, Cormac Gallagher sketched out some crucial considerations in this context, and I want to revisit some of these considerations here and attempt to draw out some further implications.7 Pointing out some of the fundamental difficulties there are for a proper study of mankind for a psychology too closely identified with a rigid Anglo-American empiricism, Gallagher suggests that what might be required is a philosophical shift towards a more appropriate understanding of the human subject. The questions that he suggests that arise for psychology in relation to what should be its proper object are profoundly philosophical ones, which are beyond the limits of the present introductory considerations. Suffice it to say for the moment that the problems for psychology relate to its philosophical underpinning in 7 C. Gallagher. 'The Psychologist as Psychoanalyst: The Proper Study of Mankind'. in The Irish Journal of Psychology. Vol 8, No. 2 Winter 1987. pp. 111-125. 115 empiricism as a philosophy. It is overly indebted to the experimentalism of W. Wundt, and has totally neglected the starting point of F. Brentano's and his considerations on psychology from what he called an empirical standpoint.8 Gallagher goes on to offer some critically important considerations in regard to the relationship between psychology and psychoanalysis. Quoting Theodor Reik he reminds us that: 'The psychoanalyst is above all a psychologist, whatever else he may be physician, teacher, jurist, pastor analysis will exist as an essential part of psychology or not at all. For a psychologist, he suggests, this states the correct position for psychoanalysis, and he calls for the recentering of the aims and methods of psychology in the light of the discoveries of psychoanalysis. This would involve psychology in focusing on the speaking subject as distinct from what has hitherto been the main focus, namely the experimental subject. It is fundamental to a psychoanalysis properly so called to regard the speaking subject as being at the centre of its concern. That is the locus of the emergence of the unconscious of the subject and the desire that structures everything else. Drawing on the re reading of Freud by Lacan, Gallagher goes on to challenge psychology to address all that emerges from such a contemporary analysis and look at its implications for its own methods and approaches to its subject matter. Lacan argues, following Freud, that what is centred, to the human subject is desire, and any theory of human nature which didn't take account of that was fundamentally flawed. It is further clear from Freud that that desire is basically unconscious. This applies of course also to the desire of the analyst. The central challenge to the science of psychology was to find ways of accommodating the findings of analysis with all that that implies. Scientific psychology could no longer then simply adhere to the common paradigms of what is regarded as science, but would have to elaborate a method proper to its own peculiar topic, namely the human subject. 8 For an analysis and comparison of Wundt's and Brentano's starting point for psychology see my unpublished MA thesis on The Implications ofLonergan's Insight for Cognitive Psychology, UCD, 1976. 116 A World of Meaning The human subject is bom into a pre-existing world of meaning, and the goal of development is to constitute itself in that world and take a position in it. The world as experienced in sense experience is radically a mediated world and the predominant mode of that mediation is linguistic or symbolic. So it follows that an understanding of subjectivity will involve the psychologist - as well as the analyst, and all other disciplines concerned with human sciences properly so called - with the basic question of meaning. One can of course take the word in the sense of a noun, where it has to do essentially with the overall context of the word and how it is used in the language, following Wittgenstein. Where does the word make sense, fit in, or where does it belong in such a manner as to conform to the grammar and syntax of the language of which it forms a part. The meaning of a word is given by its place in the chain of language, or of signifiers as Lacan has it. Any human subject can be said to understand the meaning of the word when he can use the word as it is understood by the hearers. But apart from the meaning as a substantive, there is the sense of meaning as intending, wanting, planning, etc. and of course, in a basic way, desiring.9 The world given by pre-existing meaning is already there, given to the experiencing subject. It is to that larger world mediated by meaning that we refer to when we speak of the real world, and in it we live out our lives. But the subject knows this world to be insecure because meaning is insecure, since besides truth there is error, besides fact there is fiction, besides honesty there is deceit, and besides science there is myth. Lonergan speaks also of meaning in the second sense. Besides the world given in experience there is also the world that we make, as he puts it. The world that we make, we first intend, and this might be followed by planning, structuring and organising. What one might consider to be intended is a transformed 9 For a useful discussion of meaning in this sense, see B. Lonergan's fDimensions of Meaning' in Collection: papers by Bernard Lonergan, F. Crowe (Ed), New York, Herder and Herder, 1967, pp. 252-67. 117 world. The human subject doesn't simply accept the world as given, but through his desire attempts, however unsuccessfully, to transform it. It is in that sense that one might say that the subject constitutes his world. Lonergan speaks at this point of the emergence of the existential subject and by that he means the place where the subject finds out for himself that he has to decide for himself what he has to make of himself. Lonergan's account of meaning is of importance here even though he doesn't explicitly advert to the operations of the unconscious in any clear way. But what is useful is the detailed analysis of human meaning, and its place in the structure of the human subject It is being suggested here that the Lacanian symbolic order is conceivable in terms of the world as mediated, and the world as constituted by the subject as being that which emerges progressively in the unfolding of human desire. This particular sketch of a theory of meaning is offered simply to indicate what the challenge to a human science of psychology might involve. It would have to take the basic issue of meaning as a central concern, and include the enormous elaboration of that that is implied in Freud's initial discoveries and Lacan's later re-formulations of them. The challenge offered to Irish psychologists by Gallagher more than ten years ago has gone largely unanswered. But it is gratifying that it has been issued and that the work of sketching the framework for a much needed human psychology and psychoanalysis continues in Dublin under his inspiration. The sub-title of the present review speaks of a paradigm for psychology. Perhaps in the light of what has emerged from that review we cannot be said to be nearer to anything like a useful paradigm. But some crucial questions have been asked, and of particular importance seems to be the issue of meaning touched on above. Perhaps that is all one can manage for the moment, but it is none the less important. To have asked the right or the most useful question is all an analyst can ever hope for. The answer or answers must come from somewhere else, perhaps from the unfolding subjectivity of the readers 118 Address for correspondence: APPX School o f Psychotherapy S t Vincent's Hospital Elm Park Dublin 4 LECTU1E RAISONNÉE ET CRITIQUE DES ŒUVRES DE FREUD ET DE LACAN Charles Melman 4^ année, Séminaire du 8 octobre 1998 à mon cher Cormac Gallagher, en témoignage d'amitié Certains d'entre vous ont peut-être eu connaissance d'un document que je vous ai apporté ce soir, parce que je trouve ces phénomènes assez intéressants pour ouvrir le séminaire cette armée. Je ne sais pas si la presse, si les média, chez nous, en ont parlé. Il s'agit d'une exposition qui a eu lieu au Musée de la Technique et du Travail de Mannheim, ville allemande d'une certaine importance. Cette exposition s'intitule Les mondes du corps> regards dans le corps humain et comprend ... deux cents cadavres qui ont subi un traitement spécial la 'plastination' inventée par Monsieur Gunter von Hagens. Ce monsieur a donc réuni deux cents cadavres qui sont des écorchés dont la musculature est remarquablement mise en évidence, dont parfois la calotte crânienne est retirée, ce qui permet de voir les hémisphères cérébraux. Lorsqu’il s’agit de malades, Monsieur von Hagens s'est arrangé pour qu'on puisse voir directement l'organe malade, le foie, le coeur, les poumons. Cette exposition a eu sept cent mille visiteurs à Mannheim ... Ce qui entre autres choses assure un certain bien-être matériel à Monsieur Gunter von Hagens, d'autant que, après le succès considérable ainsi rencontré, elle est immédiatement partie vers où? Le... Japon! Du reste, monsieur von Hagens promet d’être 'plastiné' lui-même quand le moment viendra et de figurer, on pourra lui rendre visite, dans cette exposition. Enfin! il est très content. 120 J'ai pris cette manifestation comme point de départ de ce qui aura à nous concerner cette année, dans la mesure où elle illustre de quelle façon le pouvoir de la technique (ici la 'plastination') est en mesure de nous procurer des jouissances nouvelles, en l'occurrence de porter la nécrophilie à un niveau de diffusion jusqu'ici peu égalé. Car c'est bien de cela qu’il s'agit - évidemment, c'est une exposition scientifique, puisqu'il s'agit d'anatomie, et puis de pathologie! Mais enfin, je ne suis pas certain que les sept cent mille visiteurs aient été motivés par le noble mobile de s'instruire. Lors de notre semaine d'été la question de jouissances nouvelles était donc posée à partir du séminaire sur V angoisse que nous avons largement survolé, et d'une façon qui me paraît elle aussi intéressante. Nous l'avons, à mon goût, survolé comme s'il s'agissait d'un texte scientifique, c'est-à-dire impliquant notre propre division par rapport à lui. Comme s'il s’agissait non pas de remarques concernant la psychopathologie de la vie quotidienne, mais d'une élaboration sur cette chose étrange que constituerait peut-être l'angoisse, à laquelle nous nous intéressions ... Tout ceci me paraît rejoindre ce qui me semble être le succès grandissant de la démarche scientifique, en tant qu'elle implique a priori notre propre division par rapport à l'objet d'étude, et d'autre part son triomphe lié moins à son éventuelle exactitude qu’à sa faculté de nous offrir donc des jouissances nouvelles. Car en voilà une tout de même assez! Nous allons pouvoir, sans avoir besoin de nous cacher dans les cimetières pour ceux que cela intéressait, nous allons pouvoir à la lumière des néons et dans une joyeuse cohue générale, jouir de ces cadavres! C'est-à-dire que ce progrès dans lequel nous sommes ne peut pas, je me permets de faire cette remarque, ne peut pas manquer de nous rappeler qu'après tout, c'est au nom de la science que s'est engagé, il y a soixante ans, un type d'action qui lui aussi comprenait cette idée: la science justifiait qu'au titre d'expérimentation, l'on puisse fabriquer des cadavres ... - autrement dit que l'on puisse au nom de la science, jouir des corps jusqu'au bout! Et si cette sorte de rétroaction que je vous propose est exacte, elle éclaire d'un jour qui n’a peut-être pas été souvent proposé ce qui s'est passé il y a soixante ans, c'est-à-dire une fois encore la prévalence de la référence à la science pour guider les conduites, pour les justifier, pour leur donner leur soubassement éthique, et là aussi donner la mesure d'actions qui ne pouvaient connaître plus aucune limite, plus aucune limitation. On ne saurait trop rappeler à cette occasion que à ceux qu'on a appelés les ’troupes spéciales1 qui étaient engagées pour la fabrication ainsi des cadavres sur les arrières des troupes nazies qui filaient vers l’avant, il était strictement proscrit d'être, en aucun cas, pathétiquement engagés par leur action. Autrement dit, il s'agissait d'agir en scien-tifiques ; y mettre le moindre pathos était contraire à ce qui était attendu d'eux. Ils avaient à exercer une action de nettoyage, un point, c'est tout ! Ceci nous ramène à l'angoisse. Je me suis permis d'évoquer au cours de ce séminaire, la façon dont finalement nous nous y sommes habitués, dont nous l'apprivoisons, et la façon dont elle en vient à constituer une modalité de jouissance nouvelle - et collective. Car Lacan disait 'on se défend contre l’angoisse', 'on se défend contre la proximité de l'objet a', sauf si, bien entendu, l'effet d'angoisse produit par cette approche est susceptible d'alimenter des jouissances nouvelles, y compris bien entendu mortifères. En recueillant le témoignage de cette manifestation, j'étais bien obligé de repenser à ceci: Lacan nous a laissés en panne, en panne volontaire, sur deux points: l'un concerne son séminaire sur Les noms du Père (et on déplorera toujours que nous n'ayons aucun accès au dossier des notes qu'il avait constituées pour tenir ce séminaire, dossier qui existe, qui doit être dans un tiroir, je ne sais même pas si quelqu'un l'a ouvert ou s'y est intéressé!) et l’autre panne, c'est qu'il est resté très discret à l’endroit de cette expression remarquable de la pensée humaine qui s'appelle la logique, et qui est l'ossature de la démarche scientifique. Il est resté discret à l'endroit de la logique, bien qu'à son propos, il ait utilisé des formulations très intéressantes mais pour des raisons qui me semblent éminemment pratiques: j’imagine qu’il ne souhaitait pas décourager ... l'ardente jeunesse qui, venue de l’École Normale, s'intéressait à son enseignement, et pour qui le rapport, la référence faite à la logique était aussi bien celle qui devait donner appui à leur action privée ou sociale, que celle qui devait régler leur démarche et leurs écrits. Car enfin, il est quand même surprenant que des psychanalystes ne s'interrogent pas davantage, eux qui sont délibérément critiques, aussi bien vis-à-vis des diverses productions dites ’intellectuelles1que de la leur! Comment se fait-il que des psychanalystes entérinent de façon volontiers automatique les affirmations d'un mode d'écriture qui, comme tous les modes d’écriture, doit être réfléchi et soumis à la critique? Qu’est-ce qui fait que des analystes semblent désarmés ou sans pouvoir à l'endroit d'une argumentation, dès lors qu'elle se réfère à la logique, et sans être en mesure eux-mêmes de mieux établir ce qui serait la leur ? Parce qu'après tout, un analyste est supposé ne pas dire n'importe quoi. Il est supposé être pris dans une stricte rationalité. Même s'il se trompe, néanmoins sa démarche n'a rien à voir avec ce qui pourrait être celle du voyant ou du thaumaturge, ou de l'interprète des songes. C'est une démarche qui, chaque fois, se réfère à une rationalité, même quand elle est dépassée (celle de Freud par exemple, sa référence à la thermodynamique, etc.). Mais il se réfère lui aussi à la rationalité et, semble-t-il, sans être en mesure de soutenir la sienne ni du même coup de tenir sa place quant à la façon dont la démarche scientifique devrait être appréhendée. C'est pour cela qu'on ne peut que se féliciter des Journées qui ont eu lieu le week-end dernier et où un certain nombre d'interventions, fort diverses, bien entendu inégales, mais toutes intéressantes parce que témoignant toutes d'une certaine approche de ce qui est ici en cause. Je crois avoir à cette occasion commencé à apporter quelques propositions que je vais me permettre de reprendre, pour que là encore votre critique puisse éventuellement m'aider dans ce chemin que je poursuis et que, comme je le disais tout à l'heure, Lacan nous a épargné. On pourrait, ce chemin, le baliser de quelques formules de Lacan. L'un des participants à ces Journées, lui-même mathématicien et vieux copain de route de Lacan, nous a dit que finalement, Lacan laisse de côté l'intuition. Il ne marche pas selon le chemin qui plaît aux scientifiques, c'est-à-dire la démonstration: il y a chez Lacan très peu de démonstrations à proprement parler mathématiques et donc ses énoncés se soutiennent avant tout de l'auteur de rénonciation. Ht il fait la grosse voix pour dire des trucs comme ’il n'y a pas de rapport sexuel' ou que 'La femme n'existe pas'. Et tout cela tient par le fait que c'est Lacan qui le dit, et sousentendu, vous répétez ce qu'il dit et vous le prenez ainsi parce qu'il Va dit. Donc l'argument d'autorité prévaudrait. Prenons donc un certain nombre de formules de Lacan pour baliser mon chemin, le rendre peut-être moins aride, par exemple 'la science commence avec la possibilité d'écrire dans un ensemble de formules des petites lettres, susceptibles dès lors dans ces formules de prendre chacune toutes les valeurs'. Voilà par exemple une assertion de Lacan. Une autre assertion ’il a fallu une société de maîtres pour que naisse la science. Là où il n'y avait pas d'esclaves (évocation de la Chine), pas de science!' ce qui est vrai d'ailleurs. La culture arabe, elle, au contraire, s'est montrée très tôt éprise de scientificité ... Ceci mérite d'être repris dés lors par ce qui souligne la distinction du signifiant et de la lettre. Je dois dire que je m'étais déjà bagarré avec ce genre de choses à propos d'un livre de Serge Leclaire, Psychanalyser, où il dit 'au commencement est la lettre' - non pas le Verbe mais la lettre. Donc distinction du signifiant et de la lettre en tant que le signifiant, comme nous le savons par cœur, se distingue avant tout, chacun d'être différent des autres, et donc différent de lui-même puisque son usage, son emploi n'est jamais que métaphorique ou métonymique ; alors que la lettre, nous savons par l'introduction aux Écrits de quelle façon Lacan en situe la genèse, c'est-à-dire par un mouvement lié aux propriétés d'une chaîne, mouvement décrit par Markov. Autrement dit, à partir du moment où dans une chaîne aléatoire de lettres, je les regroupe par trois (je simplifie) il va s'organiser un certain nombre d'exclusions à tel ou tel moment de la chaîne. 124 Donc cette lettre dont Lacan prend le souci dès l’entrée des Écrits des Écritsl ... - il ne s'agit pas de séminaires, de ce qui se supporte de la voix et vous savez de quelle façon notre ami Jean-Claude Milner s'insurge contre tout ce qui ferait référence à la présence de la voix dans l'enseignement de Lacan, cherchant à le réduire à ce qui est pure écriture, pure inscription . cette lettre, elle, contrairement au signifiant qui est donc différent de lui-même, cette lettre est toujours identique à elle-même. C'est-à-dire qu'elle ne renvoie aucunement à sa différence avec les autres lettres et elle ne renvoie pas non plus à quelque obscur réfèrent qui viendrait lui procurer un quelconque signifié. D'être réelle, la lettre a cette vertu d'être toujours identique à elle-même et Lacan le dit dans cette leçon de séminaire consacrée à Dupin et à La lettre volée de Poe, elle entraîne toujours le réel avec elle et, dit-il, même si je la déchire (autrement dit si elle perd de sa forme), elle reste la lettre. Le réfèrent du signifiant: à partir du moment où il se trouve protégé contre la psychose qui accompagne cette vertu chez lui d'être chaque fois différent de lui-même et de renvoyer du même coup à un signifié qui n'est rien d'autre que celui de la pure différence (dans cette normalité du fonctionnement du signifiant, nous sommes dans la psychose, et c'est bien pourquoi Lacan disait que la psychose, c'était 'normal'), nous savons dès lors que dans le référent, ce réfèrent jusque là organisé par la différence, s'isole un trait un; il va se trouver, ce trait un, supporter une interprétation phallique et les signifiants, ’traits unaires1par la même opération, ne vont plus avoir qu'un unique signifié. Bien qu'ils soient tous différents les uns des autres, ils n'ont plus qu'un unique signifié, le phallus. C'est-à-dire qu'ils n'ont qu'une valeur. La lettre a cette propriété de pouvoir endosser toutes les valeurs, et il faut s'interroger sur ce que peut vouloir dire ce 'toutes', pour Lacan, et s'il ne se résumait pas à l'ensemble des grandeurs que la lettre peut venir supporter. Mais la lettre en tout cas, les deux valeurs que nous connaissons en ce qui nous regarde, ce sont la valeur phallique et la valeur Autre. Et prêtons à la lettre ce pouvoir de représenter et de supporter aussi bien avec elle la valeur phallique que la valeur Autre. 125 Il serait possible à cet endroit d'engager une digression qui risquerait peut-être d'être amusante. Alors ça soulagerait un peu ... il faut faire cela (dans une leçon, il faut toujours introduire un petit moment amusant pour relancer l'attentioni). On pourrait partir de ce fait bien connu, le goût pour l’écriture, et inversement aussi bien une espèce d'impossibilité de s'exercer à ce noble art. Goût pour l'écriture, c'est-à-dire une espèce de partie de pêche pour en quelque sorte récupérer toutes ces lettres que le jeu de la chaîne signifiante a pu ainsi oblitérer, et qui sont venues à destination d'être refoulées, l'écriture permettant en cette affaire le retour du refoulé. Et la jouissance de ce qu'il faut bien considérer hélas! comme étant l'objet nutnber one, la lettre, l'objet par excellence! Je faisais remarquer à l'occasion de ces Journées, cette conférence faite à lfAssociation dans le cadre du groupe dit 'de Cordoue’ par Shmuel Trigano venu nous évoquer de façon très plaisante, intéressante, et instructive, le travail des talmudistes et des kabbalistes. Je suppose que l'ensemble de l'auditoire a pu saisir de quelle façon on pouvait être aspiré par cette jouissance de la combinatoire de la lettre, au point d'y consacrer sa vie entière et assurément dans une relation, il faudrait bien le dire, avec le vrai objet de la jouissance. La lettre à cet égard, ce n'est pas du semblant! L'écriture, il y a une moitié de la population à laquelle nous sommes très attachés et qui a volontiers et très facilement une ambition d'écrire, cette moitié de la population étant la moitié féminine, avec des réussites bien entendu certaines et des échecs non moins certains, tout cela, c'est bien normal. Mais on pourrait se dire que si chez le scribouillard mâle, il ne s'agit jamais que de retrouver, de faire revenir au jour des lettres refoulées, aller chercher dans la poubelle tout ce qui est venu là s’accumuler et pouvoir ainsi en faire son festin, chez une dame, il s'agit peut-être plus volontiers, par le jeu de l'écriture, de se créer un refoulement. Parce que a priori, pour elle, dans le champ de l'Autre, il n'y a aucune raison pour qu'il y ait quelque refoulement que ce soit. Et donc du même coup une certaine nostalgie de pouvoir jouir de cet objet vrai, et 126 non plus sous la forme du semblant qu'elle représente, elle, mais en cernant enfin ce qui fait son prix, à elle. Et en dégageant en même temps ... qu'est ce qu'on appelle un style? Moi, j'aurais envie de dire que ce qui fait la beauté du style, d'un style, c'est quand on perçoit bien que chez un auteur donné, il y a un module, autrement dit que le jeu des métaphores, des métonymies, le balancement des phrases, leur groupement, leur équilibre, finalement s'organisent autour d’un espace qui est toujours le même. Et l'effet de beauté qu'est susceptible de produire cette réalisation virtuelle, mais aussi bien réelle de cet espace en tant qu'il s'avère être le moteur, le moteur fidèle, constant régulier, de ce qui donne à ces écrits justement ce que l'on appelle un style. Vous savez que Lacan dit que le style, c'est le sujet, et d'abord de 'celui à qui l'on s'adresse', autre formule. Mais rien ne nous empêche de justifier ce que je vous évoque par le fait que la possibilité du style chez l'une de nos amies ou de nos compagnes est l'exercice qui lui permet ainsi de se créer une demeure subjective dans l'Autre, elle qui singulièrement est contrainte à jouer les hystériques pour essayer de faire valoir qu'un sujet, elle en serait un, elle aussi... En quoi cela nous intéresse-t-il? En ce que cela débouche sur une possibilité déjà incluse dans ce que j'évoquais tout à l'heure à propos de cette funeste exposition : des techniques du corps - ici en l’occurrence, l'écriture - seraient peut-être susceptibles d'organiser, de mettre en place la castration par un cheminement qui ne devrait donc plus rien au Nomdu-Père, - surtout que dans le cas présent, le Nom-du-Père se montre bien incapable de l'assurer pour une femme. Cette mise en place par des moyens purement techniques, des exercices corporels, en quelque sorte, permettrait de s'offrir du même coup des jouissances neuves ou inédites. Pourquoi ce que je raconte là était-il inclus dans mon départ? Il est clair que l'un des intérêts, des enthousiasmes que la science soulève, c'est qu'elle s'avère effectivement capable par des phénomènes d’accoutumance ou d’habitude, de créer des jouissances aussi bien nouvelles que celles-là, extrêmes, c'est-à-dire d'emblée de l'ordre de l'ujipiç, c'est-à-dire sans limites, des jouissances qui ne sont plus commandées par ce qu'il en serait d'un rapport à un semblant et liées au maintien nécessaire de la limite, mais fabrication d’une jouissance allant délibérément à l'uPpiç à l'extrême, comme notre Gunter von Hagens, allant tout de suite à une jouissance ... Donner à chacun la faculté de jouir des morts, c'est quand même une possibilité qui n'est due qu'à la science! Ce qui nous repose une question qui a été abordée, introduite au cours de ces Journées par une remarque très pertinente de Castel, c’est-àdire qu'il y aurait deux façons de transmettre le savoir, l'une transmission de la science, et puis l'autre par la cohabitation. La cohabitation avec X et les questions humoristiques qui alors se posent pour tous ceux qui ont approché les couples de personnages célèbres et qui n'ont jamais manqué d'être surpris par le fait que l'épouse du célèbre philosophe semblait en savoir beaucoup plus que tous ses élèves sur ce que pensait le Maître. Et cela d'abord évidemment parce qu'elle lui serrait soigneusement la vis (c'est une métaphore ...) mais ensuite parce que de partager son lit, sa table, son intimité, d’avoir avec lui quelques rapports intimes lui donnait sur le bonhomme un type de savoir que les élèves les plus attentionnés, les plus empressés, les plus chaleureux, les plus charmants, les plus mignons ne pouvaient avoir. Et je pourrai vous donner des noms si vous en voulez. Oui? Vous voulez des noms? Madame Heidegger était très au fait de la philosophie de son mari, et sûrement plus que les élèves qui se pressaient à la table du maître. Ce n’était pas le cas, alors c'est intéressant, ce n’était manifestement pas le cas de Madame Freud. Je ne sais pas pourquoi... Mais j’évoque devant vous ce que Lacan appelait les techniques du corps et dont il dit quelque part que finalement, on ne sait pas très bien jusqu’où vont leurs pouvoirs, jusqu'à quel point elles sont en mesure d'apprendre au corps à jouir de la façon qu'elles enseignent sans autre référence, c’est-à-dire sans passage par le signifiant C'est aussi pourquoi les histoires de séduction dans l'enfance ne sont pas, bien entendu ! je serais désolé que ce que j'ai dit là-dessus puisse prêter à confusion, ne sont 128 pas sans conséquences. Il est certain qu'il y a des enfants pour qui ce type d'expérience a pu être déterminant, nous le voyons en analyse, mais c'est aussi pourquoi on rencontre si fréquemment chez les dames cette idée que l'on a abusé d'elles dans leur enfance, que leur savoir est lié à une expérience corporelle. Puisque leur savoir ne peut être lié à une castration qui serait opérée par le père. Alors d'où leur vient-il, leur savoir sexuel, leur savoir du sexe? A la limite, elles n'ont pas d'autre moyen pour expliquer le fait qu'un beau jour, elles se sont trouvées éveillées au sexuel. Alors, ce pouvoir des techniques du corps et donc de la science ne peut que nous faire revenir à l'examen de la validité de sa démarche. Examen qui paraîtra d'emblée futile puisque la validité de sa démarche se résout précisément dans le fait qu'elle marche ou pas et que si elle marche, elle est donc valide. Et Lacan s'étonnait sur ce fait qu'un agencement de petites lettres s'avère opératoire sur le réel, il s'en étonnait. Cela ne lui semblait pas aller de soi. Pourquoi ça marche, après tout? En tout cas, je souhaite attirer de nouveau votre attention ce soir, sur le fait que toute la démarche analytique consiste à refuser les connecteurs logiques que le discours conscient établit entre les propositions pour systématiquement les suspecter et affirmer (ce qui est encore plus grave!) qu'aucun connecteur logique entre les propositions ne saurait être considéré comme ultime et définitif. Autrement dit, vous analysez un rêve, vous avez une suite de propositions, du fait de le rapporter à l'analyste vous êtes forcément amené à y introduire des connecteurs logiques, il n'est pas d'adresse à autrui qui ne comporte la référence à de tels connecteurs. Si je ne m'en sers pas, il dira que je suis complètement dinguel Si j'avance des propositions contradictoires par exemple, il dira... ça ne va pas! Ou des implications complètement arbitraires mais que la logique respecte à partir du moment où la forme est respectée, il dira que je suis m alade... Eh bien, tout le travail de l'analyste est d'être fidèle au travail du rêve lui-même. Je le faisais remarquer en me référant à quelques pages 129 essentielles de la Traumdeutung (chapitre VI sur l’élaboration du rêve) concernant la représentation des relations logiques dans le rêve, où Freud souligne que le rêve n'a aucun moyen de représenter les relations logiques, les connecteurs logiques. Cela mériterait de sa part un étonnement un peu plus grand, parce que le rêve a tous les moyens de figuration. Pourquoi n'aurait-il pas des moyens à lui, de son invention à lui, pour représenter les connecteurs logiques? Mais il faudrait franchir le pas, et dire que l’inconscient ignore les connecteurs logiques. Dans l'inconscient, il n'y a pas de ... S'il y a dans l'inconscient un 'ou bien, ou bien', c'est un 'ou bien, ou bien' qui déjà figure une adresse à un interlocuteur. Alors vous direz, oui, mais Lacan souligne que les rêves en analyse sont toujours des rêves adressés à l'analyste. Certes mais dans le texte du rêve lui-même, vous ne trouvez pas la trace du moindre connecteur logique. Et si chez Freud, il y a quelques pages consacrées à la façon de représenter la négation par la contradiction dans le rêve, ce sont des pages intéressantes mais qui montrent bien que cette contradiction qu'évoque Freud à ce propos n'est pas forcément celle qui est équivalente au signe moins de la négation ou bien à une contradiction qui serait proprement logique. Si l'inconscient est structuré comme un langage, il est fait d'unités de tailles fort diverses : la lettre, le phonème, le mot, le bout de phrase, voire une séquence phrasée tout entière; l’inconscient n’a pas d’unité en quelque sorte fixe . Ce qui compte, c'est que ça fait unité, mais sa taille dans la chaîne signifiante peut être fort variable. Mais si l'inconscient ignore les connecteurs logiques, c'est sans doute que l'inconscient n'est pas organisé ... il faut que je fasse un peu attention dans la façon de le dire pour ne pas introduire de confusion ... Dans la mesure où l’unité fondamentale de l'inconscient est la lettre, nous avons vu que le réfèrent de la lettre, ce n'est pas le phallus, que la lettre porte avec elle l'ombre du phallus qui a causé sa chute, mais ce n ’est pas le phallus, le réfèrent de la lettre. Du même coup, il n'y a pas une quelconque organisation de séquences dans l'inconscient qui serait régie par une rigueur 'connexion, disjonction, implication (encore que l'implication ne soit qu'une variante de la disjonction), négation,’, il n'y a nulle part dans l'inconscient la marque de ce qui unit, de ce qui sépare et de ce qui nie et où - j’aurai l'occasion lorsque j'écrirai là-dessus de vous le montrer mais je ne le reprendrai pas à ce séminaire -, et où on peut voir le passage dans la réalité du phallus avec ses connecteurs logiques, le passage dans la réalité du phallus que la chaîne écrite forclôt. Je m'en suis mieux expliqué l'autre jour qu'aujourd’hui, mais pour vous le rendre mieux sensible, le poinçon du fantasme, qu'est-ce que c'est? Vous pouvez le lire, dit Lacan, comme le signe de la conjonction, de la disjonction, de l'implication, du ’plus grand que’, du ’plus petit que’. Lacan prend l'arbitraire de ramener tous les connecteurs logiques à un unique signe, peu importe que vous vous en serviez pour en faire une conjonction, une disjonction ou une négation. Il ramène tout cela à un unique signe qui sera pour lui le poinçon, non seulement pour des raisons de facilité d’écriture puisque ce sont les deux signes logiques de conjonction et de disjonction qui se réunissent, mais aussi parce que le poinçon, c'est précisément ce qui soustrait, ce qui opère l'opération d'une ponction, le poinçon, c'est ce qui ponctionne, d'abord. Un texte, je me permets de reprendre ce point que j'ai déjà plusieurs fois abordé, n'a que deux moyens de faire valoir sa validité : - Ou bien l'autorité de I’énonciateur, de celui qui parle - Ou bien la consistance logique, c’est-à-dire les phénomènes de consécution, du fait qu’il y a une proposition qui vient engendrer l'autre dans un mouvement, dans un devenir qui paraît relever du nécessaire. Il ne peut pas en être autrement, une fois qu'on a posé Ifun, c'est l'autre qui vient forcément, et puis l'autre. Il apparaît d’une façon qui ne saurait nous étonner que si vous annulez la valeur de vérité de l'énonciation, et ce qui la supporte, c'est-àdire le phallus, vous faites automatiquement apparaître dans la chaîne écrite la prévalence de lois pour régir la consécution des propositions, et c'est la rigueur de cette consécution qui vaut pour vérité alors que la vérité, celle de l’énonciation, car il n'y en a pas d’autre, a été forclose! 131 C'est pourquoi aussi, toujours dans ce texte d'introduction aux Écrits, vous voyez comment Lacan dit à propos des écrits (j'ai répété ça cent fois!) qu'ils 's'en vont au vent comme traites folles' ... Ce sont des prescriptions, comment dirais-je, dont plus personne ne sait quel en est l'auteur, qui les a émises, ni ce qu'elles signifient, et qui s'en vont comme ça, avoir leurs effets d'impératifs. Si Lacan ne fait pas de démonstration, c'est tout simplement parce que la discipline à laquelle il se réfère fait la critique de ce qu'on appelle la démonstration logique et que, tirant la leçon de la constitution de l'inconscient, il retient, comme le montre l'analyse des rêves, que ce qui vaut dans l'inconscient n'est rien d'autre que, non pas la consécution, mais la contiguïté. C'est parce que les divers éléments se trouvent en relation de voisinage, que vous allez de l'un à l’autre ... Alors vous tracez des réseaux, et puis avec des retours, avec des recoupements ... mais ce qui fait que l'ensemble tient, c'est que chacun est avec l'autre dans une relation qui n'est pas de conjonction ni d'implication, ni de disjonction, mais est avec l'autre dans une relation de voisinage. En vous disant cela, je crois suffisamment évoquer ce qui constitue la justification que Lacan fasse de la topologie qui est donc la science des voisinages, fasse de la topologie le domaine dont il y a à attendre une logique qui serait cohérente avec notre domaine. Alors que la logique classique est organisée sur le principe de la conjonction et de l'exclusion, c'est-à-dire de la coupure, commencée même par Platon. Lacan s'amuse évidemment à penser qu'il s'agit de la définition du pêcheur, c'est-à-dire que vous procédez tout le temps par disjonctions et par coupures, vous élaguez sans cesse. Eh bien, il est, je crois, essentiel pour la façon dont nous 'pigeons' notre domaine de ne pas faire du réel, c'est-à-dire de ce qui est ainsi retranché, un espace de rebut et un espace qui dès lors ne nous concernerait pas mais nous avons, grâce à la topologie et à sa capacité de n'étudier que les voisinages et éventuellement s'il y a une coupure, les effets d’une coupure, à faire du réel cette dimension propre à assurer le fonctionnement de la psyché. 132 Est-ce à dire que la psychanalyse serait, elle aussi, la science du réel? Mais évidemment pas! Si Lacan dit que 'la logique est la science du réel', c’est parce que le réel est précisément ce qui fait sa limite, ce qu'elle exclut Et elle passe son temps ainsi à retrancher. Alors que pour Lacan et c'est là, je crois, la mutation qui nous intéresse, le réel est au contraire ce qui est non pas à privilégier, mais en tout cas à traiter au titre d'une dimension égale aux deux autres. Voilà pourquoi il serait temps de nous engager, plus hardiment en tout cas, dans ce type de mise au clair qui devrait rendre beaucoup plus difficiles des ouvrages comme ceux de Sokal et Bricmont ... qui d'une certaine manière, de la part de leurs auteurs, sont justifiés - dans la mesure où les psychanalystes n'ont pas répondu à ce type de problèmes, n'ont pas interrogé, non pas la validité, de l'éthique de la science, etc., mais sa démarche même. Et donc en aucun cas elle ne saurait les terroriser, dans la mesure où justement tout leur travail, du fait que le sujet, comme le dit Lacan, c'est celui de la science, tout leur travail consiste à discuter ladite démarche et à lui opposer celle de l'activité désirante, celle qui supporte et maintient un brin d'humanité dans ces nouvelles offres de jouissance (à l'exemple de ce que je vous racontais tout à l'heure, cette 'plastination'...) qu'avec succès nous offre la science. Address for correspondance: Association Freudienne Internationale 15 Rue Bouchardor 75010 Paris France LACAN AND DALI - AN ANAMORPHIC ENCOUNTER? Olga Cox Cameron 'What fun I might have had Lacan's half-mocking, backward look at his early years from the vantage point of 1966, pinpoints his much publicised connection with Salvador Dali as a stopover, left long behind in his own intellectual odyssey. On the occasion of the publication of a first extract from Paul Duquenne's translation of Schreber's Memoirs of M y Nervous Illness, in the psychoanalytic journal Cahiers pour VAnalyse, Jacques Alain Miller invited Lacan to write an introduction. Lacan took advantage of this opportunity to review the trajectory of his own thought on psychotic structures and, typically, to flatten out the importance of 'connaissance paranoïaque', signalled as crucial in the article in The International Journal of Psychoanalysis of May 1951. What a fine career as an essayist I could have made for myself using this theme which lends itself to all kinds of aesthetic variations! One has only to think of all that our friend Dali has done with it. The doctoral thesis had theorised 'le cas Aimée as 'a developmental fixation at the level of the superego', but the slow working over of Aimée's story in the years immediately following 1932 offered Lacan a number of other salient elements which would reappear, metamorphosed, in the 1960's. Aimée's relationship with her elder sister, described in 1933 as haine amoureuse is a disturbed doubling which radically subverts the stability of the narcissistic image. Furthermore, this anomaly in subjective structure is identical to that found to be at the basis of certain homicidal attacks, which the psychiatrist Guiraud had described as unmotivated murders. These acts, frequently carried out in twilight states, and of which the perpetrator has no clear memory; 'reveal a specific anomaly identical to that found in psychosis'. Thirdly this anomaly is characterised by certain types of prelogical conceptual structures, which account for 'the often remarkable aesthetic creations produced in psychotic states'. The concluding sentences of De la Psychose raise three questions to which he will return in the sixties; firstly, the subjective structure which underpins psychosis; secondly, the manner in which this impacts on creative expression and by extension on language itself; and thirdly, what he will call in the Seminar on Identification the abolition of the temporal dimension in a-subjective aggressivity. All of these questions converge on the topic of identification, most fully examined by Freud in The Ego and the Id in 1923 and in chapter seven of Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego two years earlier. In the doctoral thesis, Lacan had puzzled over the fact that Freud saw the super-ego as a passage from the outside to the inside, a reincorporation into the ego of a part of the outside world. By the sixties, a daunting panoply of topological surfaces will be invoked to account for the particular properties and functions of outside and inside in the constitution of all subjectivity, normal or psychotic. Lacan was not unaware that the questions about subjectivity, opened up throughout the sixties by means of the Moebuis strip, the Klein bottle, and eventually the Borromean Knot had already featured for some time in the work of creative artists. He himself said as much, notably in his 1966 article on Marguerite Duras's Le Ravissement de Lol V. Stein, but also at the end of the 1961-1962 Seminar on Identification, when, having quoted from Blanchot, 'the poet of our literature', he added; fI want to tell you that I am often aware of doing nothing other here than allowing you to advance with me to the point that all around us many of the best people have already got to'. This reference, in which he singles out the work of Blanchot and Klossowski, stands in contrast to the smiling dismissal of Dali's influence cited above. In the sixties Lacan will in fact quote Frege more often than Blanchot or Klossowski to illustrate subjective structure and the manner in which the functions of repetition and representation are intricated. In the thirties and forties, however, the writings of Salvador Dali, like his art, were moving strongly in the direction of a radical questioning, if not a downright subversion of the stability of these concepts. Also, Dali's writings which he himself considered not inferior to his painting, offer a deeply interesting commentary on the three inter related questions with which Lacan had ended his doctoral thesis, to wit, the particular crisis of subjectivity engendered by a too close doubling within the family structure, the relation between this structure and certain homicidal crimes, and the way in which familiar modes of representation may be sabotaged in the service of this subjectivity. In this paper I propose to examine not just Dali's influence on Lacan, but also the extraordinary convergence in the dominant concerns of both men insofar as it becomes retrospectively visible in Dali's writings, especially in his two autobiographies. Since the field of psychoanalysis is language, it seems more apt to look to these writings rather than to Dali's paintings. It would seem too that Lacan became interested in Dali via his published articles in Minotaure and not through direct contact with his painting. Not only do Dali's writings exemplify the thematic implications of Lacan's thesis, they also, like his paintings, introduce a very specific problematization of sameness and difference. This problematization, which furnishes the opening gambit of Lacan's Seminar on Identification in 1961, will become the focal point of modem French philosophy. From the 1960’s onward, as Descombes says in Le Meme et VAutre, the logic of identity has been countered by a thinking based on difference, and Deleuze asserts that, for contemporary thinkers, difference and repetition have replaced the identical and the negative as seminal concepts. Throughout the sixties Lacan inserts these questions into the heart of psychoanalytic theory. The result is a railroading of seriously difficult and abstract concepts through the well-worn definitions of psychosis, neurosis and perversion, expanding, complexifying and illuminating these definitions almost beyond recognition. Descombes rightly insisted that phenomena of representation furnish a privileged approach to the most authentic understanding of difference, since they provide access to the experience of incontestable while apparently inconceivable difference. In those of his seminars which focus on the function of repetition and the relation of the same to the different, Lacan will insist that he is speaking primarily of the relation of the subject to the signifier: 'What is in question is the relation of the subject to the signifier' he says in the opening lesson of the Seminar on Identification, repeating this messsage a little further on: 'Now more than ever I am going to make turn around the structure of language everything that I am going to say to you'. He then goes on to demonstrate his basic premises with examples taken not from the domain of language itself, but by means of topological surfaces. However, in the thirties, literature was quite remarkably extending the formal implications of what Lacan would call the radiceli duplicity of the subjective position. Most notable among French writers was Raymond Roussel, who died in 1932, and whose work, with its stunning coda, published posthumously in 1933, is an extraordinary exploration of the virtualities inherent in the repetitions of the signifier, and of the strangeness of the narrative space available in a language beset by doubleness. Lacan in the thirties looked to Caillois, Wallon and Kojéve to add shape to his theory of 'connaissance paranoiaque', and to psychoanalytic practice for the beginning of a theory of language. The questions raised at the end of his doctoral thesis will be most fully answered in the sixties when the relation of the subject to the signifier is theorised in these topological and mathematical metaphors. But Dali and Roussel had already created the shapes within writing itself which these metaphors attempt to outline. Furthermore, they explore the specificities of the relation of the subject to the signifier within structures which may be posited as psychotic. Dali made of his paranoid-critical method an instrument for the creation of great art, just as Roussel, whose celebrated 1procède1 is described by Deleuze as schizophrenic, fabricates from it his marvellously exotic fictional world. This paper will look at the immediate influence of Dali's writing on Lacan at the time of the doctoral thesis, and at the manner in which Lacan's thesis in turn inflected Dali's description of the paranoid-critical method. It will then supplement Dali's accounts of this mode of representation by an examination of the autobiographical writings which underpin his aesthetic theory. Dali is unambiguous in asserting their strict correlation, since the autobiographies set out to describe how he forged a sense of objectivity out of what he called the most terrible mental malady, 'while at the same time maintaining the freedom of the irreducible share of paranoia from which my genius derives'. The Writings of Salvador Dali The opening sentence of Ian Gibson's recent biography of Dali warns the unwary reader; Salvador Dali is not a trustworthy source of information about himself. From his adolescence he set out consciously to become a myth, and he continued to work at being Dali even after he had achieved his goal. A vital stage in the process was his The Secret Life of Salvador Dali written in 1942, when he was thirty-eight. Whatever its other qualities, the Secret Life is not concerned with rigorous autobiographical truth. On the contrary it goes out of its way to distort it, becoming in the process, a biographical minefield. It would assuredly be imprudent to replace the biographer's scepticism with a kind of uncritical mythopoeic credulity, but a psychoanalytic reading must accord as much importance to distortion and myth as it does to factual accuracy. Undoubtedly misinformation and fantasy play a large part in Dali's writings but this does not invalidate their interest. In 1979, in an interview on Spanish television, Dali put forward the view, that he was better as a writer than as a painter. While his one novel, Hidden Faces written in 1943, bears out Edmund Wilson's assertion that Dali was no novelist, his early essays on art theory and the first 138 autobiography, Secret Life, are recognised as outstanding achievements. It is these latter writings, the essays on the theory of art written between 1930 and 1935, and Secret Life, as well as later autobiographical writings, which are of relevance here. The essays on art theory energetically endorse a new mode of representation, dubbed by Dali the paranoiac-critical method, while the autobiographies link this representational innovation to what is perceived by Dali as anomalies in his own psychic structure, connected to circumstances in his early life. Dali's insistence on the centrality of these events is rubbished by his biographer. It remains true nonetheless that for all of Dali's life this story continued to function as a kind of personal myth in the Lacanian sense of the term. Chronological considerations require that the essays on art theory which relate directly to the intellectual and aesthetic osmosis that occurred in his first meeting with Lacan should take precedence over an examination of the autobiographies. However it is impossible not to begin with Dali's exuberant account of that first meeting in Chapter One of The Secret Life of Salvador Dali, published in English in 1942. This chapter consists in a series of unrelated, perhaps loosely chronological episodes which dramatise the outsider status of the writer with respect to the norm of human interchange, as well as the sometimes ludicrous consequences of his lack of self-presence. Among these 'Anecdotic Self-Portraits' is the story of his first meeting with Lacan: I seem destined to a truculent eccentricity whether I wish it or no. I was 33 ... One day in Paris I received a telephone call from a brilliant young psychiatrist. He had just read an article of mine in Le Minotaure on The Inner Mechanisms of Paranoiac Activity. He congratulated me and expressed his astonishment at the accuracy of my scientific knowledge of this subject which was so generally misunderstood. He wished to see me to talk over this question. We agreed to meet late that very afternoon in my studio on Rue Gauget. I spent the whole afternoon in a state of extreme agitation at the prospect of our interview and I tried to plan in advance the course of our conversation. My ideas were so often regarded even by my closest friends in the surrealist group as paradoxical notions - tinged with genius to be sure - that I was flattered finally to be considered in strictly scientific circles. Hence I was anxious that everything about our first exchange of ideas should be perfectly normal and serious. While waiting for the young psychiatrist's arrival I continued working on the portrait of the Viscountess de Noailles on which I was then engaged. This painting was executed directly on copper. The highly burnished metal cast mirror-like reflections which made it difficult for me to see my drawing clearly. I noticed as I had before, that it was easier to see what I was doing where the reflection was brightest. At once I stuck a piece of white paper half an inch square on the end of my nose. Its reflection made perfectly visible the drawing of the part on which I was working. At six o'clock sharp, the appointed time of our meeting, the doorbell rang. I hurriedly put away my copper, Jacques Lacan entered, and we immediately launched into a highly technical discussion. We were surprised to discover that our views were equally opposed and for the same reasons, to the constitutionalist theories then almost universally accepted. We conversed for two hours in a constant dialectical tumult. He left with the promise that we would keep in constant touch with each other and meet periodically. After he had gone I paced up and down my studio, trying to reconstruct the course of our conversation and to weigh more objectively the points on which our rare disagreements might have a real significance. But I grew increasingly puzzled over the rather alarming manner in which the young psychiatrist had scrutinised my face from 140 time to time. It was almost as if the germ of a strange curious smile would then pierce his expression. Was he intensely studying the convulsive effects upon my facial morphology of the ideas that stirred my soul? I found the answer to the enigma when I presently went to wash my hands (this incidentally is the moment when one usually sees every kind of question with the greatest lucidity). But this time it was given to me by my image in the mirror. I had forgotten to remove the square of white paper from the tip of my nose! For two hours I had discussed questions of a transcendental nature in the most precise, objective and grave tone of voice without being aware of the disconcerting adornment on my nose. What cynic could consciously have played this role through to the end? Since the dates supplied by Dali are inaccurate, as are other details such as the title of the article and the name of the journal in which it was published, the time of this meeting between the two men, must be surmised as having taken place sometime after the publication of VAne Pourri in S.A.D.L.R. in 1930 and before the completion of Lacan's thesis in 1932. VAne Pourri, which appeared in the inaugural edition of SA.D.L.R. in July 1930, was Dali's first published contribution to Surrealism. In the strongest possible terms it marked a break with Breton's privileging of phenomena such as automatic writing and dreams as exercises in passive receptivity to 'the voice which it is open to each of us to hear, and which speaks to us in the most singular fashion of something different from what we believe we are thinking'. Since according to its first Manifesto, the term 'Surrealism' was itself synonymous with this suspension of volition in order to cede the initiative to words, Dali's urgent underscoring of the primacy of will in calling forth 'the image of desire behind the simulacra of 141 terror' seems an odd inclusion, although its polemic tone was altogether in keeping with the tenor of the journal. The development of Dali's aesthetic stance corresponds in time with his first meeting with leading Surrealist artists, and also with the beginning of his life-long relationship with Gala, a relationship which he saw as utterly transformational, saving him from a headlong descent into madness. Many of the themes of VAne Pourri were already in evidence in a lecture given to the Athenu Club in Barcelona in March 1930 on 'The Moral Position of Surrealism', where he asserts ‘the rabidly paranoiac determination to systematize confusion1. In this lecture, as in VAne Pourri, which appeared in July 1930, the term ’paranoiaccritical' has not yet been forged. Perusing the article, the reader is immediately struck by the emphasis on force, violence and will in imposing the unstable truth of the image on the viewer. Paranoia offers Dali a signally effective instance of this coercive power. It is the property of paranoiac vision to solder the disparateness of everyday surroundings and events, into coherent dramas which are as irrefutable as they are unlikely: It is enough for a delusional interpretation to bind together the meanings of various pictures hanging on a wall in order for others to be unable to deny the existence of this link. Paranoia uses the outside world to illustrate an obsessive idea, with the disturbing result that this idea is rendered valid for the spectator. That Dali was well aware of the subjective implications of this transfer to the other is obvious from his later commentary; I define the paranoiac-critical method as the art of playing upon all one's own inner contradictions with lucidity by causing others to experience the anxieties and ecstasies of one's life in such a way that it becomes gradually as essential as their own. But I very early realised my life formula; to get 142 others to accept as natural the excesses of one's personality and thus to relieve oneself of his own anxieties by creating a sort of creative participation. As a schoolboy, Dali had hit on an astounding device to free himself from unbearable anxiety. In full view of the pupils and teachers in his school, he would hurl himself from a high roof into the schoolyard, discovering that whatever his injuries might be on landing, ’my own fears disappeared in the anxiety I caused my schoolmates’. This definition of paranoia which leans on the transfer to the other, is entirely in keeping with the insights of classical psychiatry and with Freud's first observations on this topic to Fliess when he underlines his comment that 'the subject matter has remained unchanged; what was changed was something in the placing of the whole thing’. Dali's first article describes paranoiac activity as capable of systematising confusion, and refers to the speed and extreme subtlety of the paranoid process, but it is only after his meeting with Lacan that he attacks the assumption in psychiatry that the systematised delusion is a secondary elaboration, the statue, as de Clerambault used to say, which installs itself on the plinth of a primary disturbance. In the prologue to a proposed essay, ' Paranoiac-Critical Interpretation of the Obsessive Image in Millet's Angelas', published in Minotaure in 1933, which directly follows Lacan's article on Le Problème du Style et la Conception Psychiatrique des Formes Paranoïaques de VExperience', Dali recognised his debt to Lacan. Lacan had demonstrated that the delusion itself is a systématisation, an active element magnetising reality around its field of force. In his thesis, Lacan had emphasised the revelatory character of delusion, the experience of sudden illumination, of things falling into place. 'Cela a fait un richochet dans mon imagination' was Aimée's picturesque phrase in her account of the discovery that her best friend was in fact the persecutor responsible for the plagiarisations which beset and harried her. 143 Like the articles written by Dali on the paranoiac-critical method in 1933 and 1935, Lacan is at pains to establish this as a non-rational mode of perception, while also laying particular emphasis on the importance of this phenomenon as a means of decrying the views of de Clerambault and the purveyors oijblies raisonnantes. His views are however, considerably more conservative than those of Dali and of course denuded of Dali’s violent and vitriolic onslaught on the world of reality. When Lacan opens his major Seminar on Les Psychoses in 1955 by invoking the authority of his 'master' de Clerambault, he nonetheless remains true to this Dalinean insight, distinguishing between de Clerambault's 'parasitic p o in t... around which the subject supposedly constructs something1, and his own affirmation that 'A delusion isn't deduced. It reproduces its same constitutive force. It, too, is an elementary phenomenon'. Further on in the same Seminar, delusion will be defined in an echo of Dali's repeated assertion, as a field that has organised a certain signifier. Lacan identifies delusion as a disturbance in perception, and links it to a whole series of such disturbances directly attributable to psychaesthenia or to the mechanisms of what were known as etats oniroides, the dreamlike or twilight states which figured so prominently in nineteenth century psychopathology: an explanation which Freud had already put seriously in doubt in his paper on fausse reconnaissance in 1913. Dali obviously appreciated the negative thrust of Lacan’s remarks, the blow struck at the establishment. The clarity with which Lacan disengages himself from his predecessors, dismissing the criteria set up by Serieux, Capgras and others as at best approximative, gave Dali free reign to inveigh against a miserably reductionist psychiatry. However insofar as Lacan seeks to enlarge these views in the doctoral thesis, he leans more towards Lombrosian sociology than towards Freudian psychoanalysis. The paranoid-critical method is inseparable from the foregrounding of the double image. From childhood on, Dali had been fascinated by optical illusions and stereoscopic experiments. In L'Ane Pourri, he asserts that the paranoid image is essentially double: 144 It is via a strict paranoiac process that it has been possible to obtain a double image; that is the rperesentation of an object which without the slightest figurative or anatomical modification is at the same time, the representation of another object which also is devoid of the smallest anomaly which might indicate some kind of mutual adjustment. As in the sixteenth and seventeenth century fascination with anamorphic devices, Dali's interest in the double image undercuts the factitious demarcation between illusion and reality which constitutes normal life. Already in 1662, Descartes, whose contribution to dioptrics will be evoked by Lacan in the topological Seminars of the sixties, had asserted; 'A difference exists between reality and our conception of it. This is true not only of art but of life1. Dali's ambition is 'the complete discrediting of the world of reality'. Paranoia effectively achieves this. The doubleness achieved is itself susceptible to triplication or quadruplication, its capacity for ceaseless replication limited only by the individual's facility with respect to paranoid thinking processes. Curiosity about the relation between desire, representation and double inscription, so forcefully posited here by Dali, will fuel many of Lacan's topological demonstrations in the sixties. In the 1932 thesis Lacan tends to assimilate the anomalies of perception specific to paranoia into a sociological discourse, although strongly defending their creative and aesthetic validity. Dali on the contrary, of whom Breton remarked, 'nul plus que lui n'est feru en psychanalyse' goes much further. The connection between psychoanalytic theory and the paranoiac-critical method has been appreciatively remarked on by the feminist critic, Naomi Schor: While many commentators have been tempted to dismiss Dali's psychoanalytic ventures as parodies of scientific discourse, nothing but another clever hoax perpetrated on the public by the master 'cretiniseur', I will argue - by reading Freud after Dali - that Dali's surrealist 'psycho-criticism1 145 ranks as one of those 'misprisions' more perceptive and provocative than many a 'serious1application of Freud. Indeed in a retrospective and megalomanic gesture in 1939, Dali will invoke Freud's reflections on Leonardo da Vinci and a Memory of his Childhood, among other predecessors, as having laid 'the epistemological and philosophical cornerstone of the majestic edifice of imminent paranoiac painting'. From his student days in Madrid, Dali had immersed himself in the works of Freud, and in the 1930's according to Julien Green spoke of him 'like a Christian talks of the New Testament'. Just as Freud, on perhaps very slight evidence, linked Lenoardo's painting to his childhood experience, Dali has no hesitation in linking his own focus on the paranoiac double image, to events surrounding his birth. His several autobiographies recount an early experience of doubleness which he claimed broke in on and disrupted his sense of his own identity. He also described the potentially homicidal consequences of this disturbance on inter-subjective relationships, and the manner in which it organised the force field of representation, thus vividly exemplifying in his own person, a response to the question with which Lacan had ended his doctoral thesis. Lacan had pointed out the relation between a certain psychotic structure and a-subjective aggressivity, and had wondered about the creative representations to which this structure might give rise. In later years, Dali was influenced by a psychoanalyst, Pierre Roumegueres, who subsumed this story of Dali's life into the myth of Castor and Pollux, but this rather inflated gesture is simply a more resonant version of Dali’s personal myth as set forth repeatedly in the autobiographical writings. Truth or fiction, it fuctions as a powerfully coherent narrative, welding the facts, or as Joyce would say, the 'unfacts' of his life to a very particular mode of artistic representation. 146 A utobiographical W ritings The Secret Life of Salvador Dali was published in English in 1942 to a mixed reception. George Orwell described it as 'a striptease act conducted in pink limelight’. The Dallas Texas Herald hailed it as ’a wild jungle of fantasy, posturing, belly-laughs, narcissist and sadist confessions'. It is a first version of a story which will be extended and expanded in several other autobiographical texts, most notably The Unspeakable confessions of Salvador Dali published in 1973. In it he recounts the circumstances of his birth. Researchers who have followed up the connection between Dali and Lacan have been struck by the similarities, no doubt coincidental, between the biographical backdrop to the paranoid crime of Lacan's patient, Aimée, and the autobiographical facts to which Dali assigns the origin of the crises attendant on the earliest experience of his own identity. In these autobiographies, Dali tells of the death of an elder brother, also named Salvador, after their father, three years before his own birth, and describes the impact on him of his parents' massive anxiety following the tragic death of this elder brother: My parents' despair was assuaged only by my own birth ... And within my mother's womb I could already feel their angst. My foetus swam in an infernal placenta. As noted in the previous chapter, Lacan had alluded in his thesis to a tragedy in the family of origin of his patient Aimée, Marguerite Anzieu. According to Lacan's version, while the mother was pregnant with his patient, an older sister, the eldest girl in the family, fell into a fire and was burned alive before her mother’s eyes. This little girl was also called Marguerite, though it would appear from parish records that the accident occurred a year and a half before the birth of the second Marguerite. The mother was probably indeed just pregnant at the time of the accident, and gave birth eight months later to a stillborn child. Lacan's patient was born eleven months after the stillbirth and was therefore the first child to enter the family after the death of the original Marguerite, which had so traumatised the mother. In Dali's case, it would appear that his dating is inaccurate and masks the near instanteneity of the death of the first and the conception of the second Salvador. The first Salvador actually died, aged two and three quarter years, on August 1st 1903, nine months and ten days before the birth of Dali, so it is not impossible that Dali, conceived in the wildness of parental grief, swam, as he put it, in an infernal placenta. In later years he would insist; 'I lived through my death before living my life'. Dali's emphasis is not on the factual event, but on its implications for him and his parents; 'The excess of love lavished on me by my father from the day of my birth was a narcissistic wound, one I had already felt in my mother's womb'. He felt a shadow cast over his own existence by this dead older brother; I deeply experienced the persistence of his presence both as a trauma - a kind of alienation of affections - and a sense of being outdone. All my efforts thereafter were to strain towards winning back my rights to life. Being locked in a death-bearing identification with the other Salvador, he says, allows him no self-presence and no possibility of assuming a narcissistic image. His biographer, Ian Gibson, tellingly entitled his authoritative tome, The Shameful Life of Salvador Dali, and refers repeatedly to Dali's shame-driven personality. Given the far-reaching links between shame and a disturbed narcissistic image, it is regrettable that Gibson does not develop this perceptive insight beyond pointing out that Dali was the only painter in the history of art to depict shame, and to suggest that in 'forcing us to contemplate its sources and its agonies, Dali made one of his most important contributions to civilisation'. Of the impossibility of assuming a narcissistic image, Dali says; 148 I had no corporeal image (my double started by being a dead boy) fate having willed for me to be bom without a body or in an angelic one with images of putrefaction to boot. Having no body he 'burst upon the world' and the first chapter of The Secret Life of Salvador Dali recounts the degree to which his relationships with others was marked by upsurges of homicidal energy. These anecdotic self-portraits describe how more than one childhood companion came perilously close to murderous assault. Some of these attacks seem totally unmotivated, others occur in the context of an unassumable desire. I was five years old ... I was walking in the country with a boy smaller than I who had blond unruly hair, and whom I had known only a short time. I was on foot and he was riding a tricycle. With my hand on his back I helped to push him along. We got to a bridge under construction which had as yet no railings of any kind. Suddenly as most of my ideas occur, I looked behind to make sure no-one was watching us and gave the child a quick shove off the bridge. He landed on rocks fifteen feet below. I ran home to announce the news. Another time, having administered a kick in the head to his sister, he pronounced himself carried away with the delirious joy of this savage act. Such acts of aggression against companions in one-to-one situations took on a compulsive character; Bom double with an extra brother I first had to kill him off in order to assume my own place, my own right to my own desire. 149 In the doctoral thesis, Lacan had emphasised that the murderous attack on the double which had been Aim6e's crime, revealed a subjective structure identical to that found in psychosis. In his 1948 paper on Aggressivity, Lacan cites a small story taken from the writings of St. Augustine as an example of the threat to being, posed by the other; Vidi ego et expertus sum zelatum parvulum: nondum loquebatur et intuebatur pallidus arna.ro aspectu conlactaneum suum 1 I have seen with my own eyes and known very well an infant in the grip of jealousy; he could not yet speak and already he observed his foster-brother, pale and with an envenomed stare. This story will feature frequently in Lacan's teaching, and will be given an expanded and poetic reformulation in the Seminar on Identification where it will be presented as an exemplary moment in the birth of the imaginary, an original version of an essential identificatory redoubling. Before the little child saw his brother at the breast, the breast was simply a part of his ongoingness, part of the rhythms of his being, not something he might or might not have; but this vision of his brother rocks him to the foundations of his existence, at a level which has nothing to do with either need or satisfaction. The mortal pallor of the onlooking child tellingly marks his virtual eclipse as he takes in the fact that he is not there. The other is there. That moment of blinding recognition in which desire appears in the image of its loss is a first and stunning apprehension of oneself as a separate being, but of oneself as not there, a first inscription of identity, perilously poised between being and non-being. The gap opened between oneself and the image of desire is the gap in which subjectivity and the dimension of the temporal must come to be installed. But anomalies exist which make it impossible for the subject to sustain this gap, as psychosis and the murderous or suicidal passage a Vacte demonstrate. Dali, as the above examples show, while yielding to violence, did not succumb to the vertiginous seductions of homicide. He found himself however, drifting inexorably towards the equally vertiginous abyss of madness; 'little by little my entire universe was being coloured by the glints of madness' is his description of his early adulthood. Feeling his world being swallowed by the maw of mad laughter he trawled philosophy for the essential substance which might rescue him. My eagerness to read what I did not understand, stronger than my will, must have obeyed a violent necessity for the spiritual nourishment of my soul and just as a calcium deficiency in children causes them to eat lime and plaster ... so my spirit must have needed the categorical imperative which I chewed and rechewed for two consecutive years without swallowing it. But one day I did swallow it. I who never wept over novels wept on reading a definition of 'identity' by one of these philosophers, I don't remember which. This however was not enough. The destabilisation consequent on 'being bom double' was eventually countered by a different doubling, which is how Dali describes his lifelong relationship with his wife, Gala. Dali's highly coloured accounts of this relationship make it clear that he draws a crucial distinction between two mutually exclusive kinds of psychic doubling, one of which sabotages while the other reinforces identity. In his autobiographies he returns to the topic of his salvation many times, always emphasising certain factors. He speaks of a particular feature, a birthmark on Gala's ear, as providing the essential stabilising function which creates a bulwark against the endless slippage of paranoiac doubleness; 'My entire unconscious found stability around that axis, like a planet around its sun1. Within the maelstrom of madness, Gala created identifiable contours; 151 Out of the most terrible mental malady, my fantastic wandering, my paranoiac vision, my deliriousness, she made a classical order. She de-limited - I might say Dalimit-ed my delirium. Attempts to circumscribe the contours of this transmutation were to become a central feature of Lacan's teaching, from the Seminar on Desire and its Interpretation in 1958-1959 onwards. In recounting the inaugral moment of their lifelong relationship, Dali declares: 'Gala drove the forces of death out of me, and first and foremost the obsessive sign of Salvador my dead elder brother'. This was no metaphor. At the moment when the closeness of their relationship became explicit, Dali, prey to homicidal impulses, became locked in the impossibility of distinguishing between Gala as his fantasised double and Gala the real person. For me the great problem of madness and lucidity was that of the limits between the Galuschka of my false memories, who had become chimerical and dead a hundred times through my subconscious pulsions and my desire for utter solitude, and the real Gala whose corporeality it was impossible for me to resolve in the pathological alienation of my spirit. I was 'fighting’ this central problem of my life, this bull of my desire, who I knew, would at a given moment be there immobile and menacing a few centimetres from my own immobility, confronting me with the sole and only choice: either to kill him or be killed by him. It was Gala's desire, apparently the mirror image of his own, and yet distinct and indisputably other, which released Dali from this impasse. Dali gives two slightly different accounts of this event. According to the 1942 version, Gala declared; 'I want you to kill me', and Dali, astonished 152 and disappointed at having his own secret offered to him, instead of the ardent erotic proposal he had expected, suddenly recognised that she too had an inner world of desires and frustrations, and moved within a rhythm of her own 'between the poles of lucidity and madness1. This recognition of Gala's otherness transmitted in the words of his own homicidal urge effects an extraordinary change in Dali, a transmutation which in 1942, he can only convey by means of an allegorical tale inserted into the autobiographical text. The Figurine with the Sugar Nose tells the story of a necrophilic king, who periodically chose a beautiful girl with whom to spend a night of unfulfilled love. The king would lie beside the girl looking at her, and at daybreak would draw his sword and cut off her head. Finally a girl, wilier than the others, substituted a wax model for herself, to which she had appended a sugar nose. When the king beheaded this figure, the sugar nose broke off and flew into his mouth. Surprised by the sudden sweetness the king cries out in regret whereupon the girl who had been listening came forth, and the king is 'suddenly and miraculously cured of his criminal aberration1, marries the girl and lives happily ever after. In his interpretation of this allegory, Dali emphasises the substitutive operation which had effected the cure, pointing out the incongruous inadequate aspect of the small object which violently and suddenly transmitted the sweetness which could serve as a bridge to desire 'enabling it to pass from death to life'. This real sweetness 'was that which by surprise happened to occupy the expected place which the fictive sweetness of death was to occupy’. Dali's allegory attempts a heavy handed and clumsy account of a process which Lacan in the Sixties describes as a crucial but unlocatable moment in the becoming of the subject. In the Seminar on Desire and its Interpretation, he highlights the passionate self-destruction betrayed in the pallor of the onlooking child, and sees the first self image, the image of the other as a first substitute for this subject 'in his destructive passion'. A transmutation must occur which establishes the subject as a subject of desire, or at least permits the possibility of this position. This moment bears an essential relation to the Mirror stage, but is of a different, a more crucial order. The several topological surfaces which dominate Lacan's teaching from 1961 onwards attempt to encompass the transmutation which must occur between something in the demand of the Other which will eventually constitute the desire of the subject, and conversely something in the desire of the Other which will have an essential bearing on the demand of the subject. This transmutation, based on an essential asymmetry between demand and desire, is variously described by Lacan as the panic point, the whirlwind point. Punningly it is the point d'Orage’, topologically it is the circle of retrogression, the reversion point of the Moebius strip which functions, he says, as the model for what is in question at this crucial moment in the identificatory process. Lacan frequently stresses the epistemological difficulties of giving an adequate description of this process: ... we have simply to think about this circular antipodal relationship as a sort of radiating intercrossing, as one might say, concentrating the exchange of one point with the opposite point of the single edge of this hole, and in concentrating it, as one might say, around a vast central interlacing which escapes our thinking and which does not allow us in any way therefore to give a satisfactory ■representation of it. Dali's two accounts of Gala's role in his emergence from madness put the accent on the factor of transmutation. In his second autobiography, he declares; My cruelty, my ferocity, my desire to humiliate and to soil were being transformed like a laser beam in the diamond prism of Gala's heart and intelligence. This transmutation allows him to become himself via a narcissistic doubling which is life-bearing and no longer death-bearing as in his earlier identification with the dead brother. From that moment on I was cured of my haunting obsessions, my laughter, my hysterics ... Gala became the salt of my life, the steel of my personality, my beacon, my double-ME ... I felt myself a man, freed from my terror and my impotence. By her I was henceforth gifted with telluric vertical forces such as allow a man to penetrate a woman ... I did not go mad because she took over my madness. The allegorical tale in 1942 had emphasised the mediating role of the 'paradoxical inadequate object1, the sugar nose which was the bridge to desire. Lacan in his teaching insists on the function of an object, designated 'object cause of desire', as the indispensable turning point in this identification where the subject is constituted as desiring. The crucial transmutation between the pre-subjective being and the Other in which desire is bom, is mediated by this object; 'it is starting from the problematic of the beyond of the demand that the object is constituted as object of desire’. This object will be an object in which the subject will find 'the very virtues of his initial demand’. In 1942 Dali was unable to give an account of this process except by way of allegory. In his second autobiography, the object which allows him to exist is situated on Gala's body, and has become a beauty spot on her left earlobe. This mark provides definitive proof of the death of the other Salvador, ridding him of craziness and granting him access to lucid existence; 'My entire unconscious found stability around that axis, like a planet around its sun1. That this 'cure' is less complete than Dali's narrative suggests is clear from other passages in these writings notably in The Secret Life where a number of recurrent bouts of nearmadness are described. Throughout his autobiographical writings, Dali insists on the correlation between biographical fact and aesthetic theory. Gazing at the 155 moisture stains on the ceiling as a child at school, he trained his vision to see difference in the same, or alternatively sameness in difference. His relationship with Gala, crystallised around the distinguishing birthmark, provides an essential stabilisation, and functions as a bulwark against the endless slippages of paranoiac doubleness. This relationship, however, is not something which tips Dali from madness into sanity, but rather something which allows him a foothold on the boundary line from where his creativity can function; 'In becoming exorcised through the strength of Gala and her love I found pathways to the method of truth’. He describes this method; The secret lies in lucidly keeping a steady course between the waves of madness and the straight lines of logic. Genius consists in being able to live while going constantly from one frontier to the other. This steady course is pursued not with calm security but with unflinching vigilance. Identity for Dali is, he says, a moment by moment achievement, portrayed as occurring picture by picture; 'from picture to picture ... my bodily image was little by little restructured beginning with Gala'. ... but also urgently ongoing, and carved by his will out of the horrors hidden in time; My whole being is a field of work that I unify through my will. If for one second this wave of force stops Dali no longer exists ... Were I drop vigilance for one second I might be taken unawares by a nightmare monster. His is an aesthetics inclusive of the ’irreducible share of paranoia', from which his genius derives. Both the papers on art theory and the autobiographical writings emphasise equally the centrality of paranoia and the critical lucidity which enables him to forge this paranoia into creative expression; I channelled my delirium through reason, as in art I found my expression through classicism. I turn my contradictions into a veritable coherence. I can truly say that I do not know when I begin simulating or when I tell the truth, but I do know where and when delirium ends. Through the pitiless demand of cold intelligence, I transformed part of my personality into an analytical faculty and won back from madness a domain that I turned into power and creation. The difference - need I repeat - between a madman and me is that I am not mad. Dali's autobiographies sketch a bizarre, indeed almost a baroque portrait of what clinical terminology would call the familial anomaly constituted by the doubling of identity, attendant on the circumstances of his birth. He gives numerous examples of the manner in which this anomaly resulted in his growing up without a corporeal image, but rather inhabiting a subjective structure where the risk of homicidal violence overshadowed every opening onto the emergence of desire. This structure was eventually modified by the relationship with Gala which provided a foothold not on the safe shores of sanity but on the boundary which made him master of his genius while retaining access to 'delirium'. These autobiographical accounts explicitly aim to outline the biographical underpinning of the mode of representation dubbed ’the paranoiac-critical method'. Lacan had ended his thesis in 1932 with a call for further exploration via his own method of 'concrete psychological analysis' of the types of lived experience, in particular the anomalies in family life, which can give rise to psychosis, along with the 'pre-logical conceptual structures' issuing in the aesthetic creations specific to psychotic states, and the link between psychosis and certain homicidal 'unmotivated' crimes. 157 Within ten years Dali had published a vivid, concrete, idiosyncratic and probably half-fictional exploration of the manner in which these three factors can intersect to form the weave from which he created both a personal identity and a body of great art. Not only can these autobiographical writings be fruitfully linked to Lacan's thesis, Dali's narratives, accentuating as they do, a necessary transmutation between the subject and the other in the constitution of identity, a transmutation mediated by an object specified by Dali as that which functions as the bridge to desire, appear to anticipate or at least to have much in common with Lacan's theorisations of the becoming of the subject, as elaborated via the topological surfaces of the Moebius strip, the cross-cap, or the Klein bottle throughout the Sixties. Indeed one commentator has suggested that Dali's work represents a kind of pre-Lacanian Lacanianism. In 1936, the year in which Lacan first presented his theory of the Mirror stage, Dali wrote a poem entitled The Metamorphosis of Narcissus and painted a canvas of the same name. (He took this painting to his meeting with Freud in 1938). Dali's own commentary is illuminating; If one looks at the hypnotic motionless form of Narcissus for a while from a little distance and with a certain 'distracted fixedness' it slowly vanishes and finally becomes invisible. Exactly in this moment the metamorphosis of the myth takes place, because the appearance of Narcissus suddenly is transformed into the appearance of a hand, which emerges from its own mirror image. This hand carries in its fingertips an egg ... from which the new narcissus is formed - the flower. Next to it one can see the plaster-sculpture of a hand, the hand of the water turned to stone, which holds the ... flower. One must, of course, suspect the retrospective look, since it is imbued with its own anamorphic biases, but from the vantage-point of the Nineties, this commentary by Dali, with its focus on the metamorphosis which occurs 158 precisely at the moment of fading appears closer to Lacan's later work than to the Lacan of the Thirties. Address fo r correspondence: APPI School o f Psychotherapy S t Vincent's Hospital Elm Park Dublin 4 We who are addicted to books will have a mental list of those teachers along the way who opened doors onto new intellectual directions. There are five on my list, the most recent one being Cormac. For fourteen years Cormac has been an extraordinarily inspiring teacher in the School for Psychotherapy at S t Vincent's Hospital. Week by week, he is there, forging intelligent, articulate and accessible inroads into Lacanian texts, which for each batch of newcomers appear at first glance to be altogether impenetrable. To be able to teach well, one must be oneself stirred and challenged by the text or the topic in hand and this is why Cormac's lectures are always interesting. His engagement with Freud and Lacan is not static; year by year he pushes out the boundaries, and engages his students in the questions which currently preoccupy him. It is always fun to watch a new class, and to see the intellectual ferment begin to happen. The enormous esteem in which he is held was rather touchingly conveyed to me a couple of years ago when a student, praising my lectures, surmised that I must knoiv 'nearly as much as CormacPraise Indeed! Having trained psychoanalytically in the School for Psychotherapy, most of us put a lot of thought and effort into understanding and maintaining the analytic position. For this reason we don't often speak of personal warmth. In wishing Cormac a happy 60th birthday I would like to pay tribute to this quality in him. In the terible days following the diagnosis of Dick's fatal illness, and the devastation following his death, Cormac, like so many friends and 159 colleagues, wrote warm letters of support and sympathy which greatly counted at the time; small lights in a world of darkness. I wish him a wonderful birthday; and may the coming years be long, happy and even perhaps sometimes restful UNE TORPEUR ORDINAIRE Christiane Lacôte Le jeune homme partit pour l'étranger. C'était une demi-solution et il le savait un peu, puisque l'étranger n'est que la figure compacte de ce que Lacan désigne de son incomplétude même, le grand Autre. Mais cette figure dégradée de l'Autre était aussi pleine que l'objet que sa jouissance consommait et cette symétrie n'était pas encore rompue. * * * * * Aujourd'hui, dans nos contrées, la souffrance n'est plus de mise. Tant mieux, en un sens. Il est admis qu'elle n'est plus rédemptrice et qu'un monde meilleur ne nous attend plus en récompense de nos peines. La souffrance ne se tisse plus avec une espérance religieuse, elle est un mal radicalement. Cela n'exclut pas qu'elle puisse être un spectacle, télévisé le plus souvent, 'en direct7, dit-on. Mais le spectacle ne vient pas de la fenêtre ou de la porte: seul l'horizon est vu de l'immeuble géant II vient de cette fausse proximité que procure l'écran de télévision; l'actualité est filtrée par le montage de ses images. Qu'arrive-t-il alors quand le fait-divers fait irruption réellement dans le cercle familial? * * * * * Nous condenserons dans ce récit fictif plusieurs cas de clinique ordinaire aujourd'hui. Un samedi, un jeune homme sort de cette discothèque où il a dansé comme les autres, aussi seul que les autres, abruti de musique assourdissante plus que d'alcool. Il frime dans la voiture paternelle, roule à trop vive allure et tue plusieurs de ses amis qui étaient avec lui. Lui161 même, seul survivant, a quelques contusions et fractures. Il arrive alors à un dispensaire, abruti d'anxiolytiques. Il se plaint à peine et récite la leçon apprise: 'Je ne suis pas coupable'. Ses parents, et quelques parents des enfants morts dans cet accident, installent autour de lui un 'nursing' incessant: 'il ne faut pas qu’il souffre car il risquerait de se suicider'. Le tableau pervers est en place: à un tel choc, à un tel trauma, on ne peut résister. On le réconforte, on le drogue, on lui raconte qu'il n'est pas coupable, car - insiste-t-on - s'il se rendait compte de ce qu'il a fait, il irait droit à la mort. L'alternative terrible est posée, pas d'échappatoire. On entend derrière ce 'nursing:' bienveillant, la vengeance implacable qui ne laisse aucun choix: ou bien le sujet est exclu par les drogues anxiolytiques/ ou bien il l’est par la mort. D'ailleurs, il suffit de prendre un peu plus de ces comprimés anesthésiants pour aller d'un terme à l'autre. Et si le jeune homme meurt, ce ne sera que d’une over dose pour quelque chose, qui de toutes manières, était trop 'over'. Le psychanalyste a peu de marge, non pas pour écouter mais pour intervenir dans une problématique bien ordinaire aujourd'hui: Ü ne faut pas que le jeune homme souffre et subjective sa douleur et le deuil de ses amis, il ne faut pas qu'il se sente coupable car ce serait immédiatement trop et il serait emporté par ce 'trop'. Le psychanalyste qui dans sa pratique même ne peut que solliciter la responsabilité du sujet, que faire entrevoir des plaisirs mal assurés tels que les aléas des rencontres entre homme et femme les procurent heurte tout le monde qui est sûr de sa 'défonce'. Les jouissances toutes faites et sûres, de la musique assourdissante, du moteur lancé à fond, de l'alcool, de la drogue ont une emprise puissante. Les parents qui ont laissé faire continuent dans la même dérive, ils continuent la 'défonce': ils maîtrisent l’anesthésie, enroulent l’adolescent dans les bandelettes d'une compréhension totale, éternisent la momification car, dans le fond, ils ne lui donnent pas d'autre choix que de payer de sa vie. Nulle tentative pour le réveiller et l'aider à élaborer sa responsabilité et son deuil. Nulle tentative pour que le temps s'élabore autrement à partir de cet événement irréversible. Au contraire, les parents eux-mêmes, abrutis de chagrin et de calmants installeront les dispositifs d'une vengeance sans frein sur 162 l'adolescent coupable: ils le transformeront en son propre fantôme dans l’endurance éternisée de ce qui est immobilisé dans ce cataclysme. On a désigné là une forme de l'enfer car si l'expiation est étemelle, il n'y a plus ni culpabilité, ni punition, on passe à un autre niveau, celui de la désubjectivation. Cette vengeance n'obéit pas au vieil adage 'oeil pour oeil, dent pour dent' où entrait parfois un certain sens de l'honneur. Dans cette torpeur de clinique ordinaire il ne peut être question d'honneur. Rien, dans l'entourage parental ou amical ne propose au jeune adolescent quelque geste ou parole par lesquels il y aurait un échange au mal qu'il a fait. Certes, ü n‘y a pas d'échange possible à la perte de la vie. Mais tout geste d'échange doit-il être annulé dès lors qu'il ne peut pas être égal? La balance doit-elle être la règle? Qu'il y ait une faille, un déséquilibre, un hiatus, cela pourrait être au contraire l'occasion de rompre avec les idéaux mortels de la totalisation, d'amorcer une prise de conscience de la division subjective. Mais, dans l'organisation ordinaire de la torpeur, il s'agit souvent, aujourd'hui, d'empêcher le travail du deuil. Or le deuil, ce n'est pas se consoler d'une perte, mais savoir que cette perte peut signifier que l'on n'a pas la maîtrise de la jouissance. Sans, pour autant renvoyer à l'idée antique du destin. Ce peut-être l'occasion de remarquer la différence entre la jouissance toxicomaniaque, assurée par un produit chimique, assurée aussi de son terme ultime, la mort, et la jouissance sexuelle qui n'est jamais promise dans ce qui réunit et sépare un homme et une femme. L'aléa de la jouissance sexuelle, c'était justement ce qui devait être rendu impossible, selon la vengeance doucereuse dont était victime le jeune homme. Cette vengeance faisait tourner en rond corps, mort et jouissance et la mort n'était pas autre chose que la seule limite possible à une jouissance sans frein. J. Lacan, dans son séminaire R.S.I., met en oeuvre une autre tirade que ce tournage en rond du corps, de la mort et de la jouissance par lequel il rend compte, avec exactitude, de certains aspects du symptôme contemporain. 163 Comment déjouer le piège de la torpeur? Comment faire entendre qu'il peut y avoir un courage du désir à poser d'autres limites à la jouissance que celles de la mort? Address for correspondence: 7, bd du Temple 75003 Paris France 164 WE CAN REMEMBER IT FOR YOU WHOLESALE Helena Texier (When to the sessions of sweet silent thought I summon up remembrance of things past,...) 'What is human?' and 'What is reality?'. It would seem, in the recent, albeit short-lived, furore caused in the field of psychiatry on their 'discovery' of 'false memories' in the course of talking cures, specifically in relation to sexual abuse, that these two questions seem to be causing that field some anxiety. I've elsewhere said that it is regrettable that psychiatry on this matter seems to lag behind psychoanalysis by more than one hundred years.1 But more regrettable still is the implication from some quarters of the establishment, generally the most vocal, that this 'discovery* should be read as proof of the inherent danger of talking cures, as if the only adequate response to the new-found knowledge of the human subject is, precisely, to reinforce the science by firmly (fore)closing the door in its face. The perceived 'danger' of the 'talking cure' appears to follow, as far as I can gather, from two points; firstly, in that there is no measurable, empirical basis on which to make a judgement with regard to the status, the 'reality', of anything that is produced as memory; secondly, that the psychiatrist risks leaving himself open to being implicated in the production of such 'false memories' (for example, that his method involves suggestion, an 'implantation' of memory) and therefore open to the possibility of being sued by someone falsely accused of abuse or, indeed by a patient, traumatised by memories, by-products of therapy which would not have arisen were it not for the treatment. Ostensibly then, although there is mention of the trauma 1 c.f. Editorial, THE LETTER, issue 12, Spring, 1998. 165 caused to the patient or those falsely accused, the 'danger' is really one posed for the psychiatrist; firstly, in that the very ground of his field, the reliance on empirical method, finds itself challenged by a speaking subject; secondly, insofar as there is a risk to his bank-balance, reputation, etc. Best to leave well enough alone. Most interesting perhaps, although no mention of it is made, is this precariousness of the position in which that field of knowledge is placed in virtue of its new-found knowledge. It would seem that the emerging spectre of the 'false memory' in the field of psychiatry casts a threatening shadow over the previous unproblematic universe of certainties in which the enigmatic existence of the unconscious has no place. One would be forgiven for comparing this moment to another, one which is integral to the coming into being of subjectivity itself, the introduction of uncertainty, a 'not-knowing1casting the shadow of doubt over the certainties of the past. It is hardly necessary to remind you that this moment on the threshold of subjectivity concerns the child's discovery of castration which, in a similar fashion, punctures a hole in the previously 'whole' universe, the new-found knowledge having as a logical consequence the insinuation of a lack in the knowledge of an earlier time. Furthermore, this discovery has another effect, one in which a desiring subject finds itself implied and therefore implicated: if I stumble upon the truth then wasn't it because without knowing it I was looking for it. Here the epistemological drive is seen to have been predicated on a lack in knowledge. Now for the real discovery, - one is not master in one's own home. It is precisely the subjective stance taken in relation to this 'notknowing' which, as is the case for any subject-to-be, will determine the structure of and, therefore, the possibilities for any body of knowledge following from it. If evidence in support of this were needed, one would only have to turn to a germinal moment in the history of psychoanalysis. Consider the effects of the different approaches taken by Breuer and Freud in relation to the discourse of Anna O. Breuer, the master, certain of himself, listened only long enough to hear himself implicated in her productions ('agalma-mated' into her discourse, one might say). Abruptly 166 finding himself on uncertain territory, confused, horrified and with a reputation to consider, he took to his heels. Freud on the other hand, while he is often criticised for his adoption of this master position, continued to listen, to discover the transference and out of it to invent the analytic position. It would seem then that psychiatry's rather belated attention to the 'false memory' leaves it on the same cusp of a subjectivity which it has previously eschewed, now finding itself poised at the point where it will either flee from the implication of its new knowledge or become interested in the possibilities it may be afforded by it. It remains to be seen whether the answer will aim at reinforcing the possibility of a completitude of knowledge inherent to the perverse solution; now we know that we didn't know, but all the same we'll carry on as if we didn't know it; a solution which Lacan recasts as a disjunction between knowledge and truth, knowledge deluding itself with respect to the truth which drives it. In fact the shattering of 'past certainties' by 'uncertainties about the past' returns us neatly to the topic of memory itself. The question imposes itself of whether there is not something taken all too easily for granted, and covertly so, in this expression 'false memory'. Is there not already silently implied here as unproblematic its corollary, - 'true memory'? The problematic nature of this latter concept and its relation to the obviously troublesome former one for the Science Faction is curiously underlined by a work from the field of Science Fiction, the author of which was, coincidentally, plagued throughout his life by the two questions which rear up in the face of psychiatry and with which we opened: 'What is human?' and 'What is reality?'. These two not unrelated questions dominated both the life and work of the science fiction writer, Philip K Dick, prompting more than forty novels and two hundred short stories, and incidentally probably also lying at the heart of his thirteen marriages, his various episodes of rampant paranoia and his complete breakdown at the point at which his writing failed him, culminating in his Exegisis, the account of his ’divine invasion', which by all accounts would prove a worthy equal to Schreber's Diary. Readers unfamiliar with either his life or that genre of literature are 167 probably more familiar with the cinematic versions of his work, most notably with Ridley Scott's cult-status Bladerunner, a masterful rendition of his novel Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep?, and with Total Recall, Paul Verhoeven's box-office hit, a version of Philip K Dick's short story We can remember it for you Wholesale. What is remarkable about the works of Dick is that working comfortably in a genre which is often considered 'low' literature he manages to transform it into a kind of Ur-literature of the human predicament, eminently psychological, often theological, undoubtedly philosophical, infinitely real and perpetually surfing the borders of subjectivity. His stories in this respect, even if by his own admission they are not at all beautiful, have more in common with the dark worlds of E. T. Hoffman or E. A. Poe than with the sci-fi universe of the Starship Enterprise- Ingenious plots, generously laced with the blackest of humour and played out in a world which admits of futuristic and fantastic possibilities, seduce the reader into suspending his judgement of what can be admitted as constituting reality, while the subjective underpinnings of the works mean that these ’alternative1worlds eventually end up bearing uncanny resemblance to the most intimate nooks and crannies of our own. Dick's books are remarkable in that the notion of memory as constitutive of human reality is used alternately, initially, to establish reality and, subsequently, to undermine it, seducing the reader into a solid plot which always turns out to be a red herring, steadily chipping away at space and time until reality disintegrates. To this end he employs the devices of 'false memory implants' and of 'simulacra1, the use of the idea of androids, resembling humans in all respects save the contents of their minds. Bladerunner employs both. In this story the hero, Deckard, has lost his humanity living an anaesthetised existence in a virtually dead world. The backdrop to the scenario is a futuristic soulless time in which almost nothing 'natural' exists. One can never be sure of the essence of the object, animate or inanimate, of whether it is 'real' or an engineered replica of some 'original' thing. Deckard is a bounty hunter, engaged to track down and destroy escaped androids, replicants, on the loose and looking for their Maker - literally. 168 The scientific technique for determining the 'false' or 'true' nature of a suspect involves posing him a series of questions the response to which will reveal him as an authentic subject or not. (A kind of futuristic DSM). The method is stretched to its very limit when he comes up against a replicant who does not know she is not human and this on the basis of the fact that she has a whole host of memories stretching all the way back to childhood and including those persistent scenarios emulating Freud's screen memories, intimating important, barely accessible, subjective turning points. All of these have been implanted by her Maker. Already here we have a literary figuration of the relation of the memory of the subject to the desire of the Other; recalled subjective turning points have everything to do with the encroachment of this Other. This in itself would prove a useful point of departure for a consideration of the circumstances in which memory can be 'implanted'. In another work, the short story We Can Remember It For You Wholesale, this theme of memory and the possibility of its implantation is taken up again. Interestingly, the work opens with a moment on the border between sleep and awakening, a dream, onto which the scenario which follows is hung. He awoke - and wanted Mars. The valleys, he thought. What would it be like to trudge amongst them? Great and greater yet: the dream grew as he became fully conscious, the dream and the yearning. ... I will go, he said to himself. Before I die I'll see Mars. This overture onto the field of the dream, the yearning, leads us abruptly via the hero, Douglas Quail, onto the field of memory. In this future time Quail, not having the financial resources to really make the trip to Mars, decides to avail of the services of the Rekal Corporation which, (presumably having followed to their logical conclusion the commercial possibilities of the false memory syndrome), specialises in what are called 'extra-factual' memory implants. They will ensure that for a fraction of the cost of the real journey to Mars that he will 'remember' it just as if he had gone. They 169 will incorporate his request to have been to Mars as an Interplan agent, sent there on a dangerous and highly secret mission and, in addition, they will furnish tangible proof of his journey which they will plant on his person and in his apartment so that reality will furnish him support for his remembered ’trip’. Phantasy and reality will be inmixed in such a way as to be indistinguishable. Furthermore, this trip will in fact be better than the real thing: Had you really gone to Mars as an Interplan agent, you would by now have forgotten a great deal; our analysis of true-mem systems - authentic recollections of major events in a person's life - shows us that a variety of details are very quickly lost to the person forever. Part of the package we offer you is such deep implantation of recall that nothing is forgotten. Convinced by the sales talk, Quail parts with his money, and proceeds to the implantation room where he receives a preparatory injection which renders him unconscious, returning him to that time between wakening and sleep with which the story begins. And this is the point where the proposed scientific procedure fails before it has begun. Before the implantation and quite spontaneously, the unconscious Quail begins to speak in his sleep and it becomes apparent that he is already recalling his trip to Mars. Lowe the technician reports; 'He wants a false memory implant that corresponds to a trip he actually took. And a false reason which is the real reason1. He wants to recall consciously what must be an unconscious memory which some government agency has tried to erase. Going to Mars meant something special to him, and so did being a secret agent. They couldn't erase that; it's not a memory but a desire, undoubtedly the same one that motivated him to volunteer for the assignment in the first place. 170 The technical team, unlucky enough to have uncovered 'a genuine Interplan agent with a cover so perfect not even he himself knew what he was, or rather is1, are caught in a dilemma posed by the infiltration of desire into the field of memory, expressed in these terms by one of their number; What do we do? Graft a false-memory pattern over the real memory? ... He'd have to hold two quite opposite premises in his mind simultaneously: that he went to Mars and that he did not. That he's a genuine agent for interplan and he's not. Having successfully introduced the sort of confusion which a blurring of the boundaries between phantasy and reality by infection with desire effects, the author takes us further and further into it. Having recalled his trip, the government agency pursues the errant agent to kill him. Quail convinces them that it should be possible to resolve the situation amicably. (Afterall he's been of great service to them and surely they owe him something). He proposes that the memory be obliterated by replacing it with the 'memory' of a more powerful scenario. 'Suppose once my authentic memories have been cancelled, something more vital than standard memories are implanted. Something which would act to satisfy my cravings'. The psychiatrist engaged to identify a suitable replacement memory finds something. 'Mr Quail,' the stern-faced, elderly Interplan psychiatrist said, 'you possess a most interesting wish-fulfilment fantasy. Probably nothing such as you consciously entertain or suppose. This is commonly the way; I hope it won't upset you too much to hear about it. ... This production is a grotesque dream of your childhood; it is no wonder you fail to recall it'. In this wish-fulfilment he single-handedly prevents the invasion of the Earth by an alien star system. The invaders are so impressed by the depth 171 of his kindness that they spare Earth for as long as he is alive. So by merely existing he keeps the Earth safe from alien rule. In keeping with the grandeur of childhood, he's the most important person in the world! Once the Mars memories have been erased and this over-riding childhood wish has been incorporated into the memory implant, he'll believe it really happened. Mars-memories erased, Quail is now lying in the laboratory of the Rekal Corporation. Once more, in preparation for the implantation, he receives an injection which renders him unconscious, returning him again to that time between wakening and sleep with which the story begins. And this is the point where the proposed scientific procedure fails as it had before. (You've probably already guessed!). Before the implantation and quite spontaneously, the unconscious Quail begins to speak in his sleep and it becomes apparent that he is recalling the alien invasion of Earth and how he so impressed the invaders by his kindness that his very existence guarantees the salvation of the planet. 'They told me not to tell', Douglas Quail mumbled in a dull drug-saturated voice. 'That was the agreement. I wasn't even supposed to remember. But how could I forget an event like that?'. In a humorous twist, Quail announces that he has tangible proof of the reality of his memories of the invasion; the Aliens have given him something, - a magic destroying rod which, incidentally, he used to execute his mission on Mars. (Yes, he still has total recall of that). And this magic destroying rod, incontrovertible evidence of the objective reality of his memory of the past, well, - it's invisible! Moreover, and if your head is not already spinning at the acrobatic loops that Dick has taken you through, it is not clear that the whole story is not just the product of that time suspended between sleep and awakening, hanging on the dream, manifesting itself through the mouth of the sleep-talking Quail, with which the story began and to which, through loops of fancy, it constantly returns. 172 So in this field of uncertainty at the dawning, or better, the yawning of the subject, what are we left with? Certainly with a subject whose existence is secured because it has the Big Other over a barrel. In addition, and as if this were not enough, we have a story whose ingenious plot manages to pay more tribute to the level of complexity required for any satisfactory theory of memory than many scientific attempts have managed. Here we are presented with a world in which the memory available to consciousness is dependent on the desire of the Other which, nonetheless, cannot erase it once it has been written; a universe which bears witness to the incompatibility of the desire of the Other with the desire of the subject and, paradoxically, the reliance of the one on the other. (The aims of the government agency, Interplan, its secret mission, are dependent on the desire of Quail to volunteer for it). The 'false memory', the implantation of a recollection, is pursued alternately, out of the desire of the subject (Quail wants to remember something for the pleasure of it; wants to remember something else because his existence comes to depend on it) and out of the desire of the Other (The Other, the Rekal Corporation, gains financially out of it; the Other, Interplan, wants him to remember something so as not to remember something else). Forgetting too is permeated by compromises between conflicting agencies; Quail can't remember the trip to Mars because the government agency would rather he didn't and because remembering would prove fatal to him, can't remember the invasion because the Aliens told him not to and because he partly wants to comply with this, since the Aliens (radically Other) have guaranteed him his existence. Added to this is the further complication pointed up by the dilemma of the technician Lowe, who can be viewed here as the a-subject of the scientific field, carrying out procedures to the letter until these grind to a halt when confronted with the speaking subject, who conjures up for him the paradox of holding as equally true a premise (I am a secret Interplan agent) and its contrary (I am not a secret Interplan agent). In addition, with the unfolding of the story in the 'looping' of memories, we witness the later story of an early story (the childhood phantasy) making its way into the text of the earlier 173 story of a later story (the adult adventure), each loop changing the context of the past and altering the potential outcome of the subject's future. None of this was unfamiliar to Freud. From the outset and even before his invention of the psychoanalytic method, - (evidently the backward looping of memory is as much a part of the story of psychoanalysis as it is for any other subject!) - Freud's project would give a systematic account of the workings of the mnemic system which leaves little room for the ascription of any truth value to the inscriptions of the impressions of existence, those mnemic traces, which could be seen to issue from any direct correlation to reality. For Freud then, even in his earliest attempts at giving an account of memory, there is no question of any resemblance between the memory trace and the 'real1 cause of the impression. Indeed reality itself, or at least the notion of any objective or de-subjectivised reality, is, in the process, radically undermined. In the reworking of his Project for a Scientific Psychology in the light of Die Traumdeutung we see in chapter VII of the latter work, which can be considered the summit towards which the whole work climbs, that from the first it appears that that very turning toward reality is itself driven, even in the vestigial subject, by the search for that hallucinated object which Freud posits as prototypical wishfulfilment So the turning towards reality is an intentionalised one set in motion by the search for a 'something' which would correspond to the mnemic trace of the hallucinated object, - and all of the thought activity 'which is spun out from the mnemic image to the moment at which the perceptual identity is established by the external world ... merely constitutes a roundabout path to wishfulfilment'. So thought activity itself is set in motion, intentionalised, by desire. At this point it would be worthwhile taking a cursory backwards glance at the aforementioned last chapter. You will recall the scenario which Freud describes in the section on wishfulfilment in which the hungry baby, unable to escape the tension caused by his need for food, falls back upon the memory of the experience of satisfaction, temporarily assuaging his yearning by calling up, hallucinating, the perception of the satisfying object. The need persisting nonetheless, the subsequent turning towards a 'somewhere else', aims at establishing a 'perceptual identity' not with any real object but with this object as remembered. So at one and the same time it is the success of and the failure of the hallucination that sets an intentionalised train in motion. This scene, encapsulating the relation of the subject to desire in an admittedly embryonic form, really is a crucial one for the understanding of Freud's conception of what is human. Previous to this moment here staged, Freud has described the psychical apparatus as working on the basis of a reflex arc, a well functioning machine operating automatically so as to evacuate all exciting innervations of their energy, as efficiently as possible, in order to return the level of energy in the system as a whole to the lowest possible. If we can speak of intentionalisation of the apparatus here then it is only in the sense that it automatically functions toward a given end. Stimulus engenders response. Matters become more complicated however when a spanner lodges itself firmly in the works. There appears a source of excitement emanating from the machine itself which, moreover, it cannot rid itself of. And it this which opens the door for the human onto the field of desire; in this case of the inchoate subject, the hungry baby, moving him to 'real-ise' his 'dream1. From an initial basis in need there is something demanded from reality the cause of which is, in however rudimentary a form, a desire. Here we have a very different form of intentionalisation. The machine starts to operate off its own bat and not because it is smoothly working but because, precisely, the something that isn't working at all well functions as a kind of motivator, an internal powersource, (which perhaps gives an additional meaning to Lacan's 'battery of signifiers'). It's very much like the joke about the little boy Freddie whose parents become increasingly worried when one year follows the next without his beginning to speak or show any interest in anything. One day they are sitting down to another sad and silent meal when suddenly Freddie asks his father to pass him the salt. Through tears of joy his parents ask him why he hasn't spoken up till now. 'Why Mother!' the boy says, 'You always put in exactly the right amount of salt before1. Of course, this very rudimentary prototype of a desiring subject conveyed by 175 the account of the hungry baby or the saltless Freddie is not the whole story, but it does introduce us to a general trend in Freud's thinking whereby the biological or functional is ultimately superseded by something which, although anaclitic on this, proves to have infinitely more significance for human existence. Secondly, there is also implied another notion that reverberates throughout his work; that the ' thing that does not work' constitutes the driving force of the subject, even to the point where the not-working-thing must be preserved irrespective of the consequences. Quite paradoxically, it will prove to be that which will work tirelessly, (sometimes, it quite literally works the subject to death), what Freud calls variously the ideal worker, the entrepreneur, the Capitalist, - the Unconscious. The very heart of The Interpretation of Dreams, this interrogation of reality (reality put to the test as opposed to 'reality testing') by desire, achieves a new articulation of these two separate questions 'What is Human?' and 'What is reality?', as 'What is human reality?, indicating perhaps that the questions are only problematic if there is an attempt to treat them as mutually exclusive. Freud’s account of psychical reality leaves us in no doubt that, if we operate as if a concrete incontrovertible reality separate from ourselves exists, if we take it as unquestionable, then it is not because it was a given from the start, and the clinic can certainly furnish us with testimony to the contrary. With respect to the possibility that memory could ever furnish us with incontrovertible evidence as to the veracity of past realities Freud does not inspire much hope. Far from it being the case that the apparatus of memory captures events like fresh concrete might receive the imprint of a foot to give us incontestable and permanent reference of the impact of the real, set in stone so to speak, and while it is not exactly the case of a footprint in eternally shifting sand, - Freud's theory of memory does insist on a system which is not static but undergoing successive transformations; see for example his letter to Fliess of 6th December 1986, in which he speaks of 'the material present in the form of memory traces being subjected from time to time to a re arrangement in accordance with fresh circumstances - to a retranscription' and of memory as present not once but several times over and in different registers. Inscriptions of memory which are later chronologically have, as logical consequence, transformational effects on material from an earlier period, in many ways making a nonsense of any notion of chronological sequence. So even if it is the case that impressions of existence are initially 'neutral' (and if we put on hold the problem of the status of such representations in relation to the circumstances causing them) then the registration of the contents of memory, their associative arrangements, will not be at all neutral. These will be intentionalised and therefore unique for every subject, - the whole will always be greater than the sum of its parts, - and it is this which contributes to both the particularity of dream formation and the unfolding of 'free' association. What then can we make of the possibility for Total Recall in all of this? If by 'total' we mean exact, complete and objectively accurate reproduction of past events, then I think we've already said enough to put paid to any hope of it. Maybe we can content ourselves then with the notion of a sort of partial recall, a kind of objective retrieval of contents from the albeit subjective and idiosyncratically organised store of the mnemic system? Well, we don't fare any better down this lane and for a number of reasons. Firstly, if as Freud held it's the case that every recourse to the activity of memory is intentionalised, so too is the very appeal to memory itself. This is linked for Freud to his assertions, on the one hand, that consciousness and memory are mutually exclusive, that is, that consciousness, to remain perpetually open to the reception of new perceptions, retains no trace of them ... [TJhere are obvious difficulties involved in supposing that one and the same system can accurately retain modifications of its elements and yet remain perpetually open to the reception of fresh occasions for modification. ... The mirror of a reflecting telescope cannot at the same time be a photographic plate. ... and, on the other hand, that consciousness is the result of the addition of the faculty of attention to what is preconscious, that is, what is so 177 structured as to be capable of being admitted to consciousness. 'Attention' is then the outcome of investment by the Capitalist mentioned earlier on, the Unconscious, - the repository of interest'. (As an aside, one might here point to the potential this thesis would have in theorising adequately what might be at stake in the recently 'discovered' Attention Deficit Disorder). So not only do psychical contents have to be translated into a version of the text that consciousness can accommodate, but the work of translation is not undertaken disinterestedly, and ends up being a compromise between the desire to be known and the desire to remain unknown, resulting in a translated version not of any original lost text but, rather, of that compromise. Where then does this leave the work of psychoanalysis? Certainly very far from the heady beginnings when, despite being already armed with elements towards a theory of memory which would indicate the problematic nature of such an approach, it laboured under the illusion that the work consisted in simply remembering what had been forgotten, in uncovering an original trauma, for example, by lifting the repression brought to bear on it. Soon 'remembering' would show itself to be as infused by desire as 'forgetting' already proved itself to have been, and the 'lifting of repression1proved to be less like the falling away of a thick veil which leaves unmasked a naked reality, than like the raising of the theatre curtain which allows the succession of acts in the performance of eine andere Schauplatz to be witnessed. Here, the lifting of repression doesn't constitute its abolition but rather signals its preservation, since the Other Scene which is defined by it is delimited by its raising and its lowering, in much the same way as the scenario of Philip K Dick's short story ultimately is played out in that other time between the closing and the opening of Douglas Quail's eyelids. Whatever emerges in that interval pertains to a truth having everything to do with a reality which, for all that, can only be taken as psychical, referring to the truth of the subject itself. This can't be a reality whose truth-value is to be established by reference to the supporting evidence of an external objective reality, that is, independent of the subject's narrative. We must content ourselves with something of the order of Quail's invisible magic rod. One would not, for example, require the exact geographical coordinates of the Garden of Eden, nor await the verificatory evidence of the belly-buttonless forms of a long dead man and woman, to divine the truth-value of the story of Genesis. It's not so very different in the case of the genesis of the subject except, of course, for the fact that here it's more a question of a navel of absence than the absence of a navel. If then the work of psychoanalysis bears some relation to the work of translation, what constitutes a good one? Is it the translation which is most faithful to the original? The Czech author, Milan Kundera, in an article for Le Monde on the subject of the work of translation wrote of the excellence of the English translation of the title of Proust’s a la recherche du temps perdu as Remembrance of Things Past, a phrase borrowed from one of Shakespeare's sonnets. One would find it hard to disagree and yet the translation which remains 'faithful to the original' is in no way an accurate one; it’s not a repetition of it, - more a re-presentation than a representation. Perhaps there is something in Kundera’s example of excellence of translation that could prove useful to us. Does not the experience of the clinic bear witness to the fact that the subject suffers from too much faithfulness to the original One, - so much so that all previous attempts at translation have of necessity failed, the 'failure of translation' constituting, for the Freud of The Interpretation of Dreams, repression itself. A frequent, almost banal, example of this, and one which Freud discusses in the opening chapter of the dream-book, is that of the analysand who doubts the possibility of analysis since he can never articulate in all its detail the content of his dream, can never be sure of giving a faithful, that is, an exact, complete and accurate, account of it. Or the analysand who doubts because only a fragment is available to him. Or the analysand who refuses or resents even the slightest nuance added to the text by the analyst on the grounds that this introduces some impurity into its spontaneous unfolding, addition of the nuance somehow implying an intolerable puncturing of the completeness, the inviolability of the original One. All of these are but variations on the same covert theme; one must remain faithful, give oneself over completely, to the preservation of this original Other as complete unto itself. Besides the obvious ramifications of this for the work of analysis, there is another less obvious one concerning the relation of the one who would be analyst with psychoanalysis itself. The implication here is that taking up the analytic position cannot consist in any faithfulness to the original (Freud, Lacan, or one’s own analyst) which is merely a mantra like repetition of it, but rather involves one in a work of translation which requires that one add one's tuppence-worth. And if one is not prepared to pay then perhaps it's only fitting that one foreclose the door opening onto the landscape of the Other scene, for it's likely to slam in one's face anyway. In point of fact, even if one refuses this entrance onto the space of the unconscious, figured for us by Philip K. Dick as bounded by the opening and closing of the eyelids, one will end up paying nonetheless in terms of the possibilities for one's discourse. The shape of any future discourse will depend on whether one closes the eyes and remains ignorant, or closes one eye and enters into the joke. By way of conclusion then, a snippet concerning the entrance onto that space of a winking T, which Lacan wanted to make difficult, anOther scene from Philip K. Dick: The door refused to open. It said, 'Five cents, please'. He searched his pockets. No more coins; nothing. Til pay you tomorrow' he told the door. Again he tried the knob. Again it remained locked tight. ’What I pay you,’ he informed it, 'is in the nature of a gratuity; I don't have to pay you'. 'I think otherwise', the door said. 'Look in the purchase contract you signed when you bought this conapt.' In his desk drawer he found the contract; since signing it he had found it necessary to refer to the document many times. Sure enough; payment to his door for opening and closing constituted a mandatory fee. Not a tip. 'You discover I'm right', the door said. It sounded smug. 180 From the drawer beside the sink Joe Chip got a stainless steel knife; with it he began systematically to screw the bolt assembly of his apt's money-gulping door. Til sue you', the door said as the first screw fell out. Joe Chip said, 'I've never been sued by a door. But I guess I can live through it1. Address fo r correspondence: THE LETTER Centre for Psychoanalytic Studies LSB college 6-9 Balfe Street Dublin 2 THE TIGHT-ROPE WALKERS Guy Le Gaufey The idea according to which Freud began with psychoanalysis by putting an end to his practice of hypnosis is generally very well accepted today. In spite of some criticism which claims that this is not so obvious, the analytic community (let's suppose for the moment that such a thing exists) holds to this assertion through thick and thin. But it is equally evident that something had been kept alive from hypnosis in the new technique of free association, and a simple look at two of Freud’s texts will be enough to support this: the first one written in the glorious time of hypnosis, the second, ten years later, in Die Traumdeutung. The former one, the little known and not much read Psychische Behandlung, was written in 1890, to be included in a collective book whose title was: Die Gesundheit: Ihre Erhaltung, ihre Storung, ihre Wiederkerstellung (Health: its preservation, its troubles, its return). Because this book was known only in its third edition (dated 1905), this essay is even attributed to 1905 in the Standard Edition, which looks immediately impossible given its contents: an emotive defence in favour of hypnosis, a technique which, according to this Freud, represented 'a progress in the art of healing'. During the 1880's, as a medical practitioner strongly impressed by Charcot and Bemheim (whom he was in the process of translating), he used hypnosis almost daily. In this text, after a long introduction about the importance of words in the relation between body and mind, he gives a brief account of the means through which hypnosis can be achieved. After having given an account of how many and multifarious these can be, he sums them up in a single sentence: But the same result can be brought about by describing the onset of the state of hypnosis and its characteristics quietly and firmly to the subject - that is, by 'talking him into' hypnosis.1 Isn't it bizarre, this 'talking him into'?2 But here Strachey had to translate a sort of Freudian pun: 'wenn man ... ihr die Hypnose also 'einredet". 'Einreden' is rather pejorative a verb in German; it generally means 'to make someone believe in something, or even swallow it - hook, line and sinker'. And through his inverted comas Freud suggests that this common verb has to be translated as Strachey did: ein-reden, to talk into, to talk inside. Irrespective of the order given by the hypnotist ('sleep', or something else), the key to hypnosis is clearly linked for Freud with the success in 'talking the patient into'. What does that mean? That is too big a question for us to answer now, if indeed it is even possible. Let's rather suppose that such a state is established. To what end? Freud is then clear: Hypnosis endows the physician with an authority such as was probably never possessed by the priest or the miracle man, since it concentrates the subject's whole interest upon the figure of the physician; it does away with the autocratic power of the patient's mind which, as we have seen, interferes so capriciously with the influence of the mind over the body.3 This 'autocratic power1is extremely interesting. It appears twice in this text, under two forms: Eigenmächtigkeit, and Selbsherrlichkeit, which are so close to each other that the French translator decided to stick to a single word ('autocratisme'), and Strachey chose respectively 'autocratic power' and 'autocratic nature1. The main benefit of hypnosis would be, according 1 S. Freud. Psychical (or Moral) Treatment. S.E., VH, London, Hogarth Press, 1953. p. 294. 2 More bizarre in the French translation than in English, where the verb 'to talk into' is a precise and good translation. But French language is here compelled to elaborate a long proposition: 'autrement dit en lui insinuant Vhypnose par la parole'. ^ibid, p. 298. to Freud, the putting aside of this autocratic power which every human being is naturally able to bring into action, a power then described as a very strong obstacle on the way to acting upon the body by means of the mind. So, if we could put it offside momentarily, we could work in association with the powers of the mind as a surgeon works in agreement with the functioning of the body under anaesthesia. Later on, when Freud changed his way of 'operating' thanks to his new 'fundamental rule' of free association, his aim, with respect to this Eigenmächtigkeit, remained the same as the one from the time of hypnosis: to put it offside. The first time he apparently conveyed this fundamental rule - that is, to Fraülein Elisabeth -, he told her th a t... ... perhaps she thought that her idea was not the right one; this I told her was not her affair; she was under an obligation to remain completely objective and say what had come into her head, whether it was appropriate or not.4 This clear dismissal of the patient's authority over his stream of thoughts and, in consequence of the fundamental rule, over his stream of words, is the main characteristic of psychoanalytic treatment to this very day. The fact that the fundamental rule follows the line of hypnosis is nowhere more visible than in the last page of the first part of the famous seventh chapter of the Interpretation of Dreams, whose title is 'The Forgetting of Dreams'. With the help of a new terminology, in which the expression 'purposive idea' is crucial, Freud now re-defines his rule as an instruction given to the patient not to bother worrying about having purposive ideas during the session. Which allows him to add immediately that two purposive ideas always remain at stake: When I instruct a patient to abandon reflection of any kind and to tell me whatever comes into his head, I am relying firmly on the assumption that he will not be able to abandon the 4 S. Freud. Studies on Hysteria. S.E., II, p. 154. purposive idea inherent to the treatment ... There is another purposive idea of which the patient has no suspicion - one relating to myself> The second one refers undoubtedly to that 'figure of the physician’ mentioned in a previous quotation, the one to which the patient’s autocratic power has slipped, and who is now in charge of this authority 'never possessed by the priest or the miracle man'. The first one is essential too: the patient is supposed (’I am relying firmly on the assumption') not to abandon the idea that all of this is only a treatment. And this is in agreement with a double statement Freud makes in the same text. He notices that the power of the hypnotist is such that the patient is 'completely tractable' (you could tell him to take a bite out of a potato under the impression that it is a pear), but we must also recognise that 'the best hypnotic suggestion does not exercise unlimited power but only power of a definite strength'.6 With that, we are well armed with enough quotations from Freud to address the problem, or even the paradox correctly: what if such a power is to be abandoned, but not completely? Is it just a hoax? If you 'give up your Right of Governing your self' to someone, you are not supposed to keep a bit of it in such a way that, if you no longer agree with what this one is asking you to do, you could break off the deal and recover the completeness of your right to govern yourself. The phrase in quotation marks comes from Leviathan, when Hobbes expresses the deal supposed to stand at the very roots of the Common-Wealth and citizenship: I Authorise and give up my Right of Governing my self, to this Man, or to this Assembly of men, on this condition, that 5 S. Freud. The Interpretation of Dreams. London, Penguin Books, 1982. p. 699. Italics are mine. 6S. Freud. Psychical Treatment, op.cit., p. 300. 185 you give up thy Right to him, and Authorise all his Actions, in like manner.7 As mythical as such a deal would be, once it is done, it is done. We get a glimpse of this when something like a riot occurs, where a political power in charge is outflanked by forces its police cannot control. The reasoning, in the aftermath, is always the same: the riots were triggered off by 'strangers', or by ’irresponsible elements', which clearly means people who were not, or are no longer citizens, because this power - which I do not suppose here to be either stupid or dumb - is strictly unable to conceive that a citizen could withdraw the authorisation through which this very power exists. As a citizen, you have the right (at least democratically speaking) to fight the people in charge, but you are never allowed to fight this power itself because, in so doing, you would also destroy the citizen in you, you would be turning your violence against yourself, which, in the logic of a Welfare State, is paradoxical. Your right to govern yourself cannot be understood as a right to put the roots of the political power, and therefore the roots of citizenship, into question. At least, it is inconceivable for very good Hobbesian (and republican, and democratic) reasons. There is also another way of looking at this strange abandonment of any Eigenmächtigkeit, a very modern one according to some new standards in sexuality; I mean sado-masochistic rituals, the practice of 'S&M' as it is called today. One is supposed to actually abandon any power of turning down the whims of the other, and to submit oneself entirely to the sadistic caprices of this other, the common aim of both being the attainment of better climaxes. More generally, in his now famous paper Is the Rectum a Grave?,8 Léo Bersani draws our attention to the fact that powerlessness could actually be something decisive in sexual pleasure, insofar as, he suggests, 'There is a big secret about sex: most 7 T. Hobbes. Leviathan. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996.p. 120. 8 Leo Bersani. 'Is the Rectum a Grave?' in Aids Cultural Analysis, Cultural Activist. Ed. Douglas Crimp, an October book, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1987. people don't like it'. They would not like it because they would feel, somehow, that such a powerlessness constitutes part of the price to be paid, whether one is male or female, leading each to a momentary loss of sexual identity, something the macho-style is forced to deny constantly through projecting it onto a construction named 'femininity'. In each of these different cases (hypnosis, analysis, Leviathan, S&M), and in spite of their numerous dissimilarities, the turning point is the same: someone is supposed to have agreed, on joining in such a game, that he/ she9is not able? allowed? to go back on it. We easily relieve our conscience by thinking ourselves capable of stopping the game at any given time, - but this is not so obvious. Of course this possibility remains conceivable from the cold viewpoint of an impartial observer who finds himself standing outside, but the other trapped in the game (the hypnotist, the analyst, the Prince, the sadist) is not necessarily so opened up and ’tractable', and not because of any ill-will, but rather because he is the one in charge of the game, and he takes care of his business. We now have to take into account something usually hidden by the posture of the free observer: in these games, nobody is in the place of a referee, or an empire, able to say: 'enough', or 'break', even in the most hidden reaches of the mind of each one. There is here a fundamental dissymetry, turning around the fact that one is supposed to have abandoned freely ones right of governing oneself If one does not, there is no game; but if one does, the usual paradoxes linked to intentional servitude arise. Without plunging more deeply into this philosophical maelstrom, let's note that our four examples (hypnosis, analysis, Leviathan, S&M) can be described as games in which an initial agreement is required, explicitly or not, but where there is, for all that, no clear picture of a final agreement. Of course, many benefits are expected in each case; some relief of pain, a constitution and a Common-Wealth, new intensities of pleasure ... But they all depend on a certain powerlessness, an abandonment of this bizarre Eigenmächtigkeit, a loss which is set as the price one has to pay to enter the 9 1 so much dislike this politically correct grammatical couple that I will content myself from now on with the trite machismo which uses only the masculine as generic. 187 game. No one will be surprised to discover, later on, that a central concept in each of these cases is the one of 'resistance', even if with Hobbes this resistance is not so easy to locate. But this last example is also the one which permits us to touch upon a crucial point. The Prince is the one whose acts and words represent the acts and words of those who have abandoned to him their right of governing themselves. So that when this Prince says or does anything as a Prince, he speaks and acts as if any of his 'authors' (Hobbes' word) would have spoken or acted in 'like maimer' (except that the Prince has now the power of the ensemble of these authors, each one named, from now on, a 'citizen'). The power of this Prince over each citizen is therefore unlimited because no one can consciously rebel against him without rebelling against himself too. It is as simple as this: a citizen is not a slave, he is free within the frame of that law that the Prince is to concern himself with as every citizen has asked him to do. And there is not the least irony in it: freedom bears no relation to wildlife, in spite of any romantic notions to the contrary. And therefore, freedom is a consequence of a submission to an unlimited power. 'Unlimited' means exactly that no citizen can draw a line in front of the law in such a manner as to protect his freedom. It is rather difficult to think calmly about these matters nowadays because we have our head filled with stories about how one has to protect oneself against some misuse of the law. I am not talking about that; only about the fact that freedom implies that the citizen has not the least right to retract himself from the deal which makes him a citizen, that is: a full respect for the law. The difficulty here comes from a very common topological mistake: this 'unlimited' can be frightening if we hear in this, as a mere synonym, the idea of an infinite power, while something unlimited is not necessarily infinite! A brief look at a simple sphere is enough to put that idea in check: there is no 'limit' of any kind to its surface, nonetheless, this surface can be perfectly finite. A plane, or a line is necessarily infinite if unlimited, but the idea of abandoning a power which, in fact, did not exist as such before its very abandonment, leads us to something much more warped than a plane or a line. Indeed, in a supposed wilderness the fact of 188 governing oneself is obviously not a right, but rather merely a fact (if anything). It becomes a right only when abandoned in favour of a social contract. As citizen then, one is entirely submitted to the law. There is no part of oneself which, by nature, escapes the law. If, nonetheless, there are some parts of one's life this law has decided not to know, this is also a decision of the law, never that of any citizen. That being who, with his neighbour, has contracted to the transformation of both of them into citizens through abandoning their right to this same Prince, - what was he before? A man? A beast? A wolf? That could appear so sophisticated a question that it might appear not to be worthwhile answering it. But, if what is not submitted to the law has to be located in this being from whom (from which?) the citizen has, out of the blue, blossomed, wouldn't it be interesting to make some valuable statements about that? Is that being still at stake behind, beside, or inside the citizen? Is he the one capable of stopping the game when it has gone too far? Unfortunately, no enquiry will give us the least shadow of an answer, for any answer of that kind will concern the primary causes from which a political, a philosophical or metaphysical system springs up, as it does in Hobbes, or in Rousseau. What we could, instead, remind ourselves of is that freely waiving one's right to govern oneself puts in train a sort of irreducible splitting of the one who waives it. Could it not be the case that this splitting is one of the main results of each of those games? To the apparent contrary of this state of powerlessness, something altogether different emerged in the very beginnings of psychiatry, under the French name of 1Traitement moral'. On the same basis as the one Freud supported in his 1890 paper, a French psychiatrist, François Leuret, overemphasised the influence of the mind over the body, going so far as to bluntly deny any somatic aetiology in madness. In his Fragments Psychologiques sur la Folie, published in 1843, he argued that; ... insanity was only the exaggeration of an error in thinking, and that the normal operations of the mind were the most appropriate standard by which to judge the pathological extent of a hallucinatory delusion.10 The treatment he practised and recommended was therefore based upon the idea that the physician has to force the madman to recover a more or less complete power of governing himself. In this perspective, the Freudian Eigenmächtigkeit, far from being abandoned, or dismissed, or put offside, is required as the very spring of the healing. To this end, Leuret used a rather rough technique - cold showers, abrupt reversals from care to disdain etc. - which brought him strong reproaches from most of his colleagues. But his aim was clear: to tame the madman in such a way that he would be himself capable of taming the errors in his own way of thinking, transforming him into a true Eigenmächtigkeit champion. I would claim that, insofar as he is to conceive himself as standing at this old cross-road, the psychoanalyst is still today managing with these two opposites in the treatment he directs. On the one hand, thanks to the fundamental rule, he can hold that the patient has more or less abandoned his power of governing his stream of thoughts. Here, I would just emphasise that this rule is not to be taken as an ideal, and that it is generally out of place to push the patient into implementing it better too frequently. Once it has been said, some slight clarifications can be made very few, indeed and that is all! The possible resistances of the patient will not be further weakened by any reminder of the rule which, in any case, would immediately only set it up to be targetted by them, whereas it is none other than the law distributing the speech between the two actors on the analytical stage. Given then this other Freudian axiom according to which a repressed idea will always turn out to be consciously represented, through the transference, you are just supposed to wait and to watch out. All of a sudden, it will come out, by itself. On the other hand, Freud, faced with hysteria, was forced to note that this rule was not functioning all that well, - not only with obsessional patients, but also with phobic people, in as much as they kept standing 101. Dowbiggin. Inheriting Madness. Oxford, University of California Press, 1991. p. 39. more or less comfortably behind the inhibition to which they were compelled because of their phobia. In New Ways of Psychoanalytical Treatment (1919), he wrote that two kinds of phobic people exist: the former is capable of facing angst, the latter not, at least not alone. He went on: We have some chance to succeed with the latter form only if, through the influence of analysis [durch den Einfluß der Analyse], we bring it to the former one, that is through getting the patient to go out alone and then to fight off angst. What does that mean 'through the influence of analysis' other than that, gently or not, directly or not, you push your patient to cope with what he complains of not being able to? If you are not clever enough, the reply is foreseeable: 'I came to you because I couldn't do that, and now you ask me to just go and do it! Are you kidding?'. But the truth is that, in the case of such inhibition, you could construe absolutely anything, put it anyway you like and still nothing will really move. True, a symptom can be removed by means of interpretation. But a mere inhibition, a reine Hemmung as Freud called it in the first chapter of Inhibition, Symptom and Angst is beyond the reach of any interpretation because it is entirely located in the ego, the Freudian ego. There is so little of the unconscious in inhibition that an interpretation, no matter how enlightened, can only give more consistency to it. The patient will patiently agree with his analyst as long as this one keeps linking his inhibitions to his story. We can tackle this problem on the analyst's side too. Of course, he is not supposed to direct his patient as a spiritual adviser for, if he did, he would himself break the rule he has first proposed to follow. Moreover, if the patient is constantly asking for such guidance, every analyst would recognise how dangerous responding to this kind of demand would be for the treatment. Apparently, things are rather more clear on this side; and nonetheless, how frequent in some cases is this movement which would lead the analyst to admonish his patient! I do not claim here that it must never be done. I am not exactly talking about techniques. But I do want to 191 show how much the analyst is trapped here in a tension between the posture of the hypnotist and the one of the tamer. As usual, there are those who try to escape so essential a tension through crafty tactics. This was the case with the so-called 'therapeutic alliance' by which the analyst was invited to establish a rational link with the ’healthy part' of his patient’s ego. One way or another, we must recognise that every analyst does that. But the question remains: how far can this link be trusted? Not much, if neuroses are even approximately what we think they are! We can't rely for very long on such an 'alliance' without guessing that it places the patient in the position of a gun dog, or better: a pointer. This kind of animal is supposed to be hypnotised in the Freudian way, that is: his master 'talks him into', so that he is perfectly obedient, but moreover, this dog is also supposed to have so perfectly tamed his instincts that, at the right moment, alone and in front of the wild fowl, he will be able to stop and stay put. On the one hand: no inhibition of any kind, no longer any Eigenmächtigkeit to resist his master's voice; on the other, the maximum of inhibition, the capacity to hold back his most powerful drives. Isn't it a miracle of balance, the voice of the master matching decisively the power of nature? A plague on all those stuffy Freudian and post Freudian stories! Don't we now have something newer and better adapted to analytical technique? I mean the Lacanian signifier, the subject that has nothing to do with the old and oh-so narcissistic alter ego, and the object a which is a sort of strict opposite to any honest object? True again, the landscape has really changed. But the fact that the splitting is now mainly on the side of the analyst has just inverted the positions, leaving the forces in not so different a state. Transference is now to be conceived as bringing into play a newcomer, the famous sujet-suppose-savoir. The first day it appeared in Lacan's seminar as the very key to transference, June 3rd 1964, it was totally confused with the analyst himself: 'Le sujet-suppose-savoir, dans Vanalyse, c'est Vanalyste'.n But only three years later, in his extremely 11J. Lacan. Les quatre concepts fondamentaux de la psychanalyse. Paris, Seuil, 1973. p. 204. important paper Proposition du 9 octobre sur le psychanalyste de Vécole, he wrote: We can see that, if analysis consists in the preservation of an agreed situation between two partners, who stand there as the analysand and the analyst, it cannot expand itself but at the price of the ternary constituant introduced in the discourse so instituted, whose name is: subject-supposed-to know, a formation not from artifice but from vein, as detached from the analysand. We have to see what qualifies the analyst to answer this situation which we see as not wrapping his person. [...] What is here paramount to us is the analyst in his relation to the knowing of this supposed subject, [a relation] not secondary but direct.12 Our initial question about hypnosis and moral treatment crops up again, but with new nuances. If (first possibility) the analyst and the s.s.s. are conceived as one and the same person, we just fall again into the square of 'hypnosis' as Lacan defines it, thanks to his own terms, on June 24th 1964. But if, on the contrary, we consider they are two different persons - as is suggested, for instance, in some cases of obsessional neurosis, when you are told that this extremely aggressive thought was not at all directed against 'you', but against the 'analyst' only - we can guess we are not going the right way either. If the analyst, on his part, allows himself to be dragged into believing in the difference between himself and this mere offspring of transference which is this strange s.s.s. (or even believing in the very opposite: a striking similarity), then this analyst will be the one who acts out the main resistance to analysis. Inevitably, along the way, he will some day try to bring the patient to face 'reality', using as an argument this 'reality' he had first put aside thanks to the fundamental rule. This is only one of the usual deadlocks through which an analysis 12 J. Lacan. 'Proposition du 9 octobre 1967 sur le psychanalyste de Vécole', in Scilicet I. Paris, Seuil, 1968. p. 20. 193 caves in, and turns into a psychotherapy in which words are but the means of mastering nature, whether outside or inside. But if you are rather more keen to drive out this kind of subject trapped in a symptom, you would do better to stay at this embarrassing crossing where you do not know, you will not know, if you actually are that devil s.s.s. or not. This analyst's ignorance and fragile balancing act in face of these two slopes - the 'I am1and the 'I am not' (this s.s.s.) - is rather unstable, and can be narcissistically quite uncomfortable on occasions. This point of balance on the analyst's part is certainly close to what Freud called 'neutrality', although in a much more precise sense which does not gather together the many significations he tried to grasp with it. In spite of the fact that this concept looks outdated for some people today,13 I think it has to be re-located as opening and supporting the field of transference such as psychoanalysis welcomes it: not only a way of remembering through acting-out, not only a path strewn with love's deceits, but a very strange balance, on the patient's side this time, between a perfect powerlessness able to give way to hypnosis, and a no less perfect all-powerfulness which stubbornly builds its interlocutor as its own creature. Address for correspondence: 15, Rue d'Ass as 75006 Paris France 13 Including Owen Renik, in his recent paper: 'The Perils of Neutrality', in Psychoanalytic Quaterly, LXV, 1996. pp. 495-517. 194 THE LETTER C e n tre fo r William J. Richardson Lacan for beginners William J. Richardson The subject o f ethics Marcel Czermak Peut-on parler de psychose sociale? Helen Sheehan The follower Claude Dumezil Symptome, ethique et desir d'analyste Rik Loose A review of Freud's early remarks on addiction: from an ideal to masturbation Paul Verhaeghe Trauma and hysteria within Freud and Lacan Tom McGrath Psychology and psychoanalysis - a scientific paradigm Charles Melman Lecture raisonnee et critique des oeuvres de Freud et de Lacan Olga Cox Cameron Lacan and Dali -an anamorphic encounter? Christiane Lacote Une torpeur ordinaire Helena Texier We can remember it fo r you wholesale Guy Le Gaufey The tigh-rope walkers P s y c h o a n a l y t i c S t u d ie s , LSB COLLEGE issn 0791-9875
© Copyright 2024 Paperzz