Mathematical depth and Szemerédi`s theorem

Mathematical depth and Szemerédi’s theorem
Andrew Arana
Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign (until August 2015)
Philosophy, University of Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne, IHPST (after August 2015)
Logic Colloquium 2015, Helsinki, August 7, 2015
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
1 / 26
Introduction
Introduction
Mathematicians frequently cite depth as an important value for their research.
For instance, the Annals of Mathematics since the 1920s has more than a hundred articles
employing the modifier “deep”, referring to deep results, theorems, conjectures, questions,
consequences, methods, insights, connections, and analyses.
However, there is no single, widely-shared understanding of mathematical depth.
Today I will attempt to bring some coherence to mathematicians’ understandings of depth, by
using Szemerédi’s theorem as a case study.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
2 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
Szemerédi’s theorem
A set A of positive integers has positive density if the proportion of elements of A among the
integers from 1 to n approaches a positive number in the limit as n goes to infinity.
Szemerédi’s theorem, infinite form (1975)
Each subset of the natural numbers of positive density contains an arithmetic progression of
arbitrary length.
Szemerédi’s theorem, finite form (1975)
Let k 3 be an integer and let 0 <  1. Then there is a positive integer N = N(k, ) such
that any subset of {1, 2, . . . , N} of at least N elements contains an arithmetic progression of
length k.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
3 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
Szemerédi’s theorem
In 1936 Erdős and Turán had conjectured that every sufficiently “dense” subset of N contains
an arithmetic progression of length three, and more strongly, of arbitrary length.
In 1953, Roth resolved this conjecture for k = 3, and his 1958 Fields Medal citation listed this
result among his significant achievements.
In 1975 Szemerédi resolved the conjecture for arbitrary k.
Erdős, “Some problems and results in number theory” (1984)
I offered $1,000 for [my conjecture] and late in 1972 Szemerédi found a brilliant but very
difficult proof of [my conjecture]. I feel that never was a 1,000 dollars more deserved. In fact
several colleagues remarked that my offer violated the minimum wage act.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
4 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
What Szemerédi’s theorem asserts
Gowers, Abel Prize announcement for Szemerédi, 2012
One way of understanding Szemerédi’s theorem is to imagine the following one-player game.
You are told a small number, such as 5, and a large number, such as 10,000. Your job is to
choose as many integers between 1 and 10,000 as you can, and the one rule that you must
obey is that from the integers you choose it should not be possible to create a five-term
arithmetic progression.
For example, if you were accidentally to choose the numbers 101, 1103, 2105, 3107 and 4109
(amongst others), then you would have lost, because these five numbers form a five-term
progression with step size 1002.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
5 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
What Szemerédi’s theorem asserts
Gowers
Obviously you are destined to lose this game eventually, since. . . if you keep going for long
enough you will eventually have chosen all the numbers between 1 and 10,000, which will
include many five-term arithmetic progressions.
But Szemerédi’s theorem tells us something far more interesting: even if you play with the
best possible progression-avoiding strategy, you will lose long before you get anywhere near
choosing all the numbers.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
6 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
What Szemerédi’s theorem asserts
1
Szemerédi for k = 23, = 1000
: There exists a positive integer N such that every subset of
N
{1, 2, . . . , N} of at least 1000
elements contains an arithmetic progression of length 23.
Gowers
If, for instance, we are trying to avoid progressions of length 23, Szemerédi’s theorem tells us
that there is some N (which may be huge, but the point is that it exists) such that if we play
N
the game with N numbers, then we cannot choose more than 1000
of those numbers–that is, a
mere 0.1% of them–before we lose. And the same is true for any other progression length and
any other positive percentage.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
7 / 26
Szemerédi’s theorem
Proofs of Szemerédi’s theorem
There are three main proofs of Szemerédi’s theorem.
Szemerédi’s combinatorial proof (1975; Abel Prize 2012)
• Furstenberg’s ergodic-theoretic proof (1977; Wolf Prize 2006/7)
• Gowers’ Fourier-analytic proof (1998; Fields Medal 1998)
•
Recently these proofs have been mixed together to yield yet further proofs.
One key aim of reproof, especially from Bourgain 1986 (Fields Medal 1994) onward, has been
to find better bounds on N.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
8 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Szemerédi’s theorem has been judged deep
Tao and Vu, Additive Combinatorics (2006)
Of course, a “typical” additive set will most likely behave like a random additive set, which one
expects to have very little additive structure. Nevertheless, it is a deep and surprising fact that
as long as an additive set is dense enough in its ambient group, it will always have some level
of additive structure. The most famous example of this principle is Szemerédi’s theorem. . . [a]
beautiful and important theorem.
Announcement of the Rolf Schock prize for Szemerédi, 2008
[The prize is awarded] for his deep and pioneering work from 1975 on arithmetic progressions
in subsets of the integers, which has led to great progress and discoveries in several branches
of mathematics.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
9 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Why is it deep?
I have considered four types of criteria of depth, what I call
Genetic criteria
• Evidentialist criteria
• Consequentialist criteria
• Cosmological criteria
•
Today I will concentrate on evidentialist and cosmological criteria of depth.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
10 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Objectivity as a desideratum for an analysis of depth
In the course of assaying a critierion of depth, one issue of interest to many philosophers of
mathematics will recur.
Can judgments of mathematical depth be objective? And if so, in what sense?
In a preliminary investigation of depth like this one, it is not my goal to decide definitively on
the larger questions of whether depth is objective, what objectivity of the relevant sort would
consist in, and whether it is a good/bad thing that depth is/is not objective.
But I ask of each account of depth whether it can deliver a notion of depth that is not vague,
is temporally stable, and is not essentially dependent on our contingent interests or our merely
human limitations.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
11 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
Evidentialist criteria
I call a criterion of depth evidentialist if it links the depth of a theorem with some quality of
its proof.
One evidentialist criterion was identified by Daniel Shanks.
Shanks, Solved and Unsolved Problems in Number Theory (1978)
We confess that although this term “deep theorem” is much used in books on number theory,
we have never seen an exact definition. In a qualitative way we think of a deep theorem as one
whose proof requires a great deal of work�it may be long, or complicated, or difficult, or it
may appear to involve branches of mathematics the relevance of which is not at all apparent.
Shanks thus locates the depth of a theorem in the laboriousness of its proof.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
12 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
Laboriousness of Szemerédi’s proof
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
13 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
Laboriousness and impurity
But there is a problem: Shanks has given four characteristics of proofs: length, complexity,
difficulty, and impurity. But these are different!
A proof can be difficult and not deep: consider the proof of the four color theorem.
A proof can also be pure and deep: consider Szemerédi’s proof!
Which of these characteristics is best suited for an evidentialist criterion of depth?
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
14 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
The problem of multiple proofs
This question is compounded by another problem.
There are multiple proofs of Szemerédi’s theorem, by Szemerédi, Furstenberg, Gowers, and by
others.
Which proof should determine the depth of Szemerédi’s theorem on an evidentialist criterion
of proof?
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
15 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
The problem of multiple proofs: difficulty
Start with difficulty: one could say that a theorem is deep if all its proofs are difficult.
But this is difficult to predict or prove.
One could say instead that a theorem is deep if some of its proofs are difficult.
But a single theorem can have both difficult and easy proofs (e.g. infinitude of primes).
Why should its having a difficult proof take precedence over its having an easy proof as far as
depth is concerned?
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
16 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
The problem of multiple proofs: impurity
Continue with impurity: one could say that a theorem is deep if all its proofs are impure.
But this is also difficult to predict or prove.
One could say instead that a theorem is deep if some of its proofs are impure.
But one can inject logically “inessential” impurities into an otherwise pure proof (for instance,
diagrammatic moves in an otherwise algebraic proof).
Objection: they’re inessential! But how can one determine which impurities are inessential?
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
17 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
The problem of multiple proofs
In fact the problem of multiple proofs is a problem for all evidentialist criteria of depth.
Another evidentialist strategy: a theorem is deep if its
9
every proof of it
>
>
>
almost every proof of it canonical proof >
=
shortest proof
is deep
>
>
simplest proof
>
>
;
least deep proof
These are parasitic on a prior criterion of depth of proof, though.
That demands separate analytic work.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
18 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Evidentialist depth
The criterion of multiple proofs
We can try to transform the problem of multiple proofs into a virtue.
We can say that a theorem is deep if it has many different proofs.
But this demands an account of the individuation of proofs.
The problem is that two apparently different proofs could be in fact the same.
Therefore it is difficult to determine how many different proofs a theorem has.
The problem of individuation of proofs is itself deep.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
19 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Consequentialist depth
Consequentialist criteria
A consequentialist criterion of depth, by contrast, measures the depth of a theorem by some
quality of its consequences or the consequences of its proofs, such as fruitfulness.
Green and Tao (2004) used Szemerédi’s theorem to prove that there are arbitrarily long
arithmetic progressions consisting only of prime numbers (the first item cited in Tao’s Fields
Medal announcement).
But consequentialist criteria are interest-dependent; a theorem is deep only so long as its
consequences are of interest to us.
Consequentialist criteria can be objective only if other values that mathematicians hold, such
as “interestingness”, are objective.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
20 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Cosmological depth
Cosmological criteria
The last type of criterion of depth I want to discuss is what I will call a cosmological criterion.
I’ve chosen this word because of the Greek word kosmos, which means “order”.
Godefroy, Les mathématiques, mode d’emploi (2011)
Szemerédi’s theorem. . . is a deep combinatorial result that establishes (like Ramsey’s
theorems) the inescapable presence of certain structures, lumps of order in a formless dough
[grumeaux d’ordre dans une pâte informe], even though we have a great deal of freedom of
construction since the only constraint imposed on A is positive density.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
21 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Cosmological depth
Cosmological criteria
Szemerédi identifies this feature of his theorem as well.
Interview with Szemerédi after Abel Prize award
In finite objects we look for patterns, different shapes, and try to understand what conditions
make different patterns emerge, this is one of the most fundamental questions. A slightly
pompous and philosophical way to put it is that we want to prove that there is order in any
chaos. in other words, if you give me a hostile structure, I will still be able to find orderly parts
in it.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
22 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Cosmological depth
Order in chaos
Szemerédi’s theorem tells us that for any arithmetic progression of length k and any desired
positive density, there’s an N such that we’re guaranteed to find such an arithmetic
progression choosing only from a subset of {1, 2, . . . , N} of our desired density (so its size can
be very small relative to N).
What Godefroy calls a “formless dough” and what Szemerédi calls “chaos” is the chosen dense
subset of {1, 2, . . . , N}.
We choose these subsets without any other constraints besides positive density.
Szemerédi’s theorem shows that these “randomly” chosen sets must contain arithmetic
progressions of the desired length.
This “unexpected” structure is what makes Szemerédi’s theorem deep, on what I’m calling a
cosmological view of depth.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
23 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Cosmological depth
A precisification of cosmological depth
In a more formal direction, one could think about cosmological depth as follows.
Let us suppose there is a predicate S measuring the orderliness of what is expressed by a
statement.
Then a theorem is cosmologically deep if S(premises) << S(conclusion).
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
24 / 26
The depth of Szemerédi’s theorem
Cosmological depth
A problem for cosmological depth
The cosmological view of depth does not fully capture depth as used in practice.
For instance, Wiles’ result that all elliptic curves arise from modular forms is surely deep.
But the premise (that E is an elliptic curve) is at least as orderly as the conclusion (that E
arises from a modular form).
Thus this result is not deep according to the cosmological criterion.
Note also that the theorem that every modular form has an elliptic curve attached to it�the
Eichler-Shimura theorem�is surely also deep.
We then have two deep theorems with the logical forms, respectively, of “every A is a B” and
“every B is an A”.
But if the << relation is antisymmetric, as seems reasonable, it would follow that only one of
the two theorems can be cosmologically deep.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
25 / 26
Conclusions
Conclusions
I have put forward Szemerédi’s theorem as a case of a deep theorem.
I’ve articulated four different accounts of its depth, and indicated some pros and cons of each.
Arithmetic combinatorics is a rich source of cases for thinking about depth, because its
theorems tend to be simply stated and readily understandable, yet strong.
Furthermore it has been a hotbed of activity in the last couple of decades, with several
articulate mathematicians at its center.
Arana (Illinois/Paris)
Depth
Helsinki LC 2015
26 / 26